Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Nonexistence.Nathan Salmon - 1998 - Noûs 32 (3):277-319.
  • Hermeneutic fictionalism.Jason Stanley - 2001 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25 (1):36–71.
    Fictionalist approaches to ontology have been an accepted part of philosophical methodology for some time now. On a fictionalist view, engaging in discourse that involves apparent reference to a realm of problematic entities is best viewed as engaging in a pretense. Although in reality, the problematic entities do not exist, according to the pretense we engage in when using the discourse, they do exist. In the vocabulary of Burgess and Rosen (1997, p. 6), a nominalist construal of a given discourse (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • The Varieties of Reference.Gareth Evans & John Mcdowell - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (238):534-538.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   582 citations  
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought.George M. Wilson & Francois Recanati - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (1):159.
  • Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts.Kendall L. Walton - 1990 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (2):161-166.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations  
  • Thinking, Language, and Experience.James E. Tomberlin & Hector-Neri Castaneda - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):667.
  • On Considering a Possible World as Actual.Robert Stalnaker & Thomas Baldwin - 2001 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75:141-174.
    [Robert Stalnaker] Saul Kripke made a convincing case that there are necessary truths that are knowable only a posteriori as well as contingent truths that are knowable a priori. A number of philosophers have used a two-dimensional model semantic apparatus to represent and clarify the phenomena that Kripke pointed to. According to this analysis, statements have truth-conditions in two different ways depending on whether one considers a possible world 'as actual' or 'as counterfactual' in determining the truth-value of the statement (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Assertion revisited: On the interpretation of two-dimensional modal semantics.Robert C. Stalnaker - 2004 - In Garc (ed.), Philosophical Studies. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 293-309.
    This paper concerns the applications of two-dimensional modal semantics to the explanation of the contents of speech and thought. Different interpretations and applications of the apparatus are contrasted. First, it is argued that David Kaplan's two-dimensional semantics for indexical expressions is different from the use that I made of a formally similar framework to represent the role of contingent information in the determination of what is said. But the two applications are complementary rather than conflicting. Second, my interpretation of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Assertion revisited: On the interpretation of two-dimensional modal semantics.Robert C. Stalnaker - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 118 (1-2):299-322.
    This paper concerns the applications of two-dimensional modal semantics to the explanation of the contents of speech and thought. Different interpretations and applications of the apparatus are contrasted. First, it is argued that David Kaplan's two-dimensional semantics for indexical expressions is different from the use that I made of a formally similar framework to represent the role of contingent information in the determination of what is said. But the two applications are complementary rather than conflicting. Second, my interpretation of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 1905 - Mind 14 (56):479-493.
    By a `denoting phrase' I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the center of mass of the solar system at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. Thus a phrase is denoting solely in virtue of its form. We may distinguish (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1196 citations  
  • The problem of empty names.Marga Reimer - 2001 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 (4):491 – 506.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • "Exists" as a predicate.George Nakhnikian & Wesley C. Salmon - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (4):535-542.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Putnam’s paradox.David Lewis - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):221 – 236.
  • Names without bearers.Jerrold J. Katz - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (1):1-39.
  • Why We Need A - Intensions.Frank Jackson - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 118 (1-2):257-277.
    I think recent discussions of content and reference have not paid enough attention to the role of language as a convention-governed system of communication. With this as a background theme, I explain the role of A-intensions in elucidating one important notion of content and correlative notions of reference.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Fictionalism and the informativeness of identity.Kroon Frederick - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 106 (3):197 - 225.
    Identity claims often look nonsensical because they apparently declare distinct things to be identical. I argue that this appearance is not just an artefact of grammar. We should be fictionalists about such claims, seeing them against the background of speakers' pretense that their words secure reference to a plurality of objects that are then declared to be identical from within the pretense. I argue that it is the resulting interpretative tension – arising from the fact that two things can never (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Direct Reference: From Language to Thought.Jennifer M. Saul - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):134-135.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   193 citations  
  • Speaking of nothing.Keith S. Donnellan - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (1):3-31.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   160 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   740 citations  
  • Two notions of necessity.Martin Davies & Lloyd Humberstone - 1980 - Philosophical Studies 38 (1):1-31.
  • Epistemic Two-Dimensional Semantics.David J. Chalmers - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 118 (1-2):153-226.
  • Empty names.David Braun - 1993 - Noûs 27 (4):449-469.
    This paper presents a theory of empty names that is consistent with direct-reference theory and Millianism.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   155 citations  
  • Complex demonstratives.Emma Borg - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 97 (2):229-249.
    Some demonstrative expressions, those we might term ‘bare demonstratives’, appear without any appended descriptive content (e.g. occurrences of ‘this’ or ‘that’ simpliciter). However, it seems that the majority of demonstrative occurrences do not follow this model. ‘Complex demonstratives’ is the collective term I shall use for phrases formed by adjoining one or more common nouns to a demonstrative expression (e.g. ‘that cat’, ‘this happy man’) and I will call the combination of predicates immediately concatenated with the demonstrative in such phrases (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts.Kendall L. WALTON - 1990 - Philosophy 66 (258):527-529.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   371 citations  
  • Intentionality.John Searle - 1983 - Philosophy 59 (229):417-418.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   594 citations  
  • Themes from Kaplan.Joseph Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein - 1990 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 180 (3):572-573.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Talk about Beliefs.Mark Crimmins - 1995 - Studia Logica 54 (3):420-421.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations