Switch to: Citations

References in:

Occasionalism and strict mechanism: Malebranche, Berkeley, fontenelle

In Christia Mercer (ed.), Early Modern Philosophy: Mind, Matter, and Metaphysics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 206-230 (2005)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Malebranche et Newton.Paul Mouy - 1938 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 45 (3):411 - 435.
  • Occasionalism and general will in Malebranche.Steven M. Nadler - 1993 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (1):31-47.
    This paper examines a common misreading of the mechanics of Malebranche's doctrine of divine causal agency, occasionalism, and its roots in a related misreading of Malebranche's theories. God, contrary to this misreading, is for Malebranche constantly and actively causally engaged in the world, and does not just establish certain laws of nature. The key is in understanding just what Malebranche means by general volitions'.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Force (God) in Descartes' physics.Gary C. Hatfield - 1979 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 10 (2):113-140.
    It is difficult to evaluate the role of activity - of force or of that which has causal efficacy - in Descartes’ natural philosophy. On the one hand, Descartes claims to include in his natural philosophy only that which can be described geometrically, which amounts to matter (extended substance) in motion (where this motion is described kinematically).’ Yet on the other hand, rigorous adherence to a purely geometrical description of matter in motion would make it difficult to account for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Siris and the scope of Berkeley's instrumentalism.Lisa J. Downing - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (2):279 – 300.
    I. Introduction Siris, Berkeley's last major work, is undeniably a rather odd book. It could hardly be otherwise, given Berkeley's aims in writing it, which are three-fold: 'to communicate to the public the salutary virtues of tar-water,'1 to provide scientific background supporting the efficacy of tar-water as a medicine, and to lead the mind of the reader, via gradual steps, toward contemplation of God.2 The latter two aims shape Berkeley's extensive use of contemporary natural science in Siris. In particular, Berkeley's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Force (God) in Descartes' Physics.Gary Hatfield - 1998 - In John Cottingham (ed.), Descartes. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 281-310.
    Reprint of: Gary Hatfield, Force (God) in Descartes' physics, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 10 (2):113-140 (1979) -/- Abstract. It is difficult to evaluate the role of activity - of force or of that which has causal efficacy - in Descartes’ natural philosophy. On the one hand, Descartes claims to include in his natural philosophy only that which can be described geometrically, which amounts to matter (extended substance) in motion (where this motion is described kinematically).’ Yet (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Force and inertia in the seventeenth century: Descartes and Newton.Alan Gabbey - 1980 - In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics and Physics. Barnes & Noble. pp. 230--320.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • The metaphysics and physics of force in Descartes.Martial Gueroult - 1980 - In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics and Physics. Harvester Press. pp. 196--229.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Occasionalism of Louis de la Forge.Steven Nadler - 1993 - In Causation in Early Modern Philosophy. Pennsylvania State University Press. pp. 57--73.