Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Wittgenstein and the Logic of Inference.Jan Zwicky - 1982 - Dialogue 21 (4):671-692.
    TheTractatusfirst appeared in 1921, the same year that Post's “Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions” appeared in theAmerican Journal of Mathematics. As the latter is the first piece clearly to present and exploit the distinction between a deductive system and a truth-functional interpretation of such a system, we may conclude that Wittgenstein's views had been arrived at somewhat before a variety of logical concepts had received the clarification and refinement incipient on the now taken-for-granted distinction between proof and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein on the beautiful, the good and the tremendous.Roger A. Shiner - 1974 - British Journal of Aesthetics 14 (3):258-271.
  • Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Language.Roger A. Shiner - 1973 - Dialogue 12 (4):683-699.
  • Canfield, Cavell and Criteria.Roger A. Shiner - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (2):253-272.
  • The Private Language Passages.J. P. Schachter - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (3):479 - 494.
    Discusssion of passages 243 et. seq. of Wittgenstein's Philosophical lnvestigations tends to concentrate on the argument supporting the thesis that a logically private language is impossible. When the discussion becomes broader, the presumption is generally that this thesis is one premifs of an argument against solipsism. I believe that the passages will support a valid argument that might, at first glance, give comfort to someone in the egocentric predicament, but that this comfort would quickly grow cold on closer examination. I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some doubts about skepticism.L. Resnick - 1987 - Philosophia 17 (2):141-148.
  • Sociological knowledge: Winch, marxism, and verstehen revisited.Kai Nielsen - 1982 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42 (4):465-491.
  • On the Rationality of Groundless Believing.Kai Nielsen - 1981 - Idealistic Studies 11 (3):215-229.
    There are three remarks of Norman Malcolm’s with which I should like to begin. The first is his remark that.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Symposium on Saying and Showing in Heidegger and Wittgenstein.Peter McCormick, Eva Schaper & J. M. Heaton - 1972 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 3 (1):27-45.
  • L'Écart des deux Wittgenstein comme discours.Roger Lapointe - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (2):276-293.
    La distinction de deux Wittgenstein est-elle mythique, ainsi que le voudrait R. J. Bernstein? Mythe créé involontairement par un penseur aussi peu mythomane que possible, B. Russell, quand, dans sa préface au Tractatus, il assigna à l'auteur l'intention d'établir les « conditions d'un langage logiquement parfait ». Prenant le contre-pied d'un Wittgenstein-I lancé à la poursuite d'un langage idéal, Wittgenstein-II aurait, dans Investigations philosophiques, opéré un retour au langage naturel et au sens commun.Il est sans doute possible d'exagérer la distance (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wisdom and Dilman on the scope of reason in religion.Kai Nielsen - 1980 - Philosophical Investigations 3 (4):1-14.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Some Grammatical States.J. F. M. Hunter - 1977 - Philosophy 52 (200):155 - 166.
  • Wittgenstein on Inner Processes and Outward Criteria.John Hunter - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):805 - 817.
    Wittgenstein's dictum in 580 of Philosophical Investigations, ‘An “inner process” stands in need of outward criteria’, is one of his most frequently mentioned remarks, and is largely treated as a particularly clear and unproblematic statement, at least as Wittgenstein's sayings go. When anyone finds it unproblematic, he naturally does not say what he takes it to mean; but if it is as mystifying as I will claim, and if its meaning is as well concealed as I will suggest, it is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein on Language Games.J. F. M. Hunter - 1980 - Philosophy 55:293.
    In reading Wittgenstein one can, and for the most part perhaps should, treat the expression ‘language-game’ as a term of art, a more or less arbitrarily chosen item of terminology meaning something like ‘an actual or possible way of using words’. It would then be a fairly routine task to work out answers to such questions as what features of the ways a word is used are emphasized by this term of art, what philosophical purposes are served by the description (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and Knowing the Meaning of a Word.J. F. M. Hunter - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (2):294-304.
  • Wittgenstein and materialism.J. F. M. Hunter - 1977 - Mind 86 (344):514-531.
  • Realism, nominalism, and Wittgenstein.H. A. Nielsen - 1980 - Philosophical Investigations 3 (1):21-25.
  • Wittgenstein, Universals and Family Resemblances.Nicholas Griffin - 1974 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):635 - 651.
    Wittgenstein expounds his notion of a family resemblance in two important passages. The first is from The Blue Book:This craving for generality is the resultant of a number of tendencies connected with particular philosophical confusions. There is— The tendency to look for something common to entities which we commonly subsume under a general term. We are inclined to think that there must be something common to all games, say, and that this common property is the justification for applying the general (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on religious utterances.Wayne Grennan - 1976 - Sophia 15 (3):13-18.
    In "lectures and conversations" wittgenstein suggests that there is an "enormous gulf" between religious believers and non-believers, when the latter wish to dispute religious claims. d z phillips and others have interpreted his remarks as implying that non-believers cannot disagree with believers because different language-games are being played. i try to show that for wittgenstein the gulf exists for a different reason: non-believers take religious utterances as being truth claims, but they are not. they are really vehicles for conveying feelings (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant’s Constitutive-Regulative Distinction.Stanley G. French - 1967 - The Monist 51 (4):623-639.
    My purposes in this paper are to explain the constitutive-regulative distinction as set out by Kant in the Dialectic and Methodology, and to note its reappearance in contemporary philosophy.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Behaviorism and perception.George Englebretsen - 1974 - Man and World 7 (2):149-157.
  • Two Types of Scepticism.Douglas Odegard - 1979 - Philosophy 54 (210):459 - 472.
    Suppose that a jury in a murder trial brings in a verdict of guilty and one of the jurors still wonders whether the verdict is a good one, although he is not inclined to try to have it reversed. Is his attitude coherent?
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tractatus objects.John V. Canfield - 1976 - Philosophia 6 (1):81-99.
  • Criteria and method.John V. Canfield - 1974 - Metaphilosophy 5 (4):298–315.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Criteria and rules of language.John V. Canfield - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (1):70-87.
  • Anthropological Science Fiction and Logical Necessity.John V. Canfield - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (3):467 - 479.
    What is the source of the hardness of the logical must? What does the necessity of mathematical and logical inference consist in? If I am plotting the curve y = x2 and assume that x = 2 I must conclude that y = 4; no other consequence can be drawn. What is the nature of this ‘must'?Understanding Wittgenstein's answer to this question is essential to understanding his later philosophy. The question of the nature of logical or mathematical necessity is as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • "Showing" in the Tractatus : the Root of Wittgenstein and Russell's Basic Incompatibility.I. Block - 2014 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 17:4.
  • Wittgenstein: Philosophy and Grammar.Ralph H. Johnson - 1970 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 44:99.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Popper and rationality a Wittgensteinian critique.William Burns Hutchinson - unknown
    Source: Masterss International, Volume: 40-07, page:. Thesis --University of Windsor, 1981.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • "A Model" Tractatus "Language".John V. Canfield - 1972 - Philosophical Forum 4 (2):199.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophy as Therapy: An Examination of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Method.Judith Ann Rochester - 1978 - Dissertation, University of Toronto (Canada)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paradigms: The Later Wittgenstein's View of Meaning.Christine M. Koggel - 1981 - Dissertation, Carleton University (Canada)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A note on Wittgenstein as an unwilling nominalist.F. F. Centore - 1973 - The Thomist 37 (4):762-767.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation