Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The standard picture and its discontents.Mark Greenberg - 2011 - In Leslie Green & Brian Leiter (eds.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law. New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this paper, I argue that there is a picture of how law works that most legal theorists are implicitly committed to and take to be common ground. This Standard Picture (SP, for short) is generally unacknowledged and unargued for. SP leads to a characteristic set of concerns and problems and yields a distinctive way of thinking about how law is supposed to operate. I suggest that the issue of whether SP is correct is a fundamental one for the philosophy (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Ontological relativity and other essays.Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.) - 1969 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    This volume consists of the first of the John Dewey Lectures delivered under the auspices of Columbia University's Philosophy Department as well as other essays by the author. Intended to clarify the meaning of the philosophical doctrines propounded by Professor Quine in 'Word and Objects', the essays included herein both support and expand those doctrines.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1304 citations  
  • Foreword.Christopher Peacocke - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy 105 (9):441-452.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The pragmatics of legal language.Andrei Marmor - 2008 - Ratio Juris 21 (4):423-452.
    The purpose of this essay is to explore some of the main pragmatic aspects of communication within the legal context. It will be argued that in some crucial respects, the pragmatics of legal language is unique, involving considerations that are not typically present in ordinary conversational contexts. In particular, certain normative considerations that are typically settled in a regular conversational context are unresolved and potentially contentious in the legal case. On the other hand, the essay also argues that a careful (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Legal realism and legal positivism reconsidered.Brian Leiter - 2001 - Ethics 111 (2):278-301.
  • A Reply to Our Critics.Steven Knapp & Walter Benn Michaels - 1983 - Critical Inquiry 9 (4):790-800.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Against Theory.Steven Knapp & Walter Benn Michaels - 1982 - Critical Inquiry 8 (4):723-742.
    By "theory" we mean a special project in literary criticism: the attempt to govern interpretations of particular texts by appealing to an account of interpretation in general. The term is sometimes applied to literary subjects with no direct bearing on the interpretation of individual works, such as narratology, stylistics, and prosody. Despite their generality, however, these subjects seem to us essentially empirical, and our argument against theory will not apply to them.Contemporary theory has taken two forms. Some theorists have sought (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • How to Read “Epistemology Naturalized”.Bredo C. Johnsen - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy 102 (2):78-93.
  • Naturalism in Epistemology and the Philosophy of Law.Mark Greenberg - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (4):419-451.
    In this paper, I challenge an influential understanding of naturalization according to which work on traditional problems in the philosophy of law should be replaced with sociological or psychological explanations of how judges decide cases. W.V. Quine famously proposed the ‘naturalization of epistemology’. In a prominent series of papers and a book, Brian Leiter has raised the intriguing idea that Quine’s naturalization of epistemology is a useful model for philosophy of law. I examine Quine’s naturalization of epistemology and Leiter’s suggested (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • How facts make law.Greenberg Mark - 2004 - Legal Theory 10 (3).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • How facts make law.Mark Greenberg - 2004 - In Scott Hershovitz (ed.), Exploring Law's Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin. Oxford University Press. pp. 157-198.
    I offer a new argument against the legal positivist view that non-normative social facts can themselves determine the content of the law. I argue that the nature of the determination relation in law is rational determination: the contribution of law-determining practices to the content of the law must be based on reasons. That is why it must be possible in principle to explain what makes the law have the content that it does. It follows, I argue, that non-normative facts about (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • A New Map of Theories of Mental Content: Constitutive Accounts and Normative Theories.Mark Greenberg - 2005 - Philosophical Issues 15 (1):299-320.
    In this paper, I propose a new way of understanding the space of possibilities in the field of mental content. The resulting map assigns separate locations to theories of content that have generally been lumped together on the more traditional map. Conversely, it clusters together some theories of content that have typically been regarded as occupying opposite poles. I make my points concrete by developing a taxonomy of theories of mental content, but the main points of the paper concern not (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Legislation as Communication? Legal Interpretation and the Study of Linguistic Communication.Mark Greenberg - 2011 - In Andrei Marmor & Scott Soames (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Language in the Law. Oxford University Press, Usa.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Can the Law Imply More than It Says? On Some Pragmatic Aspects of Strategic Speech.Andrei Marmor - 2011 - In Andrei Marmor & Scott Soames (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Language in the Law. Oxford University Press, Usa.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Explaining theoretical disagreement.Brian Leiter - manuscript
    Shapiro has recently argued that Dworkin posed a new objection to legal positivism in Law's Empire, to which positivists, he says, have not adequately responded. Positivists, the objection goes, have no satisfactory account of what Dworkin calls “theoretical disagreement” about law, that is, disagreement about “the grounds of law” or what positivists would call the criteria of legal validity. I agree with Shapiro that the critique is new, and disagree that it has not been met. Positivism can not offer an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsedered.Brain Letter - 2001 - Ethics 111:300-301.
  • Interpreting legal texts: What is, and what is not, special about the law.Scott Soames - manuscript
    To be presented at an International Conference on Law, Language, and Interpretation, at the University of Akureyri, Akureyri, Iceland, April 1-2, 2007.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Naturalism and naturalized jurisprudence.Brian Leiter - 1998 - In Brian Bix (ed.), Analyzing Law: New Essays in Legal Theory. Oxford University Press. pp. 79.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations