Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Yes Means Yes: Consent as Communication.Tom Dougherty - 2015 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 43 (3):224-253.
  • Still more about duties to oneself.Warner Wick - 1960 - Ethics 71 (3):213-217.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • More about duties to oneself.Warner Wick - 1959 - Ethics 70 (2):158-163.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Moral Competence, Moral Blame, and Protest.Matthew Talbert - 2012 - The Journal of Ethics 16 (1):89-109.
    I argue that wrongdoers may be open to moral blame even if they lacked the capacity to respond to the moral considerations that counted against their behavior. My initial argument turns on the suggestion that even an agent who cannot respond to specific moral considerations may still guide her behavior by her judgments about reasons. I argue that this explanation of a wrongdoer’s behavior can qualify her for blame even if her capacity for moral understanding is impaired. A second argument (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • On duties to oneself.Marcus G. Singer - 1958 - Ethics 69 (3):202-205.
  • Duties and duties to oneself.Marcus G. Singer - 1963 - Ethics 73 (2):133-142.
  • Practical Identity and Duties to the Self.Paul Schofield - 2019 - American Philosophical Quarterly 56 (3):219-232.
    In this paper, I appeal to the notion of practical identity in order to defend the possibility of synchronic duties to the self—that is, self-directed duties focused on one's present self as opposed to one's future self. While many dismiss the idea of self-directed duties, I show that a person may be morally required to act in ways that advance her present interests and autonomy by virtue of her occupying multiple practical identities at a single moment.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the Supposed Incoherence of Obligations to Oneself.Janis David Schaab - 2021 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 99 (1):175-189.
    ABSTRACT An influential argument against the possibility of obligations to oneself states that the very notion of such obligations is incoherent: If there were such obligations, we could release ourselves from them; yet releasing oneself from an obligation is impossible. I challenge this argument by arguing against the premise that it is impossible to release oneself from an obligation. I point out that this premise assumes that if it were possible to release oneself from an obligation, it would be impossible (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On the Existence of Duties to the Self.Paul Schofield - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90 (3):505-528.
    Contemporary philosophers generally ignore the topic of duties to the self. I contend that they are mistaken to do so. The question of whether there are such duties, I argue, is of genuine significance when constructing theories of practical reasoning and moral psychology. In this essay, I show that much of the potential importance of duties to the self stems from what has been called the “second-personal” character of moral duties—the fact that the performance of a duty is “owed to” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Can Duties to the Self Bind if They Are Waivable?Paul Schofield - 2021 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 99 (1):190-195.
    ABSTRACT It is often argued that, because she would always be in the position to waive it, a person cannot owe a duty to herself. In a recent AJP article, Janis David Schaab argues that a person can owe a duty to herself even if it can be waived, thus rendering unwarranted a scepticism about such duties, as well as efforts to show that they are unwaivable. Here I argue that, for all that Schaab says, waivability continues to threaten the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Commitment and the Second-Person Standpoint.Janis Schaab - 2019 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 73 (4):511-532.
    On Chang's voluntarist account of commitments, when we commit to φ, we employ the 'normative powers' of our will to give ourselves a reason to φ that we would otherwise not have had. I argue that Chang's account, by itself, does not have sufficient conceptual resources to reconcile the normative significance of commitments with their alleged fundamentally volitional character. I suggest an alternative, second-personal account of commitment, which avoids this problem. On this account, the volitional act involved in committing is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The possibility of consent.David Owens - 2011 - Ratio 24 (4):402-421.
    Worries about the possibility of consent recall a more familiar problem about promising raised by Hume. To see the parallel here we must distinguish the power of consent from the normative significance of choice. I'll argue that we have normative interests, interests in being able to control the rights and obligations of ourselves and those around us, interests distinct from our interest in controlling the non-normative situation. Choice gets its normative significance from our non-normative control interests. By contrast, the possibility (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • How to Release Oneself from an Obligation: Good News for Duties to Oneself.Tim Oakley - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (1):70-80.
    In some cases, you may release someone from some obligation they have to you. For instance, you may release them from a promise they made to you, or an obligation to repay money they have borrowed from you. But most take it as clear that, if you have an obligation to someone else, you cannot in any way release yourself from that obligation. I shall argue the contrary. The issue is important because one standard problem for the idea of having (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Paradox of Duties to Oneself.Daniel Muñoz - 2020 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 98 (4):691-702.
    Philosophers have long argued that duties to oneself are paradoxical, as they seem to entail an incoherent power to release oneself from obligations. I argue that self-release is possible, both as a matter of deontic logic and of metaethics.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Professor Wick on duties to oneself.Mary Mothersill - 1960 - Ethics 71 (3):205-208.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Autonomy, free speech and automatic behaviour.Andrés Moles - 2006 - Res Publica 13 (1):53-75.
    One of the strongest defences of free speech holds that autonomy requires the protection of speech. In this paper I examine five conditions that autonomy must satisfy. I survey recent research in social psychology regarding automatic behaviour, and a challenge to autonomy is articulated. I argue that a plausible strategy for neutralising some of the autonomy-threatening automatic responses consists in avoiding the exposure to the environmental features that trigger them. If this is so, we can good autonomy-based pro tanto reasons (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Ontological Status of Consent and its Implications for the Law on Rape.H. M. Malm - 1996 - Legal Theory 2 (2):147-164.
    One of the dominant themes of the symposium from which this collection of articles arose was the ontological status of consent. Is consent a particular state of mind? Is it the signification of that state of mind via a conventionally recognized act? Or, is consent a normative concept that evaluates not only the presence of a state of mind or act, but also the appropriateness of that state of mind or act in the particular circumstances?
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Who Can Be Wronged?Rahul Kumar - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (2):99-118.
  • I, me, my self, and my duties.Frank H. Knight - 1960 - Ethics 71 (3):209-212.
  • Are there really "no duties to oneself"?Daniel Kading - 1959 - Ethics 70 (2):155-157.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Moral Magic of Consent: Heidi M. Hurd.Heidi M. Hurd - 1996 - Legal Theory 2 (2):121-146.
    We regularly wield powers that, upon close scrutiny, appear remarkably magical. By sheer exercise of will, we bring into existence things that have never existed before. With but a nod, we effect the disappearance of things that have long served as barriers to the actions of others. And, by mere resolve, we generate things that pose significant obstacles to others' exercise of liberty. What is the nature of these things that we create and destroy by our mere decision to do (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Contractualism, spare wheel, aggregation.Brad Hooker - 2003 - In Matt Matravers (ed.), Scanlon and Contractualism. Frank Cass Publishers. pp. 53-76.
  • Contractualism, spare wheel, aggregation.Brad Hooker - 2002 - In Matt Matravers (ed.), Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy. Frank Cass. pp. 53-76.
    This essay explores the reasons for thinking that Scanlon's contractualist principle serves merely as a ?spare wheel?, an element that spins along nicely but bears no real weight, because it presupposes too much of what it should be explaning. The ambitions and scope of Scanlon's contractualism are discussed, as is Scanlon's thesis that contracualism will assess candidate moral principles individually rather than as sets. The final third of the paper critizes Scanlon's account of fairness and his approach to cases where (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Ontology of Consent: A Reply to Alexander.Richard Healey - 2015 - Analytic Philosophy 56 (4):354-363.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Don’t Know, Don’t Kill: Moral Ignorance, Culpability, and Caution.Alexander A. Guerrero - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 136 (1):59-97.
    This paper takes on several distinct but related tasks. First, I present and discuss what I will call the “Ignorance Thesis,” which states that whenever an agent acts from ignorance, whether factual or moral, she is culpable for the act only if she is culpable for the ignorance from which she acts. Second, I offer a counterexample to the Ignorance Thesis, an example that applies most directly to the part I call the “Moral Ignorance Thesis.” Third, I argue for a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Authority and Reason‐Giving.David Enoch - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2):296-332.
  • Seduction, rape, and coercion.Sarah Conly - 2004 - Ethics 115 (1):96-121.
    In Tess of the d’Urbervilles, the innocent Tess is the object of Alec d’Urberville’s dishonorable intentions. Alec uses every wile he can think of to seduce the poor and ignorant Tess, who works keeping hens in his mother’s house: he flatters her, he impresses her with a show of wealth, he gives help to her family to win her gratitude, and he reacts with irritation and indignation when she nonetheless continues to repulse his advances, causing her to feel shame at (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Autonomy and Personal History.John Christman - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1):1 - 24.
    Virtually any appraisal of a person’s welfare, integrity, or moral status, as well as the moral and political theories built on such appraisals, will rely crucially on the presumption that her preferences and values are in some important sense her own. In particular, the nature and value of political freedom is intimately connected with the presupposition that actions one is left free to do flow from desires and values that are truly an expression of the ‘self-government’ of the agent. However, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   176 citations  
  • On Marcus Singer’s “On Duties to Oneself”.Michael Cholbi - 2015 - Ethics 125 (3):851-853,.
    In “On duties to oneself,” Marcus G. Singer argued that, contrary to long established philosophical tradition, there are no duties to oneself. Singer observes that to have a duty is to be accountable to someone for that duty’s fulfillment, and while she to whom a duty is owed may release the person who has the duty from being bound to fulfill it, the latter cannot release herself from the duty. For releasing oneself from a duty is no different from simply (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Ontology of Consent.Larry Alexander - 2014 - Analytic Philosophy 55 (1):102-113.
  • Sexual consent. [REVIEW]David Archard - 2018 - In Peter Schaber & Andreas Müller (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Ethics of Consent. Routledge. pp. 643-644.
  • Sanity and the Metaphysics of Responsibility.Susan Wolf - 1987 - In Ferdinand David Schoeman (ed.), Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions: New Essays in Moral Psychology. Cambridge University Press. pp. 46-62.
    My strategy is to examine a recent trend in philosophical discussions of responsibility, a trend that tries, but I think ultimately fails, to give an acceptable analysis of the conditions of responsibility. It fails due to what at first appear to be deep and irresolvable metaphysical problems. It is here that I suggest that the condition of sanity comes to the rescue. What at first appears to be an impossible requirement for responsibility---the requirement that the responsible agent have created her- (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • Autonomy and preference formation.Richard Arneson - 1994 - In Joel Feinberg, Jules L. Coleman & Allen E. Buchanan (eds.), In Harm's Way: Essays in Honor of Joel Feinberg. Cambridge University Press. pp. 42--75.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Morality of Freedom.Joseph Raz - 1986 - Philosophy 63 (243):119-122.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   991 citations  
  • Duties and Duties to the Self.Alison Hills - 2003 - American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (2):131 - 142.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations