Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Reviewing Herschel's discourse.Richard Yeo - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (4):541-552.
  • William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid nineteenth century Britain.Richard Yeo - 1979 - Annals of Science 36 (5):493-516.
    (1979). William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid nineteenth century Britain. Annals of Science: Vol. 36, No. 5, pp. 493-516.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Rethinking Whewell.John Wettersten - 1993 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 23 (4):481-515.
    The nineteenth-century appraisal of Whewell's philosophy as confused, eclectic, and metaphysical is still dominant today. Yet he keeps reappearing on the agenda of the historians and philosophers of science. Why? Whewell continues to be a puzzle. Historians evade the puzzle by deeming him to have had no serious philosophy but some interesting ideas and/or to have been socially important. Menachim Fisch's recent study offers promise of a new appraisal. But Fisch's account leads back to the puzzle. Fisch poses the question (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Whewell and the Scientists: Science and Philosophy of Science in 19th Century Britain.Laura Snyder - 2002 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 9:81-94.
    What is the relation between science and philosophy of science? Specifically, does it matter whether a philosopher of science knows much about science or is actually engaged in scientific research? William Whewell is an obvious person to consider in relation to this question. Whewell was actively engaged in science in several important ways, some of which have not been previously noted. He conducted research in a number of scientific fields, he devised new terminology for the new discoveries made by other (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • It's all necessarily so: William Whewell on scientific truth.Laura J. Snyder - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):785-807.
  • Discoverers' induction.Laura J. Snyder - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):580-604.
    In this paper I demonstrate that, contrary to the standard interpretations, William Whewell's view of scientific method is neither that of the hypothetico-deductivist nor that of the retroductivist. Rather, he offers a unique inductive methodology, which he calls "discoverers' induction." After explicating this methodology, I show that Kepler's discovery of his first law of planetary motion conforms to it, as Whewell claims it does. In explaining Whewell's famous phrase about "happy guesses" in science, I suggest that Whewell intended a distinction (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Galilean reflections on Milton friedman’s "methodology of positive economics," with thoughts on Vernon smith’s "economics in the laboratory".Eric Schliesser - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (1):50-74.
    In this article, the author offers a discussion of the evidential role of the Galilean constant in the history of physics. The author argues that measurable constants help theories constrain data. Theories are engines for research, and this helps explain why the Duhem-Quine thesis does not undermine scientific practice. The author connects his argument to discussion of two famous papers in the history of economic methodology, Milton Friedman's 'Methodology of Positive Economics', which appealed to example of Galilean Law of Fall (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Observing Science in Early Victorian England: Recent Scholarship on William Whewell.Joan L. Richards - 1996 - Perspectives on Science 4 (2):231-247.
  • Galileo’s Tidal Theory.Ron Naylor - 2007 - Isis 98 (1):1-22.
  • Galileo’s Tidal Theory.Ron Naylor - 2007 - Isis 98:1-22.
    The aim of Galileo’s tidal theory was to show that the tides were produced entirely by the earth’s motion and thereby to demonstrate the physical truth of Copernicanism. However, in the Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems Galileo did not explain some of the most significant aspects of the theory completely. As a consequence, the way the theory works has long been disputed. Though there exist a number of interpretations in the literature, the most widely accepted are based on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Whewell on the ultimate problem of philosophy.Margaret Morrison - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (3):417-437.
  • William Whewell and John Stuart Mill on the Methodology of Political Economy.Samuel Hollander - 1983 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 14 (2):127.
  • A “large And Graceful Sinuosity”.Thomas Hankins - 2006 - Isis 97:605-633.
    In 1833 John Herschel published a graphical method for determining the orbits of double stars. He argued that his method, which depended on human judgment rather than mathematical analysis, gave better results than computation, given the uncertainty in the data. Herschel found that astronomy and terrestrial physics were especially suitable for graphical treatment, and he expected that graphs would soon become important in all areas of science. He argued with William Whewell and James D. Forbes over the process of induction, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A “Large and Graceful Sinuosity”.Thomas L. Hankins - 2006 - Isis 97 (4):605-633.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Whewell's Consilience of Inductions–An Evaluation.Menachem Fisch - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (2):239-255.
    The paper attempts to elucidate and evaluate William Whewell's notion of a "consilience of inductions." In section I Whewellian consilience is defined and shown to differ considerably from what latter-day writers talk about when they use the term. In section II a primary analysis of consilience is shown to yield two types of consilient processes, one in which one of the lower-level laws undergoes a conceptual change (the case aptly discussed in Butts [1977]), and one in which the explanatory theory (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Necessary and contingent truth in William Whewell's antithetical theory of knowledge.Menachem Fisch - 1984 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 16 (4):275-314.
  • Galilean reflections on Milton friedman’ S “ methodology of positive economics, ” with thoughts on Vernon smith’ S “ economics in the laboratory&rdquo””.Schliesser Eric - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (1):50-74.
    In this article, the author offers a discussion of the evidential role of the Galilean constant in the history of physics. The author argues that measurable constants help theories constrain data. Theories are engines for research, and this helps explain why the Duhem-Quine thesis does not undermine scientific practice. The author connects his argument to discussion of two famous papers in the history of economic methodology, Milton Friedman’s “Methodology of Positive Economics,” which appealed to example of Galilean Law of Fall (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Whewell, Necessity and The Inductive Sciences: A Philosophical-Systematic Survey.Steffen Ducheyne - 2009 - South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (4):333-358.
    In this paper Whewell’s concept of necessity is scrutinized and its historical development is outlined (ca. 1833-1860). Particular attention will be paid to how Whewell interpreted the laws of the inductive sciences as being necessary since the laws of nature are concretizations of the Fundamental Ideas which can be partially described by Axioms.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Newton's training in the Aristotelian textbook tradition: from effects to causes and back.Steffen Ducheyne - 2005 - History of Science 43 (3):217-237.
  • Newton’s notion and practice of unification.Steffen Ducheyne - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (1):61-78.
    n this paper I deal with a neglected topic with respect to unification in Newton’s Principia. I will clarify Newton’s notion and practice of unification . In order to do so, I will use the recent theories on unification as tools of analysis . I will argue, after showing that neither Kitcher’s nor Schurz’s account aptly capture Newton’s notion and practice of unification, that Salmon’s later work is a good starting point for analysing this notion and its practice in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Whewell's Critics: Have They Prevented Him from Doing Good?John Wettersten - 2005 - Rodopi.
    William Whewell's views on the philosophy of science were dismissed as incoherent and eclectic when he introduced them in the middle of the 19th century, though some leading contemporaries engaged and even incorporated them. When his ideas were resurrected a century later, they were dismissed as poor induction rather than original thinking. Wettersten (philosophy of science, Mannheim U., Germany) explores why Whewell's impact continues to be felt, and why almost all theorists have had to come to terms with his ideas. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • William Whewell: A Composite Portrait.Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.) - 1991 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    William Whewell was a giant of Victorian intellectual culture. His influence, whether recognized or forgotten, is palpable in areas as diverse as moral philosophy, mineralogy, architecture, the politics of education, physics, engineering, and theology. Recent studies of the place of the sciences in nineteenth-century Britain have repeatedly indicated the significance of Whewell's sweeping and critical proposals for a reformed account of scientific knowledge and moral values. However, until now there has been no detailed study of the context and impact of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.Isaac Newton - 1999 - University of California Press.
    Presents Newton's unifying idea of gravitation and explains how he converted physics from a science of explanation into a general mathematical system.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • Between rationalism and romanticism: Whewell's historiography of the inductive sciences.Geoffrey N. Cantor - 1991 - In Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. Clarendon Press. pp. 67--96.
  • General scholium.Isaac Newton - 1999 - In The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. University of California Press. pp. 939-944.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Necessary Truth in Whewell's Theory of Science.Robert E. Butts - 1965 - American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (3):161 - 181.
  • Dialogue concerning the Two Chief World Systems.Galileo Galilei & Stillman Drake - 1954 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 5 (19):253-256.
  • A philosopher's coming of age: A study in erotetic intellectual history.Menachem Fisch - 1991 - In Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. Clarendon Press. pp. 31--66.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • William Whewell: Omniscientist.Michael Ruse - 1991 - In Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. Clarendon Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations