Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Against computational hermeneutics.Stevan Harnad - 1990 - Social Epistemology 4:167-172.
    Critique of Computationalism as merely projecting hermeneutics (i.e., meaning originating from the mind of an external interpreter) onto otherwise intrinsically meaningless symbols.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1692 citations  
  • What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (October):435-50.
  • Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology.Jerry A. Fodor - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):63-73.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   668 citations  
  • The Nature of Mind.David Malet Armstrong - 1981 - Australasian Medical Publishing Co..
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Computers, cognition and philosophy.Robert Wilensky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):449-450.
  • Godel's theorem and the mind.Peter Slezak - 1982 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (March):41-52.
  • The causal powers of the brain: The necessity of sufficiency.John R. Searle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):164-164.
  • The Chinese room revisited.J. R. Searle - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):345-348.
  • Patterns, symbols, and understanding.John R. Searle - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):742-743.
  • Intrinsic intentionality.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):450-457.
  • What’s Really Going On in Searle’s “Chinese room‘.Georges Rey - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 50 (September):169-85.
  • The Self and Its Brain: An Argument for Interactionism.Karl R. Popper & John C. Eccles - 1977 - Critica 11 (33):133-137.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Precis of the emperor's new mind.Roger Penrose - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):643-705.
    The emperor's new mind (hereafter Emperor) is an attempt to put forward a scientific alternative to the viewpoint of according to which mental activity is merely the acting out of some algorithmic procedure. John Searle and other thinkers have likewise argued that mere calculation does not, of itself, evoke conscious mental attributes, such as understanding or intentionality, but they are still prepared to accept the action the brain, like that of any other physical object, could in principle be simulated by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Physical symbol systems.Allen Newell - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (2):135-83.
    On the occasion of a first conference on Cognitive Science, it seems appropriate to review the basis of common understanding between the various disciplines. In my estimate, the most fundamental contribution so far of artificial intelligence and computer science to the joint enterprise of cognitive science has been the notion of a physical symbol system, i.e., the concept of a broad class of systems capable of having and manipulating symbols, yet realizable in the physical universe. The notion of symbol so (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   485 citations  
  • Minds, brains, programs, and persons.Drew McDermott - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):339-341.
  • Not a trivial consequence.Kenneth G. MacQueen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):163-164.
  • Minds, Machines and Gödel.J. R. Lucas - 1961 - Etica E Politica 5 (1):1.
    In this article, Lucas maintains the falseness of Mechanism - the attempt to explain minds as machines - by means of Incompleteness Theorem of Gödel. Gödel’s theorem shows that in any system consistent and adequate for simple arithmetic there are formulae which cannot be proved in the system but that human minds can recognize as true; Lucas points out in his turn that Gödel’s theorem applies to machines because a machine is the concrete instantiation of a formal system: therefore, for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Minds, Machines and Gödel.John R. Lucas - 1961 - Philosophy 36 (137):112-127.
    Gödei's Theorem seems to me to prove that Mechanism is false, that is, that minds cannot be explained as machines. So also has it seemed to many other people: almost every mathematical logician I have put the matter to has confessed to similar thoughts, but has felt reluctant to commit himself definitely until he could see the whole argument set out, with all objections fully stated and properly met. This I attempt to do.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • The timing of a subjective experience.Benjamin Libet - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):183-185.
  • Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action.Benjamin Libet - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):529-66.
    Voluntary acts are preceded by electrophysiological (RPs). With spontaneous acts involving no preplanning, the main negative RP shift begins at about200 ms. Control experiments, in which a skin stimulus was timed (S), helped evaluate each subject's error in reporting the clock times for awareness of any perceived event.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   751 citations  
  • On the nature of programs, simulations, and organisms.R. J. Harvey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):741-742.
  • Precis of the modularity of mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):1-42.
