Switch to: Citations

References in:

Berkeley and Proof in Geometry

Dialogue 51 (3):419-435 (2012)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence. [REVIEW]A. Reix - 1982 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 172 (1):64-64.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • Don't take me half the way: On Berkeley on mathematical reasoning.David Sherry - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 24 (2):207-225.
  • Three Kinds of Idealization.Michael Weisberg - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy 104 (12):639-659.
    Philosophers of science increasingly recognize the importance of idealization: the intentional introduction of distortion into scientific theories. Yet this recognition has not yielded consensus about the nature of idealization. e literature of the past thirty years contains disparate characterizations and justifications, but little evidence of convergence towards a common position.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   279 citations  
  • What is it the Unbodied Spirit cannot do? Berkeley and Barrow on the Nature of Geometrical Construction.Stefan Storrie - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (2):249-268.
    In ?155 of his New Theory of Vision Berkeley explains that a hypothetical ?unbodied spirit? ?cannot comprehend the manner wherein geometers describe a right line or circle?.1The reason for this, Berkeley continues, is that ?the rule and compass with their use being things of which it is impossible he should have any notion.? This reference to geometrical tools has led virtually all commentators to conclude that at least one reason why the unbodied spirit cannot have knowledge of plane geometry is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Minima Sensibilia”in Berkeley and Hume.David Raynor - 1980 - Dialogue 19 (2):196-200.
    Philosophers no longer argue whether Hume ever read Berkeley, yet some remain puzzled as to why so little of Berkeley appears in Hume's works. Professor Popkin has remarked that even “where Hume and Berkeley come closest to discussing the same subject or holding the same view, Hume neither uses Berkeley's terms nor refers to him.” An apparent exception to this generalization is Berkeley's doctrine ofminima sensibilia, for both philosophers use this term to denote indivisible sensible points, and both invoke such (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mathematics and Philosophy: Wallis, Hobbes, Barrow, and Berkeley.Helena M. Pycior - 1987 - Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (2):265.
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure of Euclid 's "Elements".Michael Boylan - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (4):665-668.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Galilean Idealization.Ernan McMullin - 1985 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 16 (3):247.
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
  • Hume and Berkeley on the proofs of infinite divisibility.Robert Fogelin - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (1):47-69.
    Since both berkeley and hume are committed to the view that a line is composed of finitely many fundamental parts, They must find responses to the standard geometrical proofs of infinite divisibility. They both repeat traditional arguments intended to show that infinite divisibility leads to absurdities, E.G., That all lines would be infinite in length, That all lines would have the same length, Etc. In each case, Their arguments rest upon a misunderstanding of the concept of a limit, And thus (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Berkeley.Roderick Firth - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (1):149.
  • Siris and the scope of Berkeley's instrumentalism.Lisa J. Downing - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (2):279 – 300.
    I. Introduction Siris, Berkeley's last major work, is undeniably a rather odd book. It could hardly be otherwise, given Berkeley's aims in writing it, which are three-fold: 'to communicate to the public the salutary virtues of tar-water,'1 to provide scientific background supporting the efficacy of tar-water as a medicine, and to lead the mind of the reader, via gradual steps, toward contemplation of God.2 The latter two aims shape Berkeley's extensive use of contemporary natural science in Siris. In particular, Berkeley's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Formalism.Michael Detlefsen - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford University Press. pp. 236--317.
    A comprehensive historical overview of formalist ideas in the philosophy of mathematics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • On the Compatibility between Euclidean Geometry and Hume's Denial of Infinite Divisibility.Emil Badici - 2008 - Hume Studies 34 (2):231-244.
    It has been argued that Hume's denial of infinite divisibility entails the falsity of most of the familiar theorems of Euclidean geometry, including the Pythagorean theorem and the bisection theorem. I argue that Hume's thesis that there are indivisibles is not incompatible with the Pythagorean theorem and other central theorems of Euclidean geometry, but only with those theorems that deal with matters of minuteness. The key to understanding Hume's view of geometry is the distinction he draws between a precise and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Berkeley's Triangle.Zoltan Szabo - 1995 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 12:41-63.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Some Points in Bayle, Berkeley, and Hume.Harry M. Bracken - 1987 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 4 (4):435 - 446.
  • Philosophical Works.George Berkeley - 1977 - Critica 9 (26):121-123.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations