Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Four-valued semantics for relevant logics (and some of their rivals).Greg Restall - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (2):139 - 160.
    This paper gives an outline of three different approaches to the four-valued semantics for relevant logics (and other non-classical logics in their vicinity). The first approach borrows from the 'Australian Plan' semantics, which uses a unary operator '⋆' for the evaluation of negation. This approach can model anything that the two-valued account can, but at the cost of relying on insights from the Australian Plan. The second approach is natural, well motivated, independent of the Australian Plan, and it provides a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • A Useful Substructural Logic.Greg Restall - 1994 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 2 (2):137-148.
    Formal systems seem to come in two general kinds: useful and useless. This is painting things starkly, but the point is important. Formal structures can either be used in interesting and important ways, or they can languish unused and irrelevant. Lewis' modal logics are good examples. The systems S4 and S5 are useful in many different ways. They map out structures that are relevant to a number of different applications. S1, S2 and S3 however, are not so lucky. They are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Simplified semantics for basic relevant logics.Graham Priest & Richard Sylvan - 1992 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 21 (2):217 - 232.
  • The logical structure of linguistic commitment II: Systems of relevant commitment entailment. [REVIEW]Mark Lance & Philip Kremer - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (4):425 - 449.
    In "The Logical Structure of Linguistic Commitment I" (The Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (1994), 369-400), we sketch a linguistic theory (inspired by Brandom's Making it Explicit) which includes an "expressivist" account of the implication connective, →: the role of → is to "make explicit" the inferential proprieties among possible commitments which proprieties determine, in part, the significances of sentences. This motivates reading (A → B) as "commitment to A is, in part, commitment to B". Our project is to study (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The logical structure of linguistic commitment I: Four systems of non-relevant commitment entailment. [REVIEW]Mark Norris Lance & Philip Kremer - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (4):369 - 400.
  • Two Concepts of Entailment.Mark Lance - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Research 20:113-137.
    What is the logic of entailment? The latter half of the twentieth century has seen, for even the simplest languages, a proliferation of distinct formal entailment systems, each having those willing to defend its status as the answer. Among those defenders, and among the most adamant and mutually critical, are the champions of strict implication and relevance logic. To an outsider, this debate must seem singularly odd. Here we have a group of philosophers who cannot agree on the validity of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Two Concepts of Entailment.Mark Lance - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Research 20:113-137.
    What is the logic of entailment? The latter half of the twentieth century has seen, for even the simplest languages, a proliferation of distinct formal entailment systems, each having those willing to defend its status as the answer. Among those defenders, and among the most adamant and mutually critical, are the champions of strict implication and relevance logic. To an outsider, this debate must seem singularly odd. Here we have a group of philosophers who cannot agree on the validity of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Quantification, substitution, and conceptual content.Mark Lance - 1996 - Noûs 30 (4):481-507.
  • Semantic analysis of orthologic.R. I. Goldblatt - 1974 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 3 (1/2):19 - 35.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Inference, expression, and induction.Robert Brandom - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 54 (2):257 - 285.
  • Logic of Paradox.Graham Priest - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):219-241.
  • Information flow and relevant logics.Greg Restall - 1996 - In Jerry Seligman & Dag Westerståhl (eds.), Logic, Language and Computation. CSLI Publications, Stanford. pp. 463–477.