    The Modularity of Mind proposes an alternative to the or view of cognitive architecture that has dominated several decades of cognitive science. Whereas interactionism stresses the continuity of perceptual and cognitive processes, modularity theory argues for their distinctness. It is argued, in particular, that the apparent plausibility of New Look theorizing derives from the failure to distinguish between the (correct) claim that perceptual processes are inferential and the (dubious) claim that they are unencapsidated, that is, that they are arbitrarily sensitive (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   276 citations  
  • Computationalism.Eric Dietrich - 1990 - Social Epistemology 4 (2):135-154.
    This paper argues for a noncognitiveist computationalism in the philosophy of mind. It further argues that both humans and computers have intentionality, that is, their mental states are semantical -- they are about things in their worlds.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Precis of the intentional stance.Daniel C. Dennett - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):495-505.
    The intentional stance is the strategy of prediction and explanation that attributes beliefs, desires, and other states to systems and predicts future behavior from what it would be rational for an agent to do, given those beliefs and desires. Any system whose performance can be thus predicted and explained is an intentional system, whatever its innards. The strategy of treating parts of the world as intentional systems is the foundation of but is also exploited in artificial intelligence and cognitive science (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Programs, language understanding, and Searle.Lawrence Richard Carleton - 1984 - Synthese 59 (May):219-30.
  • Parapsychology: Science of the anomalous or search for the soul?James E. Alcock - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):553.
  • [Book Chapter].Stevan Harnad - 1987
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Lost in the hermeneutic hall of mirrors.Stevan Harnad - 1990 - Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 2:321-27.
    Critique of Computationalism as merely projecting hermeneutics (i.e., meaning originating from the mind of an external interpreter) onto otherwise intrinsically meaningless symbols. Projecting an interpretation onto a symbol system results in its being reflected back, in a spuriously self-confirming way.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The View from Nowhere.Thomas Nagel - 1986 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 43 (2):399-403.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   498 citations  
  • Verifying machines' minds. [REVIEW]Stevan Harnad - 1984 - Contemporary Psychology 29:389 - 391.
    he question of the possibility of artificial consciousness is both very new and very old. It is new in the context of contemporary cognitive science and its concern with whether a machine can be conscious; it is old in the form of the mind/body problem and the "other minds" problem of philosophy. Contemporary enthusiasts proceed at their peril if they ignore or are ignorant of the false starts and blind alleys that the older thinkers have painfully worked through.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intentionality and computationalism: Minds, machines, Searle and Harnad.Michael G. Dyer - 1990 - Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 2:303-19.
  • The symbol grounding problem.Stevan Harnad - 1990 - Physica D 42:335-346.
    There has been much discussion recently about the scope and limits of purely symbolic models of the mind and about the proper role of connectionism in cognitive modeling. This paper describes the symbol grounding problem : How can the semantic interpretation of a formal symbol system be made intrinsic to the system, rather than just parasitic on the meanings in our heads? How can the meanings of the meaningless symbol tokens, manipulated solely on the basis of their shapes, be grounded (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   344 citations  
  • What is consciousness?David M. Armstrong - 1981 - In John Heil (ed.), The Nature of Mind. Cornell University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Consciousness: An afterthought.Stevan Harnad - 1982 - Cognition and Brain Theory 5:29-47.
    There are many possible approaches to the mind/brain problem. One of the most prominent, and perhaps the most practical, is to ignore it.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Is the Brain’s Mind a Computer Program?John R. Searle - 1990 - Scientific American 262 (1):26-31.
  • Steps Toward Artificial Intelligence.Marvin Minsky - unknown
    Received by the IRE, October 24, 1960. The author's work summarized here—which was done at the MIT Lincoln Laboratory, a center for research operated by MIT at Lexington, Mass., with the joint Support of the U. S. Army, Navy, and Air Force under Air Force Contract AF 19-5200; and at the Res. Lab. of Electronics, MIT, Cambridge, Mass., which is supported in part by the U. S. Army Signal Corps, the Air Force Office of Scientific Research, and the ONR—is based (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations