Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Paradox of Emotion and Fiction.Robert J. Yanal - 1994 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75 (1):54-75.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Fearing fictions.Kendall L. Walton - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (1):5-27.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • Does the Paradox of Fiction Exist?Katherine Tullmann & Wesley Buckwalter - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (4):779-796.
    Many philosophers have attempted to provide a solution to the paradox of fiction, a triad of sentences that lead to the conclusion that genuine emotional responses to fiction are irrational. We suggest that disagreement over the best response to this paradox stems directly from the formulation of the paradox itself. Our main goal is to show that there is an ambiguity regarding the word ‘exist’ throughout the premises of the paradox. To reveal this ambiguity, we display the diverse existential commitments (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Is the Paradox of Fiction Soluble in Psychology?Florian Cova & Fabrice Teroni - 2016 - Philosophical Psychology 29 (6):930-942.
    If feeling a genuine emotion requires believing that its object actually exists, and if this is a belief we are unlikely to have about fictional entities, then how could we feel genuine emotions towards these entities? This question lies at the core of the paradox of fiction. Since its original formulation, this paradox has generated a substantial literature. Until recently, the dominant strategy had consisted in trying to solve it. Yet, it is more and more frequent for scholars to try (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Really believing in fiction.David B. Suits - 2006 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (3):369–386.
    How is it possible to respond emotionally to that which we believe is not the case? All of the many responses to this "paradox of fiction" make one or more of three important mistakes: (1) neglecting the context of believing, (2) assuming that belief is an all-or-nothing affair, and (3) assuming that if you believe that p then you cannot also reasonably believe that not-p. My thesis is that we react emotionally to stories because we do believe what stories tell (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Fiction and the suspension of disbelief.Eva Schaper - 1978 - British Journal of Aesthetics 18 (1):31-44.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina.Colin Radford & Michael Weston - 1975 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 49 (1):67 - 93.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Fiction, pity, fear, and jealousy.Colin Radford - 1995 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1):71-75.
  • Rational fear of monsters.R. Joyce - 2000 - British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (2):209-224.
    Colin Radford must weary of defending his thesis that the emotional reactions we have towards fictional characters, events, and states of affairs are irrational.1 Yet, for all the discussion, the issue has not, to my mind, been properly settled—or at least not settled in the manner I should prefer—and so this paper attempts once more to debunk Radford’s defiance of common sense. For some, the question of whether our emotional responses to fiction are rational does not arise, for they are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Real Trouble with Recalcitrant Emotions.Alex Grzankowski - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (3):641-651.
    Cognitivists about the emotions minimally hold that it is a necessary condition for being in an emotional state that one make a certain judgement or have a certain belief. For example, if I am angry with Sam, then I must believe that Sam has wronged me. Perhaps I must also elicit a certainly bodily response or undergo some relevant experience, but crucial to the view is the belief or judgement. In the face of ‘recalcitrant emotions’, this once very popular view (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Pleasure and pain in literature.Oliver Conolly - 2005 - Philosophy and Literature 29 (2):305-320.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Pleasure and Pain in LiteratureOliver ConollyWhy do we enjoy the depiction, in imaginative literature, of situations that typically arouse negative emotions such as pity, sadness, and horror? One view, which aims to dissolve rather than solve the problem, is that we do not enjoy them at all. According to this theory—the pure pain theory—the problem does not arise in the first place. But the theory must explain why we (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Replies to Three Critics.Colin Radford - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (247):93 - 97.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The irrationality of recalcitrant emotions.Michael S. Brady - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 145 (3):413 - 430.
    A recalcitrant emotion is one which conflicts with evaluative judgement. (A standard example is where someone is afraid of flying despite believing that it poses little or no danger.) The phenomenon of emotional recalcitrance raises an important problem for theories of emotion, namely to explain the sense in which recalcitrant emotions involve rational conflict. In this paper I argue that existing ‘neojudgementalist’ accounts of emotions fail to provide plausible explanations of the irrationality of recalcitrant emotions, and develop and defend my (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • The Psychology of Aristotelian Tragedy.Amélie Oksenberg Rorty - 1991 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 16 (1):53-72.
  • The paradox of fiction.Steven Schneider - 2002 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Emotion.Ronald de Sousa - 2007 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Genuine Rational Fictional Emotions.Tamar Szabó Gendler & Karson Kovakovich - 2006 - In Matthew Kieran (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art. Blackwell. pp. 241-253.
    The “paradox of fictional emotions” involves a trio of claims that are jointly inconsistent but individually plausible. Resolution of the paradox thus requires that we deny at least one of these plausible claims. The paradox has been formulated in various ways, but for the purposes of this chapter, we will focus on the following three claims, which we will refer to respectively as the Response Condition, the Belief Condition and the Coordination Condition.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Art, narrative, and moral understanding.Noël Carroll - 1998 - In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection. Cambridge University Press. pp. 126--60.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • On the relation between pretense and belief.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2003 - In Matthew Kieran & Dominic McIver Lopes (eds.), Imagination Philosophy and the Arts. Routledge. pp. 125--141.
    By the age of two, children are able to engage in highly elaborate games of symbolic pretense, in which objects and actions in the actual world are taken to stand for objects and actions in a realm of make-believe. These games of pretense are marked by the presence of two central features, which I will call quarantining and mirroring (see also Leslie 1987; Perner 1991). Quarantining is manifest to the extent that events within the pretense-episode are taken to have effects (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations