Switch to: Citations

References in:

Leibniz on causation

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Leibniz : mind-body causation and pre-established harmony.Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra - 2009 - In Robin Le Poidevin, Simons Peter, McGonigal Andrew & Ross P. Cameron (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics. New York: Routledge. pp. 109-118.
    Causation was an important topic of philosophical reflection during the Seventeenth Century. This reflection centred around certain particular problems about causation, one of which was the problem of causation between mind and body. The doctrine of the pre-established harmony is Leibniz's response to the problem of causation between mind and body. In this chapter I shall (a) explain the problem of mind-body causation; (b) explain Leibniz's pre-established harmony; and (c) assess his case for it.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A critical exposition of the philosophy of Leibniz.Bertrand Russell - 1937 - Wolfeboro, N.H.: Longwood Press.
    By what process of development he came to this opinion, though in itself an important and interesting question, is logically irrelevant to the inquiry how far the opinion itself is correct ; and among his opinions, when these have been ascertained, it becomes desirable to prune away such as seem inconsistent with his main doctrines, before those doctrines themselves are subjected to a critical scrutiny. Philosophic truth and falsehood, in short, rather than historical fact, are what primarily demand our attention (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Leibniz: a collection of critical essays.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1976 - Notre Dame [Ind.]: University of Notre Dame Press.
    Broad, C. D. Leibniz's predicate-in-notion principle and some of its alleged consequences.--Couturat, L. On Leibniz's metaphysics.--Friedrich, C. J. Philosophical reflections of Leibniz on law, politics, and the state.--Curley, E. M. The root of contingency. Furth, M. Monadology.--Hacking, I. Individual substance.--Hintikka, J. Leibniz on plenitude, relations, and the "reign of law."--Ishiguro, H. Leibniz's theory of the ideality of relations.--Kneale, M. Leibniz and Spinoza on activity.--Koyré, A. Leibniz and Newton.--Lovejoy, A. O. Plenitude and sufficient reason in Leibniz and Spinoza.--Mates, B. Leibniz on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Leibniz: an introduction.C. D. Broad - 1975 - London: Cambridge University Press.
    This book, first published in 1975, provides critical and comprehensive introduction to the philosophy of Leibniz.
  • Leibniz on Causation and Agency.Julia Jorati - 2017 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book presents a comprehensive examination of Gottfried Leibniz's views on the nature of agents and their actions. Julia Jorati offers a fresh look at controversial topics including Leibniz's doctrines of teleology, the causation of spontaneous changes within substances, divine concurrence, freedom, and contingency, and also discusses widely neglected issues such as his theories of moral responsibility, control, attributability, and compulsion. Rather than focusing exclusively on human agency, she explores the activities of non-rational substances and the differences between distinctive types (...)
  • The Structure of Leibnizian Simple Substances.John Whipple - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (3):379-410.
  • Leibniz on Concurrence, Spontaneity, and Authorship.Julia von Bodelschwingh - 2011 - Modern Schoolman 88 (3/4):267-297.
    Leibniz holds that creatures require divine concurrence for all their actions, and that this concurrence is 'special,' that is, directed at the particular qualities of each action. This gives rise to two potential problems. The first is the problem of explaining why special concurrence does not make God a co-author of creaturely actions. Second, divine concurrence may seem incompatible with the central Leibnizian doctrine that substances must act spontaneously, or independently of other substances. Concurrence, in other words, may appear to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Leibniz: an introduction to his philosophy.Nicholas Rescher - 1979 - Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
  • From Immanent Natures to Nature as Artifice.Margaret J. Osler - 1996 - The Monist 79 (3):388-407.
    A commonplace in traditional historiography is the claim that an important aspect of the demise of Aristotelianism during the Scientific Revolution was a change in the concept of causality, a change which eliminated final causes from science. Projecting twentieth-century metaphysical presuppositions onto the ostensibly revolutionary thought of early modern natural philosophers, E. A. Burtt declared.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Leibniz: Creation and Conservation and Concurrence.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2007 - The Leibniz Review 17:31-60.
    In this paper I argue that the hoary theological doctrine of divine concurrence poses no deep threat to Leibniz’s views on theodicy and creaturely activity even as those views have been traditionally understood. The first three sections examine respectively Leibniz’s views on creation, conservation and concurrence, with an eye towards showing their sys­tematic compatibility with Leibniz’s theodicy and metaphysics. The fourth section takes up remaining worries arising from the bridging principle that conservation is a continued or continuous creation, and argues (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Monadic Teleology without Goodness and without God.Julia Jorati - 2013 - The Leibniz Review 23:43-72.
    Most interpreters think that for Leibniz, teleology is goodness-directedness. Explaining a monadic action teleologically, according to them, simply means explaining it in terms of the goodness of the state at which the agent aims. On some interpretations, the goodness at issue is always apparent goodness: an action is end-directed iff it aims at what appears good to the agent. On other interpretations, the goodness at issue is only sometimes apparent goodness and at other times merely objective goodness: some actions do (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Causality and Creation in Leibnitz.Nicholas Jolley - 1998 - The Monist 81 (4):591-611.
    Leibniz is famously committed to the following three metaphysical claims concerning causality.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • IX*—The Kingdom of Wisdom and the Kingdom of Power in Leibniz.David Hirschmann - 1988 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 88 (1):147-160.
    David Hirschmann; IX*—The Kingdom of Wisdom and the Kingdom of Power in Leibniz, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 88, Issue 1, 1 June 1988, Pages.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On Leibniz on subject and substance.Noel Fleming - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (1):69-95.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1994 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Adams presents an in-depth interpretation of three important parts of Leibniz's metaphysics, thoroughly grounded in the texts as well as in philosophical analysis and critique. The three areas discussed are the metaphysical part of Leibniz's philosophy of logic, his essentially theological treatment of the central issues of ontology, and his theory of substance. Adams' work helps make sense of one of the great classic systems of modern philosophy.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Person and Object.Roderick Chisholm - 1976 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39 (2):281-283.
  • Leibniz on final causes.Laurence Carlin - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (2):217-233.
    : In this paper, I investigate Leibniz's conception of final causation. I focus especially on the role that Leibnizian final causes play in intentional action, and I argue that for Leibniz, final causes are a species of efficient causation. It is the intentional nature of final causation that distinguishes it from mechanical efficient causation. I conclude by highlighting some of the implications of Leibniz's conception of final causation for his views on human freedom, and on the unconscious activity of substances.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Leibniz.Stuart C. Brown - 1984 - Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press.
  • Leibniz on Concurrence and Efficient Causation.Marc E. Bobro - 2008 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 46 (3):317-338.
    Leibniz defends concurrentism, the view that both God and created substances are causally responsible for changes in the states of created substances. Interpretive problems, however, arise in determining just what causal role each plays. Some recent work has been revisionist, greatly downplaying the causal role played by created substances—arguing instead that according to Leibniz only God has productive causal power. Though bearing some causal responsibility for changes in their perceptual states, created substances are not efficient causes of such changes. This (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Early German Philosophy: Kant and His Predecessors.Lewis White Beck - 1969 - Cambridge, Mass.,: St. Augustine's Press.
    This comprehensive history of German philosophy from its medieval beginnings to near the end of the eighteenth century explores the spirit of German intellectual life and its distinctiveness from that of other countries. Beck devotes whole chapters to four great philosophers -- Nicholas of Cusa, Leibniz, Lessing, and Kant -- and extensively examines many others, including Albertus Magnus, Meister Eckhart, Paracelsus, Kepler, Mendelssohn, Wolff, and Herder. Questioning explanations of philosophy by the racial or ethnic character of its exponents, Beck's conclusion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Historical and Critical Dictionary: Selections.Pierre Bayle & Craig Brush - 1991 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    Richard Popkin’s meticulous translation--the most complete since the eighteenth century--contains selections from thirty-nine articles, as well as from Bayle’s four Clarifications. The bulk of the major articles of philosophical and theological interest--those that influenced Leibniz, Berkeley, Hume, and Voltaire and formed the basis for so many eighteenth-century discussions--are present, including David, Manicheans, Paulicians, Pyrrho, Rorarius, Simonides, Spinoza, and Zeno of Elea.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Pre-established Harmony Versus Constant Conjunction: A Reconsideration of the Distinction Between Rationalism and Empiricism.Hidé Ishiguro - 1978 - University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Leibniz.Catherine Wilson - 2001 - Dartmouth Publishing Company.
    A collection of essays covering a range of topics related to Leibniz. The monads and the pre-established harmony make numerous appearances, and so do Leibniz's discussions of causality, relations, individuation, nature, freedom, consciousness, and divinity. In addition to sections on Leibniz's physics and his theory of substance, a number of papers are included on his philosophy of mind that draw heavily on the New Essays, along with several articles on metaphysical and theological issues, and a section on Leibniz's relationships with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The fold: Leibniz and the Baroque.Gilles Deleuze - 2006 - New York: Continuum.
    In The Fold Deleuze proposes a new and radical way of understanding philosophy and art.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz: the concept of substance in seventeenth-century metaphysics.Roger Woolhouse - 1993 - New York: Routledge.
    This book introduces student to the three major figures of modern philosophy known as the rationalists. It is not for complete beginners, but it is an accessible account of their thought. By concerning itself with metaphysics, and in particular substance, the book relates an important historical debate largely neglected by the contemporary debates in the once again popular area of traditional metaphysics. in philosophy. (Do Not USE).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • From Descartes to Hume: Continental Metaphysics and the Development of Modern Philosophy.Louis Loeb - 1981 - Cornell University Press, C1981.
  • Leibniz & Arnauld: A Commentary on Their Correspondence.R. C. Sleigh - 1990 - Yale University Press.
  • The causation debate in modern philosophy, 1637-1739.Kenneth C. Clatterbaugh - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    The Causation Debate in Modern Philosophy examines the debate that began as modern science separated itself from natural philosophy in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The book specifically explores the two dominant approaches to causation as a metaphysical problem and as a scientific problem. As philosophy and science turned from the ideas of Aristotle that dominated western thought throughout the renaissance, one of the most pressing intellectual problems was how to replace Aristotelian science with its doctine of the four causes. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Efficient Causation: A History.Tad M. Schmaltz (ed.) - 2014 - , US: Oup Usa.
    This volume is a collection of new essays by specialists that trace the concept of efficient causation from its discovery in Ancient Greece, through its development in late antiquity, the medieval period, and modern philosophy, to its use in contemporary metaphysics and philosophy of science.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony.Steven M. Nadler (ed.) - 1992 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    Three general accounts of causation stand out in early modern philosophy: Cartesian interactionism, occasionalism, and Leibniz's preestablished harmony. The contributors to this volume examine these theories in their philosophical and historical context. They address them both as a means for answering specific questions regarding causal relations and in their relation to one another, in particular, comparing occasionalism and the preestablished harmony as responses to Descartes's metaphysics and physics and the Cartesian account of causation. Philosophers discussed include Descartes, Gassendi, Malebranche, Arnauld, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Central Themes in Early Modem Philosophy. Kulstad & Cover (eds.) - 1990 - Hackett.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Leibniz, God and Necessity.Michael V. Griffin - 2012 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Leibniz states that 'metaphysics is natural theology', and this is especially true of his metaphysics of modality. In this book, Michael V. Griffin examines the deep connection between the two and the philosophical consequences which follow from it. Grounding many of Leibniz's modal conceptions in his theology, Griffin develops a new interpretation of the ontological argument in Leibniz and Descartes. This interpretation demonstrates that their understanding God's necessary existence cannot be construed in contemporary modal logical terms. He goes on to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Leibniz and the Rational Order of Nature.Donald Rutherford - 1995 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    This is the most up-to-date and comprehensive interpretation of the philosophy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Amongst its other virtues, it makes considerable use of unpublished manuscript sources. The book seeks to demonstrate the systematic unity of Leibniz's thought, in which theodicy, ethics, metaphysics and natural philosophy cohere. The key, underlying idea of the system is the conception of nature as an order designed by God to maximise the opportunities for the exercise of reason. From this idea emerges the view that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Leibniz on apperception, consciousness, and reflection.Mark Kulstad - 1991 - München: Philosophia.
    This work represents an investigation of the most important properties of the human mind consciousness, apperception and reflection - and of their significance for Leibnizian philosophy. The development of Leibniz's thinking in the course of his treatment of these themes receives especially detailed treatment, and is thoroughly documented on the basis of the original texts. The concepts of consciousness and reflection were the object of intensive discussion in the l7th century. Starting out from the problem of the distinction between humans (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Leibniz on Divine Concurrence.Sukjae Lee - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (2):203-248.
    Leibniz was a divine concurrentist. That is to say, when it came to the question of how God’s causal power relates to the natural causal activity of creatures, Leibniz held that both God and the creature are directly involved in the occurrence of these effects.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Development of Physical Influx In Early Eighteenth-Century Germany.Eric Watkins - 1995 - Review of Metaphysics 49 (2):295-339.
    Before the story can be told, however, some stage-setting is necessary. First, it is important to be clear about the most basic doctrines of Pre-established Harmony, Occasionalism, and Physical Influx. Physical Influx asserts intersubstantial causation amongst finite substances. For instance, when I appear to kick a ball, I really am the cause of the ball's motion. Pre-established Harmony denies intersubstantial causation, but affirms intrasubstantial causation. According to Pre-established Harmony, then, I am not the cause of the ball's motion, but rather (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Continuous creation.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2011 - In Peter A. French (ed.), Early Modern Philosophy Reconsidered. Wiley-Blackwell.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Efficient Causation in Spinoza and Leibniz.Martin Lin - 2014 - In Tad Scmaltz (ed.), Efficient Causation: A History. pp. 165-191.
  • Leibniz on Divine Causation: Creation, Miracles, and the Continual Fulgurations.Donovan Cox - 2002 - Studia Leibnitiana 34 (2):185 - 207.
    This paper will be a limited attempt to make sense of divine causation in Leibniz. I will not be able to discuss whether divine causation is immanent causation, nor explore the metaphysics of creation, emanation, and miracles in detail. Rather, I will focus on adjudicating the degree to which Leibniz’s famous denial of the interaction of substances bears on his views of divine causation. (edited).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz.Nicholas Jolley - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (192):417-419.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Leibniz: Metaphysics and Language.Benson Mates - 1986 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 22 (1):103-105.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Leibniz and Strawson: A New Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics.Clifford Brown - 1990
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Leibniz: How Does Sword Steel Get to be so Smart?Mark Wilson - unknown
    In substantial ways, the strangest aspects of Leibniz's wild metaphysical architecture (monads and all that) lie grounded in his efforts to understand the "unreasonable effectiveness" of the mathematics utilized in the classical modeling of ordinary materials (of which we will adopt sword steel as a chief paradigm, for reasons to be explained later). In doing so, Leibniz proceeds in a more acutely reasoned fashion than does Eugene Wigner in the famously fuzzy article from which the phrase "unreasonable effectiveness" descends. There (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leibniz: Perception, Apperception and Thought.Robert Mcrae - 1978 - Mind 87 (345):133-135.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Leibniz. Critical and Interpretative Essays.M. Hooker - 1985 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 47 (1):150-150.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Leibniz.H. Wildon Carr - 1929 - Humana Mente 4 (14):266-268.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pre-established harmony retuned: Ishiguro versus the tradition.Roger S. Woolhouse - 1985 - Studia Leibnitiana 17 (2):204-219.
    Unter Berücksichtigung von Ishiguros Gegenargumenten untersucht dieser Aufsatz erneut die traditionelle Interpretation von Leibniz' These, daß es keine kausale Wechselwirkung zwischen den Substanzen gebe und daß die kausalen Erklärungen für die Eigenschaften einer Substanz völlig in ihrer Natur lägen. Ishiguros Argumente benutzen die Unterscheidung zwischen dem Begriff einer Substanz und ihrer Natur, und in der Tat kann die Philosophie von Leibniz ohne diese Unterscheidung nicht voll gewürdigt werden. Aber sie lassen nicht erkennen, daß für Leibniz keine eindeutige Entsprechung zwischen ihnen (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations