Switch to: Citations

References in:

Paradox by (non-wellfounded) definition

Analysis 65 (4):275–278 (2005)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Paradox without Self-Reference.Stephen Yablo - 1993 - Analysis 53 (4):251-252.
  • Yablo's paradox and Kindred infinite liars.Roy A. Sorensen - 1998 - Mind 107 (425):137-155.
    This is a defense and extension of Stephen Yablo's claim that self-reference is completely inessential to the liar paradox. An infinite sequence of sentences of the form 'None of these subsequent sentences are true' generates the same instability in assigning truth values. I argue Yablo's technique of substituting infinity for self-reference applies to all so-called 'self-referential' paradoxes. A representative sample is provided which includes counterparts of the preface paradox, Pseudo-Scotus's validity paradox, the Knower, and other enigmas of the genre. I (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Yablo’s paradox.Graham Priest - 1997 - Analysis 57 (4):236–242.
  • Theories of truth which have no standard models.Hannes Leitgeb - 2001 - Studia Logica 68 (1):69-87.
    This papers deals with the class of axiomatic theories of truth for semantically closed languages, where the theories do not allow for standard models; i.e., those theories cannot be interpreted as referring to the natural number codes of sentences only (for an overview of axiomatic theories of truth in general, see Halbach[6]). We are going to give new proofs for two well-known results in this area, and we also prove a new theorem on the nonstandardness of a certain theory of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Is Yablo's Paradox Liar-Like?James Hardy - 1995 - Analysis 55 (3):197 - 198.
  • Patterns of paradox.Roy T. Cook - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):767-774.
    We begin with a prepositional languageLpcontaining conjunction (Λ), a class of sentence names {Sα}αϵA, and a falsity predicateF. We (only) allow unrestricted infinite conjunctions, i.e., given any non-empty class of sentence names {Sβ}βϵB,is a well-formed formula (we will useWFFto denote the set of well-formed formulae).The language, as it stands, is unproblematic. Whether various paradoxes are produced depends on which names are assigned to which sentences. What is needed is a denotation function:For example, theLPsentence “F(S1)” (i.e.,Λ{F(S1)}), combined with a denotation functionδsuch (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Yablo's paradox and referring to infinite objects.O. Bueno & M. Colyvan - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (3):402 – 412.
    The blame for the semantic and set-theoretic paradoxes is often placed on self-reference and circularity. Some years ago, Yablo [1985; 1993] challenged this diagnosis, by producing a paradox that's liar-like but does not seem to involve circularity. But is Yablo's paradox really non-circular? In a recent paper, Beall [2001] has suggested that there are no means available to refer to Yablo's paradox without invoking descriptions, and since Priest [1997] has shown that any such description is circular, Beall concludes that Yablo's (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Is yablo’s paradox non-circular?J. Beall - 2001 - Analysis 61 (3):176–87.
  • What is a self-referential sentence? Critical remarks on the alleged mbox(non-)circularity of Yablo's paradox.Hannes Leitgeb - 2002 - Logique and Analyse 177 (178):3-14.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations