Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Concept of Law.Hla Hart - 1961 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK.
    The Concept of Law is one of the most influential texts in English-language jurisprudence. 50 years after its first publication its relevance has not diminished and in this third edition, Leslie Green adds an introduction that places the book in a contemporary context, highlighting key questions about Hart's arguments and outlining the main debates it has prompted in the field. The complete text of the second edition is replicated here, including Hart's Postscript, with fully updated notes to include modern references (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   364 citations  
  • The concept of law.Hla Hart - 1961 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The Concept of Law is the most important and original work of legal philosophy written this century. First published in 1961, it is considered the masterpiece of H.L.A. Hart's enormous contribution to the study of jurisprudence and legal philosophy. Its elegant language and balanced arguments have sparked wide debate and unprecedented growth in the quantity and quality of scholarship in this area--much of it devoted to attacking or defending Hart's theories. Principal among Hart's critics is renowned lawyer and political philosopher (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   695 citations  
  • The Enduring Dilemmas of Autonomous Technique.Langdon Winner - 1995 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 15 (2-3):67-72.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Interpreting the notion that technology is value-neutral.Per Sundström - 1998 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1 (1):41-45.
    Value-freedom or value-neutrality is a well-known topic in the philosophy of science. But what about the value-neutrality of technology, medical or other? Is it too far-fetched to imagine technology as in some sense value-neutral — in view of its intimate connection with purposeful human action? No; unexpected perhaps, but less far-fetched than expected. If we try to conceive of technology as a cognitive possibility abstracted from each and every specific social context, we shall find three senses in which it may (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Interpreting the notion that technology is value-neutral.Per Sundström - 1998 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1 (1):41-45.
    Value-freedom or value-neutrality is a well-known topic in the philosophy of science. But what about the value-neutrality of technology, medical or other? Is it too far-fetched to imagine technology as in some sense value-neutral — in view of its intimate connection with purposeful human action? No; unexpected perhaps, but less far-fetched than expected. If we try to conceive of technology as a cognitive possibility abstracted from each and every specific social context, we shall find (at least) three senses in which (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Out of control.George Sher - 2006 - Ethics 116 (2):285-301.
  • Accountability in a computerized society.Helen Nissenbaum - 1996 - Science and Engineering Ethics 2 (1):25-42.
    This essay warns of eroding accountability in computerized societies. It argues that assumptions about computing and features of situations in which computers are produced create barriers to accountability. Drawing on philosophical analyses of moral blame and responsibility, four barriers are identified: 1) the problem of many hands, 2) the problem of bugs, 3) blaming the computer, and 4) software ownership without liability. The paper concludes with ideas on how to reverse this trend.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Distributing responsibilities.David Miller - 2001 - Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (4):453–471.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  • Causation By Omission: A Dilemma.Sarah McGrath - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 123 (1-2):125-148.
    Some omissions seem to be causes. For example, suppose Barry promises to water Alice’s plant, doesn’t water it, and that the plant then dries up and dies. Barry’s not watering the plant – his omitting to water the plant – caused its death. But there is reason to believe that if omissions are ever causes, then there is far more causation by omission than we ordinarily think. In other words, there is reason to think the following thesis true.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Philosophical Remarks on Professional Responsibility in Organization.John Ladd - 1982 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 1 (2):58-70.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Computers in control: Rational transfer of authority or irresponsible abdication of autonomy? [REVIEW]Arthur Kuflik - 1999 - Ethics and Information Technology 1 (3):173-184.
    To what extent should humans transfer, or abdicate, responsibility to computers? In this paper, I distinguish six different senses of responsible and then consider in which of these senses computers can, and in which they cannot, be said to be responsible for deciding various outcomes. I sort out and explore two different kinds of complaint against putting computers in greater control of our lives: (i) as finite and fallible human beings, there is a limit to how far we can acheive (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Engineering Practice and Engineering Ethics.Ronald Kline & William T. Lynch - 2000 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 25 (2):195-225.
    Diane Vaughan’s analysis of the causes of the Challenger accident suggests ways to apply science and technology studies to the teaching of engineering ethics. By sensitizing future engineers to the ongoing construction of risk during mundane engineering practice, we can better prepare them to address issues of public health, safety, and welfare before they require heroic intervention. Understanding the importance of precedents, incremental change, and fallible engineering judgment in engineering design may help them anticipate potential threats to public safety arising (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Responsibility without Moralism in Technoscientific Design Practice.Jaap Jelsma & Tsjalling Swierstra - 2006 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 31 (3):309-332.
    While engineering ethics usually addresses the responsibility of engineers in rare cases of whistle blowing, the authors broach the question to what extent engineers can be held responsible in normal practice. For this purpose, they define the conditions under which individuals can be imputable as they prevail in ethics and common sense. From outcomes of science and technology studies research, the authors conclude that these conditions are seldom met in modern technoscientific research practice. By examining such practice in a case (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Causation in the Law.F. S. McNeilly - 1959 - Philosophy 37 (139):83-84.
    An updated and extended second edition supporting the findings of its well-known predecessor which claimed that courts employ common-sense notions of causation in determining legal responsibility.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • It Makes no Difference Whether or Not I Do It.Jonathan Glover & M. Scott-Taggart - 1975 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 49 (1):171 - 209.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • It Makes No Difference Whether or Not I Do It.Jonathan Glover & M. Scott-Taggart - 1975 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 49 (1):171-210.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility. [REVIEW]B. J. Diggs - 1974 - Journal of Philosophy 71 (3):90-96.
  • Better communication between engineers and managers: Some ways to prevent many ethically hard choices.Michael Davis - 1997 - Science and Engineering Ethics 3 (2):171-212.
    This article is concerned with ways better communication between engineers and their managers might help prevent engineers being faced with some of the ethical problems that make up the typical course in engineering ethics. Beginning with observations concerning the Challenger disaster, the article moves on to report results of empirical research on the way technical communication breaks down, or doesn’t break down, between engineers and managers. The article concludes with nine recommendations for organizational change to help prevent communications breakdown.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Responsibility in Law and Morality.J. Angelo Corlett - 2003 - Mind 112 (446):328-331.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Is Idiot Proof Safe Enough?Louis L. Bucciarelli - 1985 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 2 (4):49-57.
  • The four faces of omission: Ontology, terminology, epistemology, and ethics.Giovanni Boniolo & Gabriele De Anna - 2006 - Philosophical Explorations 9 (3):277 – 293.
    In this paper, the ontological, terminological, epistemological, and ethical aspects of omission are considered in a coherent and balanced framework, based on the idea that there are omissions which are actions and omissions which are non-actions. In particular, we suggest that the approach to causation which best deals with omission is Mackie's INUS conditional proposal. We argue that omissions are determined partly by the ontological conditional structure of reality, and partly by the interests, beliefs, and values of observers. The final (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Problem of Clean Hands.Michael D. Bayles - 1979 - Social Theory and Practice 5 (2):165-181.
  • Regularity theories reassessed.Michael Baumgartner - 2006 - Philosophia 36 (3):327-354.
    For a long time, regularity accounts of causation have virtually vanished from the scene. Problems encountered within other theoretical frameworks have recently induced authors working on causation, laws of nature, or methodologies of causal reasoning – as e.g. May (Kausales Schliessen. Eine Untersuchung über kausale Erklärungen und Theorienbildung. Ph.D. thesis, Universität Hamburg, Hamburg, 1999), Ragin (Fuzzy-set social science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000), Graßhoff and May (Causal regularities. In W. Spohn, M. Ledwig, & M. Esfeld (Eds.), Current issues in (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Moral Responsibility for Engineers.Kenneth D. Alpern - 1983 - Business and Professional Ethics Journal 2 (2):39-48.
  • Thinking like an engineer: studies in the ethics of a profession.Michael Davis - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Michael Davis, a leading figure in the study of professional ethics, offers here both a compelling exploration of engineering ethics and a philosophical analysis of engineering as a profession. After putting engineering in historical perspective, Davis turns to the Challenger space shuttle disaster to consider the complex relationship between engineering ideals and contemporary engineering practice. Here, Davis examines how social organization and technical requirements define how engineers should (and presumably do) think. Later chapters test his analysis of engineering judgement and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Causality and Probability in the Sciences.Federica Russo & Jon Williamson (eds.) - 2007 - College Publications.
    Causal inference is perhaps the most important form of reasoning in the sciences. A panoply of disciplines, ranging from epidemiology to biology, from econometrics to physics, make use of probability and statistics to infer causal relationships. The social and health sciences analyse population-level data using statistical methods to infer average causal relations. In diagnosis of disease, probabilistic statements are based on population-level causal knowledge combined with knowledge of a particular person’s symptoms. For the physical sciences, the Salmon-Dowe account develops an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Readings in the Philosophy of Law.John Arthur & William H. Shaw (eds.) - 1993 - Pearson Prentice Hall.
    The adversary system and the practice of law -- The rule of law -- The moral force of law -- Statutes -- Precedents -- Constitutional interpretation -- Natural law and legal positivism: classical perspectives -- Formalism and legal realism -- Morality and the law -- International law -- Law and economics -- The justification of punishment -- The rights of defendants -- Sentencing -- Criminal responsibility -- Compensating for private harms: the law of torts -- Private ownership: the law of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ethics in an age of pervasive technology.Melvin Kranzberg (ed.) - 1980 - Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
  • Responsibility.Christopher Kutz - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Punishment and Responsibility.H. L. A. Hart - 1968 - Philosophy 45 (172):162-162.
  • Causes are physically connected to their effects: Why preventers and omissions are not causes.Phil Dowe - 2004 - In Christopher Hitchcock (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science. Blackwell. pp. 189--196.
  • Responsibility.Christopher Kutz - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is technology ethically neutral.H. Schnädelbach - 1980 - In Melvin Kranzberg (ed.), Ethics in an Age of Pervasive Technology. Westview Press. pp. 30.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation