Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. La Philosophie de la matiere chez Stahl et ses Disciples.Helene Metzger - 1926 - Isis 8:427-464.
  • La theorie de la composition des sels et la theorie de la combustion d'apres Stahl et ses disciples.Helene Metzger - 1927 - Isis 9:294-325.
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas Samuel Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Otto Neurath.
    A scientific community cannot practice its trade without some set of received beliefs. These beliefs form the foundation of the "educational initiation that prepares and licenses the student for professional practice". The nature of the "rigorous and rigid" preparation helps ensure that the received beliefs are firmly fixed in the student's mind. Scientists take great pains to defend the assumption that scientists know what the world is like...To this end, "normal science" will often suppress novelties which undermine its foundations. Research (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2705 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
  • New Light on Lavoisier: The research of the last ten years.W. A. Smeaton - 1963 - History of Science 2 (1):51-69.
    SINCE the publication in 1952 of Douglas McKie's Antoine Lavoisier, the standard biography which is of great value to all students of eighteenth-century science, there has been a steady increase in knowledge of most aspects of Lavoisier's life and work. This survey will be concerned ,mainly with monographs and papers in scientific and historical journals, but several important books may first be noted.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Composition, a neglected aspect of the chemical revolution.Robert Siegfried & Betty Jo Dobbs - 1968 - Annals of Science 24 (4):275-293.
  • Revolution or Reform: The Chemical Revolution and Eighteenth Century Concepts of Scientific Change.C. E. Perrin - 1987 - History of Science 25 (4):395-423.
  • Of theory shifts and industrial innovations: The relations of J. A. C. Chaptal and A. L. Lavoisier.Carleton E. Perrin - 1986 - Annals of Science 43 (6):511-542.
    Relations between J. A. C. Chaptal, pioneer of heavy chemical industry in France, and A. L. Lavoisier, reformer of chemical theory, are examined in the light of unpublished correspondence they exchanged in the period 1784–1790. The letters, together with Chaptal's early publications, allow a reconstruction of his conversion to Lavoisier's antiphlogistic chemistry. They also reveal a series of petitions that Chaptal made to Lavoisier, in the latter's official capacity as a director of the Régie des poudres et salpêtres, for relief (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Document, Text and Myth: Lavoisier's Crucial Year Revisited.C. E. Perrin - 1989 - British Journal for the History of Science 22 (1):3-25.
    Published texts, unpublished documents and, to a lesser extent, artefacts are the stuff from which historians of science fashion their interpretations of the past. From these residues we attempt to reconstruct the lost fabric of personalities, activities and institutions that constituted the practice of science, and to comprehend the flow of thought that was its substance. Like the sensory data of the empirical sciences, these raw materials are not pure chunks of reality. They must be interpreted in the light of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Lavoisier and the Caloric Theory.Robert J. Morris - 1972 - British Journal for the History of Science 6 (1):1-38.
    Professional historians of science generally recognize the importance of Lavoisier's theory of heat. However, it commonly receives scant attention in the historical treatment of his chemical theories except perhaps as an example illustrating his conservatism and giving the impression that the caloric theory, although perhaps important in the development of ideas on the nature of heat, is independent of and bears little relationship to his general chemistry or is incidental to an understanding of that chemistry. An examination of Lavoisier's writings (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Explanation in the Sciences.Émile Meyerson - 1991 - Springer.
    Emile Meyerson's writings on the philosophy of science are a rich source of ideas and information concerning many philosophical and historical aspects of the development of modem science. Meyerson's works are not widely read or cited today by philosophers or even philosophers of science, in part because they have long been out of print and are often not available even in research libraries. There are additional chevaux de!rise for all but the hardiest scholars: Meyerson's books are written in French (and (...)
  • La Philosophie de la matiere chez Stahl et ses Disciples.Helene Metzger - 1926 - Isis 8 (3):427-464.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • La theorie de la composition des sels et la theorie de la combustion d'apres Stahl et ses disciples.Helene Metzger - 1927 - Isis 9 (2):294-325.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.David Bohm - 1964 - Philosophical Quarterly 14 (57):377-379.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1157 citations  
  • The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusions.Philip Kitcher - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    During the last three decades, reflections on the growth of scientific knowledge have inspired historians, sociologists, and some philosophers to contend that scientific objectivity is a myth. In this book, Kitcher attempts to resurrect the notions of objectivity and progress in science by identifying both the limitations of idealized treatments of growth of knowledge and the overreactions to philosophical idealizations. Recognizing that science is done not by logically omniscient subjects working in isolation, but by people with a variety of personal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   741 citations  
  • The Formation of the German Chemical Community . Karl Hufbauer.M. C. Usselman - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (1):165-166.
  • The "Revolution in Chemistry and Physics": Overthrow of a Reigning Paradigm or Competition between Contemporary Research Programs?Frederic Holmes - 2000 - Isis 91:735-753.
  • The "Revolution in Chemistry and Physics": Overthrow of a Reigning Paradigm or Competition between Contemporary Research Programs?Frederic L. Holmes - 2000 - Isis 91 (4):735-753.
  • The boundaries of Lavoisier's chemical revolution/Les limites de la révolution chimique de Lavoisier.Frédéric L. Holmes - 1995 - Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 48 (1):9-48.
  • Crucial Experiments: Priestley and Lavoisier.S. E. Toulmin - 1957 - Journal of the History of Ideas 18 (2):205.
  • Lavoisier's Theory of Acidity.Maurice Crosland - 1973 - Isis 64:306-325.
  • Lavoisier's Theory of Acidity.Maurice Crosland - 1973 - Isis 64 (3):306-325.
  • The Spreading of the Word: New Directions in the Historiography of Chemistry 1600–1800.J. R. R. Christie & J. V. Golinski - 1982 - History of Science 20 (4):235-266.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • We Have Never Been Whiggish (About Phlogiston)1.Hasok Chang - 2009 - Centaurus 51 (4):239-264.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Persistence of Epistemic Objects Through Scientific Change.Hasok Chang - 2011 - Erkenntnis 75 (3):413-429.
    Why do some epistemic objects persist despite undergoing serious changes, while others go extinct in similar situations? Scientists have often been careless in deciding which epistemic objects to retain and which ones to eliminate; historians and philosophers of science have been on the whole much too unreflective in accepting the scientists’ decisions in this regard. Through a re-examination of the history of oxygen and phlogiston, I will illustrate the benefits to be gained from challenging and disturbing the commonly accepted continuities (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Preservative realism and its discontents: Revisiting caloric.Hasok Chang - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):902-912.
    A popular and plausible response against Laudan's “pessimistic induction” has been what I call “preservative realism,” which argues that there have actually been enough elements of scientific knowledge preserved through major theory‐change processes, and that those elements can be accepted realistically. This paper argues against preservative realism, in particular through a critical review of Psillos's argument concerning the case of the caloric theory of heat. Contrary to his argument, the historical record of the caloric theory reveals that beliefs about the (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • The ‘absolute existence’ of phlogiston: the losing party's point of view.Victor D. Boantza & Ofer Gal - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Science 44 (3):317-342.
    Long after its alleged demise, phlogiston was still presented, discussed and defended by leading chemists. Even some of the leading proponents of the new chemistry admitted its ‘absolute existence’. We demonstrate that what was defended under the title ‘phlogiston’ was no longer a particular hypothesis about combustion and respiration. Rather, it was a set of ontological and epistemological assumptions and the empirical practices associated with them. Lavoisier's gravimetric reduction, in the eyes of the phlogistians, annihilated the autonomy of chemistry together (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kuhn and the Chemical Revolution: a re-assessment. [REVIEW]Geoffrey Blumenthal - 2011 - Foundations of Chemistry 15 (1):93-101.
    A recent paper by Hoyningen-Huene argues that the Chemical Revolution is an excellent example of the success of Kuhn’s theory. This paper gives a succinct account of some counter-arguments and briefly refers to some further existing counter-arguments. While Kuhn’s theory does have a small number of more or less successful elements, it has been widely recognised that in general Kuhn’s theory is a “preformed and relatively inflexible framework” (1962, p. 24) which does not fit particular historical examples well; this paper (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy of Science.Alexander Bird - 2000 - Mind 109 (434):325-327.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Une mythologie révolutionnaire dans la chimie Française.Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent - 1983 - Annals of Science 40 (2):189-196.
    The French chemists of the nineteenth century insisted that the ‘rupture lavoisienne’ had marked the advent of a new world. In their view, Lavoisier not only overthrew the theory of phlogiston, he also established the science of chemistry. In the conceptual gap between notions of ‘revolution’ and ‘foundation’ an origin-myth was created. The cult of Lavoisier that developed can be interpreted as a projection of political interests and national pride. By coincidence, the Traité élémentaire appeared in 1789, Year One in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Chemistry in the French tradition of philosophy of science: Duhem, Meyerson, Metzger and Bachelard.Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (4):627-649.
    At first glance twentieth-century philosophy of science seems virtually to ignore chemistry. However this paper argues that a focus on chemistry helped shape the French philosophical reflections about the aims and foundations of scientific methods. Despite patent philosophical disagreements between Duhem, Meyerson, Metzger and Bachelard it is possible to identify the continuity of a tradition that is rooted in their common interest for chemistry. Two distinctive features of the French tradition originated in the attention to what was going on in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Is Water H2O? Evidence, Realism and Pluralism.Hasok Chang - 2012 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science.
    This book exhibits deep philosophical quandaries and intricacies of the historical development of science lying behind a simple and fundamental item of common sense in modern science, namely the composition of water as H2O. Three main phases of development are critically re-examined, covering the historical period from the 1760s to the 1860s: the Chemical Revolution, early electrochemistry, and early atomic chemistry. In each case, the author concludes that the empirical evidence available at the time was not decisive in settling the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   206 citations  
  • “The” Scientific Revolution 1500-1800: The Formation of the Modern Scientific Attitute.Alfred Rupert Hall - 1962 - London: Longmans.
  • Philosophy of Science.Alexander Bird - 1998 - Mcgill-Queen's University Press.
    Many introductions to this field start with the problem of justifying scientific knowledge but Alexander Bird begins by examining the subject matter, or metaphysics, of science. Using topical scientific debates he vividly elucidates what it is for the world to be governed by laws of nature. This idea provides the basis for explanations and causes and leads to a discussion of natural kinds and theoretical entities. With this foundation in place he goes on to consider the epistemological issues of how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Lavoisier: Memoires d'une Revolution.B. Bensaude-Vincent & M. Crosland - 1995 - Annals of Science 52 (1):86-86.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Memoir on Heat.Antoine Laurent Lavoisier, Pierre Simon Laplace & Henry Guerlac - 1983 - Journal of the History of Biology 16 (3):444-445.
  • The Hidden History of Phlogiston: How Philosophical Failure Can Generate Historiographical Refinement.Hasok Chang - 2010 - Hyle 16 (2):47 - 79.
    Historians often feel that standard philosophical doctrines about the nature and development of science are not adequate for representing the real history of science. However, when philosophers of science fail to make sense of certain historical events, it is also possible that there is something wrong with the standard historical descriptions of those events, precluding any sensible explanation. If so, philosophical failure can be useful as a guide for improving historiography, and this constitutes a significant mode of productive interaction between (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Origins of Modern Science, 1300-1800.H. Butterfield - 1951 - Science and Society 15 (4):348-351.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Thomas Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):654-657.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Historical Studies in the Language of Chemistry.M. P. Crosland - 1965 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 16 (61):65-66.
  • Paradigms and Barriers.Howard Margolis - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:431-440.
    In a forthcoming study I give an account of paradigm shifts as shifts in habits of mind. This paper summarizes the argument. Habits of mind, on this view, are what constitute a paradigm. Further, some particular habit of mind is ordinarily critical for a Kuhnian revolution. A contrast is drawn between this view and the "gap" view that is ordinarily implicit in analysis of the nature of of paradigm shifts.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Science as public culture: Chemistry and the Enlightenment in Britain, 1760–1820 (Cambridge, 1992); Simon Schaffer,“Natural philosophy and public spectacle in the 18th century”. [REVIEW]Jan Golinski - forthcoming - History of Science.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations