Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):5-20.
    It is my view that one essential difference between persons and other creatures is to be found in the structure of a person's will. Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, men may also want to have certain desires and motives. They are capable of wanting to be different, in their preferences and purposes, from what they are. Many animals appear to have the capacity for what I shall call "first-order desires" or "desires of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1459 citations  
  • Two distinctions in goodness.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (2):169-195.
  • The conceptual foundations of the land ethic.J. Baird Callicott - 2009 - In Craig Hanks (ed.), Technology and values: essential readings. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Background.[author unknown] - 2004 - The Chesterton Review 30 (3-4):411-413.
    I was born in Philadelphia, in 1928. I stayed there until I went through undergraduate school at the University of Pennsylvania, then went on to Harvard for a couple of a years in a research fellowship, and graduate school. When I was done with that, went over to MIT, and I've been in Boston ever since, around Boston since about..
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • 7. What Happens When Someone Acts?J. Velleman - 1992 - In John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza (eds.), Perspectives on Moral Responsibility. Cornell University Press. pp. 188-210.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Agent-Based Virtue Ethics.Michael Slote - 1995 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 20 (1):83-101.
  • Aristotle on Eudaimonia.J. L. Ackrill - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 15-34.
    Originally published in Proceedings of the British Academy 60 (1974), 339-359.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Desire and the good in De Anima.Henry Richardson - 1995 [1992] - In Martha Craven Nussbaum & Amélie Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De anima. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Mechanism and responsibility.Daniel C. Dennett - 1973 - In Ted Honderich (ed.), Essays on Freedom of Action. Boston,: Routledge and Kegan Paul. pp. 157--84.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Freedom of the will and the concept of a person.Harry Frankfurt - 2004 - In Tim Crane & Katalin Farkas (eds.), Metaphysics: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press UK.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   707 citations  
  • Persons, Character, and Morality.Bernard Williams - 1998 - In James Rachels (ed.), Ethical Theory 2: Theories About How We Should Live. Oxford University Press UK.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • Psychological Egoism.Joel Feinberg - 1971 - In Reason and responsibility. Encino, Calif.,: Dickenson Pub. Co.. pp. 183.
  • Internal and External Reasons.Bernard Williams - 1979 - In Ross Harrison (ed.), Rational action: studies in philosophy and social science. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 101-113.
  • The Emptiness of the Moral Will.Allen W. Wood - 1989 - The Monist 72 (3):454-483.
    It is well known that Hegel contrasts the “Moral standpoint” or “morality” with the higher standpoint of “social ethics” or “ethical life”, and that he regards Kant’s ethical theory as an expression of the moral standpoint. Hegel finds many shortcomings in the moral standpoint, but probably the most famous of Hegel’s criticisms of Kantian moral theory is the charge that Kant’s theory is an “empty formalism,” incapable of providing any “immanent doctrine of duties,” The Kantian moral law, says Hegel, has (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The self and the future.Bernard Williams - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (2):161-180.
  • Levinas and the Immediacy of the Face.Merold Westphal - 1993 - Faith and Philosophy 10 (4):486-502.
  • Free agency.Gary Watson - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (April):205-20.
    In the subsequent pages, I want to develop a distinction between wanting and valuing which will enable the familiar view of freedom to make sense of the notion of an unfree action. The contention will be that, in the case of actions that are unfree, the agent is unable to get what he most wants, or values, and this inability is due to his own "motivational system." In this case the obstruction to the action that he most wants to do (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   487 citations  
  • Free action and free will.Gary Watson - 1987 - Mind 96 (April):154-72.
  • The Possibility of Practical Reason.J. David Velleman - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 121 (3):263-275.
  • Heidegger on desire.Ben Vedder - 1998 - Continental Philosophy Review 31 (4):353-368.
    In this article is presented a reading of Heidegger in relation to the conception of desire, and its relation to various terms he uses frequently. I argue that the genesis of desire lies in the gap between the fullness of possibility and the poverty of actualization; that inauthentic desire aims at presence, possession, actualization (always insufficient); and that authentic desire aims at the conservation of the possibility-character of being. I also pay attention to the temporality of desire; to the analogy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant and the possibility of moral motivation.Mark Timmons - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (3):377-398.
    This paper is divided into three major sections. In section 1, I explain why it is that kant's theory of moral motivation is crucial in developing a certain sort of moral theory in opposition to both the ethical empiricist and the rationalist--A theory of moral reasons I characterize as a "rationalist internalism." in section 2, I present some of the detail of kant's theory of moral motivation, And in particular, The reasons why kant was led to a special a priori (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Faintest Passion.Harry Frankfurt - 1992 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66 (3):5-16.
  • Deadly vices.Gabriele Taylor - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Gabriele Taylor presents a philosophical investigation of the "ordinary" vices traditionally seen as "death to the soul": sloth, envy, avarice, pride, anger, lust, and gluttony. In the course of a richly detailed discussion of individual and interrelated vices, which complements recent work by moral philosophers on virtue, she shows why these "deadly sins" are correctly so named and grouped together.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Motive and rightness.Steven Sverdlik - 1996 - Ethics 106 (2):327-349.
    Motive and Rightness is the first book-length attempt to answer the question: Does the motive of an action ever make a difference to whether that action is ...
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • 9. Intellect, Will, and the Principle of Alternate Possibilities.Eleonore Stump - 1993 - In John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza (eds.), Perspectives on Moral Responsibility. Cornell University Press. pp. 237-262.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The schizophrenia of modern ethical theories.Michael Stocker - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (14):453-466.
  • Agent-Based Virtue Ethics.Michael Slote - 1995 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 20 (1):83-101.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Beyond decisionism and anarchy: The task of re-thinking resolve. [REVIEW]Frank Schalow - 1995 - Man and World 28 (4):359-376.
  • Agent-centred restrictions, rationality, and the virtues.Samuel Scheffler - 1985 - Mind 94 (375):409-419.
  • Autonomy Reconsidered.Sarah Buss - 1994 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1):95-121.
  • Hell on earth : Hannah Arendt in the face of Hitler.Jacob Rogozinski - 1993 - In Ari Hirvonen & Janne Porttikivi (eds.), Philosophy Today. Routledge. pp. 257-274.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Will power and the virtues.Robert C. Roberts - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):227-247.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Nonfactualism about Normative Discourse.Peter Railton - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (4):961 - 968.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Second Order Desires and Strength of Will.Mark Stephen Pestana - 1996 - Modern Schoolman 73 (2):173-182.
  • The Refutation of Agathon.Andrew Payne - 1999 - Ancient Philosophy 19 (2):235-253.
  • The Refutation of Agathon.Andrew Payne - 1999 - Ancient Philosophy 19 (2):235-253.
  • Self and will.N. M. L. Nathan - 1997 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (1):81 – 94.
    When do two mental items belong to the same life? We could be content with the answer -just when they have certain volitional qualities in common. An affinity is noted between that theory and Berkeley's early doctrine of the self. Some rivals of the volitional theory invoke a spiritual or physical owner of mental items. They run a risk either of empty formality or of causal superstition. Other rivals postulate a non-transitive and symmetrical relation in the set of mental items. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The reward event and motivation.Carolyn R. Morillo - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy 87 (4):169-186.
    In philosophy, the textbook case for the discussion of human motivation is the examination (and almost always, the refutation) of psychological egoism. The arguments have become part of the folklore of our tribe, from their inclusion in countless introductory texts. [...] One of my central aims has been to define the issues empirically, so we do not just settle them by definition. Although I am inclined at present to put my bets on the reward-event theory, with its internalism, monism, and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • When Are My Actions Due to Me?Denise Meyerson - 1994 - Analysis 54 (3):171 - 174.
  • Socratic Piety In The Euthyphro.Mark L. McPherran - 1985 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 23 (3):283-309.
  • Virtue and Reason.John Mcdowell - 1979 - The Monist 62 (3):331-350.
    1. Presumably the point of, say, inculcating a moral outlook lies in a concern with how people live. It may seem that the very idea of a moral outlook makes room for, and requires, the existence of moral theory, conceived as a discipline which seeks to formulate acceptable principles of conduct. It is then natural to think of ethics as a branch of philosophy related to moral theory, so conceived, rather as the philosophy of science is related to science. On (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   566 citations  
  • Desire as belief II.David K. Lewis - 1996 - Mind 105 (418):303-13.
  • God and Philosophy.Emmanuel Levinas - 1978 - Philosophy Today 22 (2):127-145.
  • Two conceptions of happiness.Richard Kraut - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (2):167-197.
    I argue that the many similarities between what aristotle says about "eudaimonia" and what we say about happiness justify the traditional translation of "eudaimonia" as "happiness." it is not widely realized that "eudaimonia" involves a psychological state much like the one we call "happiness." nor is it generally recognized that both "eudaimonia" and "happiness" involve a standard for evaluating lives. For aristotle, The standard is objective and inflexible; for us, It is subjective and flexible. Thus, When we call someone happy (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Happiness and the Willing Agent.Bonnie Kent - 2004 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 78:59-70.
    Contemporary philosophers who are concerned with the following three philosophical issues can learn much from Scotus: (1) the defense of agent-causal accounts of the will; (2) the search for common ground between ancient and Kantian ethics: and (3) the co-existence of free will and the capacity for sin in heaven.1) Free Will and Agent Causation: According to Scotus, the will moves itself to act, but does not cause itself. Human actions are done for reasons determinedby the agent; they are not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Reflexivity of Evil.John Kekes - 1998 - Social Philosophy and Policy 15 (1):216.
    The aim of this essay is to argue for the following claims: evil is prevalent; its prevalence is mainly the result of habitual and predictable patterns of action; these actions follow from the vices of their agents; in many cases, neither the evil actions nor the vices from which they follow are autonomous; it is nevertheless justified to hold the agents who perform these actions morally responsible for them; the widespread denial of this claim rests on the principle “ought implies (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Limits of Well-Being.Shelly Kagan - 1992 - Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (2):169-189.
    What are the limits of well-being? This question nicely captures one of the central debates concerning the nature of the individual human good. For rival theories differ as to what sort of facts directly constitute a person's being well-off. On some views, well-being is limited to the presence of pleasure and the absence of pain. But other views push the boundaries of well-being beyond this, so that it encompasses a variety of mental states, not merely pleasure alone. Some theories then (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • Intending.A. C. Purton - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (118):79-80.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Strength of character.Margaret R. Holmgren - 2004 - Journal of Value Inquiry 38 (3):393-409.
  • Rationality in action.Martin Hollis & Robert Sugden - 1993 - Mind 102 (405):1-35.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations