Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Can Atheism Be Epistemically Responsible When So Many People Believe in God?Sébasten Réhault - 2015 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 7 (1):181--198.
    Nowadays the argument for the existence of God based on the common consent of mankind is taken to be so bad that contemporary atheists do not even bother to mention it. And it seems very few theists think that the argument is worth defending. In this paper I shall argue to the contrary: not only is the argument better than usually thought, but widespread belief in God constitutes a prima facie defeater for every reasonable atheist.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • "From the Unity of the World to God: A Teleo-Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence".Paulo Juarez - 2017 - Scientia et Fides 5 (2):283-303.
    In this paper I pursue an avenue of argument implicit in Patristic thinkers — such as Tertullian and Athanasius — and explicit in the thomistic and scholastic tradition. I argue that there is an ontological unity to the world, and that this unity calls for an explanation in terms of a transcendent cause, traditionally identified with God.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Realist Conception of Truth.[author unknown] - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (189):512-518.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Theological realism, divine action, and divine location.Andrei A. Buckareff - 2016 - In Andrei A. Buckareff & Yujin Nagasawa (eds.), Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The ontological argument and the motivational centres of lives.Alexander R. Pruss - 2010 - Religious Studies 46 (2):233-249.
    Assuming S₅, the main controversial premise in modal ontological arguments is the possibility premise, such as that possibly a maximally great being exists. I shall offer a new way of arguing that the possibility premise is probably true.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The ontological argument and the motivational centres of lives: ALEXANDER R. PRUSS.Alexander R. Pruss - 2010 - Religious Studies 46 (2):233-249.
    Assuming S5, the main controversial premise in modal ontological arguments is the possibility premise, such as that possibly a maximally great being exists. I shall offer a new way of arguing that the possibility premise is probably true.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Does God Exist Because He Ought To Exist?William F. Vallicella - 2018 - In Mirosław Szatkowski (ed.), Ontology of Theistic Beliefs: Meta-Ontological Perspectives. De Gruyter. pp. 205-212.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Existence of God.Richard Swinburne - 1979 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Substantially re-written and updated, this edition of 'The Existence of God' presents arguments such as the existence of the laws of nature, 'fine-tuning' of the universe, moral awareness and evidence of miracles, to prove the case that there is a God.
    No categories
  • Perceiving God through Natural Beauty.Ryan West & Adam C. Pelser - 2015 - Faith and Philosophy 32 (3):293-312.
    In Perceiving God, William Alston briefly suggests the possibility of perceiving God indirectly through the perception of another object. Following recent work by C. Stephen Evans, we argue that Thomas Reid’s notion of “natural signs” helpfully illuminates how people can perceive God indirectly through natural beauty. First, we explain how some natural signs enable what Alston labels “indirect perception.” Second, we explore how certain emotions make it possible to see both beauty and the excellence of the minds behind beauty. Finally, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Value and Existence.William J. Wainwright - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (2):318.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • From facts to God: An onto-cosmological argument. [REVIEW]William F. Vallicella - 2000 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 48 (3):157-181.
  • Relations between universals,or divine laws?Richard Swinburne - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (2):179 – 189.
    Armstrong's theory of laws of nature as relations between universals gives an initially plausible account of why the causal powers of substances are bound together only in certain ways, so that the world is a very regular place. But its resulting theory of causation cannot account for intentional causation, since this involves an agent trying to do something, and trying is causing. This kind of causation is thus a state of an agent and does not involve the operation of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Conceptualist Argument for God's Existence.Quentin Smith - 1994 - Faith and Philosophy 11 (1):38-49.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Modal-Epistemic Argument for the Existence of God.Emanuel Rutten - 2014 - Faith and Philosophy 31 (4):386-400.
    I propose a new argument for the existence of God. God is defined as a conscious being that is the first cause of reality. In its simplified initial form, the argument has two premises: all possible truths are knowable, and it is impossible to know that the proposition that God does not exist is true. From and it follows that the proposition that God exists is necessarily true. After introducing the argument in its crude initial form and laying out the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Riddle of Existence: An Essay in Idealistic Metaphysics. Nicholas Rescher.John Leslie - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (3):485-486.
  • The Argument from Reason.Victor Reppert - 1999 - Philo 2 (1):33-45.
    In this paper I argue that the existence of human reason gives us good reason to suppose that God exists. If the world were as the materialist supposes it is, then we would not be able to reason to the conclusion that this is so. This contention is often challenged by the claim that mental and physical explanations can be given for the same event. But a close examination of the question of explanatory compatibility reveals that the sort of explanation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Argument from Reason.Victor Reppert - 2009 - In William Lane Craig & J. P. Moreland (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 344–390.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction The Nature of the Argument The History of the Argument Subdividing the Argument Five Popular Objections References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Theism and epistemic truth-equivalences.Michael C. Rea - 2000 - Noûs 34 (2):291–301.
    This paper defends the conclusion that every epistemic truth equivalence entails "near theism"--the view that (i) there exists a necessarily existent rational community and (ii) necessarily, there exists an omnisicent community.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • How to be an Anti-Realist.Alvin Plantinga - 1982 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 56 (1):47 - 70.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • No God, No Powers.James Orr - 2019 - International Philosophical Quarterly 59 (4):411-426.
    One common feature of debates about the best metaphysical analysis of putatively lawful phenomena is the suspicion that nomic realists who locate the modal force of such phenomena in quasi-causal necessitation relations between universals are working with a model of law that cannot convincingly erase its theological pedigree. Nancy Cartwright distills this criticism into slogan form: no God, no laws. Some have argued that a more plausible alternative for nomic realists who reject theism is to ground laws of nature in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Argument from Consciousness.J. P. Moreland - 2009 - In William Lane Craig & J. P. Moreland (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 282–343.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Section One: The Backdrop for Locating Consciousness in a Naturalist Ontology Section Two: The AC Section Three: John Searle and Contingent Correlation Section Four: Timothy O'Connor and Emergent Necessitation Section Five: Colin McGinn and Mysterian “Naturalism” Conclusion Further Reading References.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Consensus Gentium Argument.Loren Meierding - 1998 - Faith and Philosophy 15 (3):271-297.
    In antiquity the consensus gentium argument for God’s existence was believed to have merit (cf. Cicero, De Natura Deorum, Book II, sect.2,4), but has been considered blatantly fallacious during more recent times. In this article Bayes’ Theorem is applied to show that the argument is in fact a valid inductive argument. A two hypothesis and a four hypothesis version of the argument are analyzed. Perusal of available statistical evidence suggests that when better worldwide opinion polling data becomes available it will (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • By Whose Authority: A Political Argument for God's Existence.Tyler McNabb & Jeremy Neill - 2019 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 11 (2):163-189.
    In The Problem of Political Authority, Michael Huemer argues that the contractarian and consequentialist groundings of political authority are unsuccessful, and, in fact, that there are no adequate contemporary accounts of political authority. As such, the modern state is illegitimate and we have reasons to affirm political anarchism. We disagree with Huemer’s conclusion. But we consider Huemer’s critiques of contractarianism and consequentialism to be compelling. Here we will juxtapose, alongside Huemer’s critiques, a theistic account of political authority from Nicholas Wolterstorff’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Atheism and Theism.Hugh J. McCann, J. J. C. Smart & J. J. Haldane - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (3):462.
    In this volume, the sixth in Blackwell's Great Debates in Philosophy series, Smart and Haldane discuss the case for and against religious belief. The debate is unusual in beginning with the negative side. After a short jointly authored introduction, there is a fairly extended presentation of the atheist position by Smart. Haldane then offers an equally extended defense of theism. The authors respond to one another in the same order, and the book concludes with a brief co-authored treatment of antirealism, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On arguing for the existence of god as a synthesis between realism and anti-realism.W. J. Mander - 2013 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 (1):99-115.
    This article examines a somewhat neglected argument for the existence of God which appeals to the divine perspective as a way of reconciling the conflicting claims of realism and anti-realism. Six representative examples are set out (Berkeley, Ferrier, T. H. Green, Josiah Royce, Gordon Clark and Michael Dummett), reasons are considered why this argument has received less attention than it might, and a brief sketch given of the most promising way in which it might be developed.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Naturalism, Theism, and Objects of Reason.E. J. Lowe - 2013 - Philosophia Christi 15 (1):35-45.
    It is argued that the dispute between philosophical naturalism and theism can, ultimately, only be rationally resolved in favor of theism, owing to certain internal inadequacies of philosophical naturalism that are commonly overlooked by both its friends and its foes. The criticisms of philosophical naturalism focus on certain questions concerning the ontological status of the objects of human reason and probe into the nature of human rationality and the conditions of its possibility. There is an implicit challenge to mainstream philosophical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Argument from Wholes.John Kronen & Sandra Menssen - 2013 - Faith and Philosophy 30 (2):138-158.
    All wholes are made by an intelligent agent; some wholes were not made by an embodied agent; so, some things made by an intelligent agent were not made by an embodied agent. Such was the basic argument for God’s existence defended by Udayana, the greatest of the Nyāya-Vaiśeika philosophers, in his Kiraṇāvalī. Our paper explicates this argument and highlights its merits.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A deontic argument for God's existence.Carl R. Kordig - 1981 - Noûs 15 (2):207-208.
  • Breaking Laws of Nature.Jeffrey Koperski - 2017 - Philosophia Christi 19 (1):83-101.
    One of the main arguments against interventionist views of special divine action is that God would not violate his own laws. But if intervention entails the breaking of natural law, what precisely is being broken? While the nature of the laws of nature has been widely explored by philosophers of science, important distinctions are often ignored in the science and religion literature. In this paper, I consider the three main approaches to laws: Humean anti-realism, supervenience on more fundamental aspects of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against Naturalized Cognitive Propositions.Lorraine Juliano Keller - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (4):929-946.
    In this paper, I argue that Scott Soames’ theory of naturalized cognitive propositions faces a serious objection: there are true propositions for which NCP cannot account. More carefully, NCP cannot account for certain truths of mathematics unless it is possible for there to be an infinite intellect. For those who reject the possibility of an infinite intellect, this constitutes a reductio of NCP.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Philosophical Theology.Rufus M. Jones & F. R. Tennant - 1930 - Philosophical Review 39 (1):96.
  • The Argument from Desire.Robert Holyer - 1988 - Faith and Philosophy 5 (1):61-71.
    In this essay I offer a reformulation and defense of the argument from desire as it is presented in the works of C. S. Lewis. Specifically, I try to answer the criticisms of the argument made by John Beversluis in his recent book C. S. Lewis and the Search for Rational Religion. However, my concern is not so much Lewis as it is the argument itself, which I argue is worthy of serious and more extended philosophical treatment.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What Is Naturalism? And Should We Be Naturalists?William Hasker - 2013 - Philosophia Christi 15 (1):21-34.
    It seems reasonable to seek a definition of naturalism, yet an accurate general definition proves to be elusive. After considering proposals from Quine, Nagel, and Chalmers, I propose that naturalism as understood by the majority of contemporary naturalists is best defined by the conjunction of mind-body supervenience, an understanding of the physical as mechanistic, and the causal closure of the physical domain. I then argue that naturalism so defined is in principle unable to account for the existence of rationality; it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Atheism and Theism.J. J. Haldane - 2003 - In J. J. C. Smart & J. J. Haldane (eds.), Atheism and Theism. Malden, MA, USA: Blackwell. pp. 76–150.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introduction Theism and Science Some Varieties of Explanation ‘Old’ Teleology ‘New’ Teleology The Cause of Things God and the World God, Good and Evil Liberty and Providence Theism — Philosophical and Religious.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Argument from Reason.Stewart Goetz - 2013 - Philosophia Christi 15 (1):47-62.
    This article attempts to clarify an “argument from reason” set forth by C. S. Lewis in his Miracles. While there are various contemporary interpretations of the argument, Lewis intended to expose the “cardinal difficulty of naturalism.” First, this article seeks to clarify both Lewis’s argument and the understanding of naturalism that it presupposes. Second, philosophers of religion—especially, William Hasker and Alvin Plantinga—have significantly contributed to the argument’s contemporary discussion, and so their views are addressed with the intent to show how (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Regularities, Laws of Nature, and the Existence of God.John Foster - 2001 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 101 (1):145-161.
  • Regulatities, laws of nature, and the existance of God.John Foster - 2001 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 101 (2):145–161.
    The regularities in nature, simply by being regularities, call for explanation. There are only two ways in which we could, with any plausibility, try to explain them. One way would be to suppose that they are imposed on the world by God. The other would be to suppose that they reflect the presence of laws of nature, conceived of as forms of natural necessity. But the only way of making sense of the notion of a law of nature, thus conceived, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Peter Forrest, God without the Supernatural: A Defense of Scientific Theism. [REVIEW]Edward L. Schoen - 1998 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 43 (2):130-132.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Two ‘Proofs’ of God's Existence: A. C. EWING.A. C. Ewing - 1965 - Religious Studies 1 (1):29-45.
    I do not think that the existence of God can be proved or even that the main justification for the belief can be found in argument in the ordinary sense of that term, but I think two of the three which have, since Kant at least, been classified as the traditional arguments of natural theology have some force and are worthy of serious consideration. This consideration I shall now proceed to give. I cannot say this of the remaining one of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is the fact that other people believe in God a reason to believe? Remarks on the consensus gentium argument.Marek Dobrzeniecki - 2018 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (3):133-153.
    According to The Consensus Gentium Argument from the premise: “Everyone believes that God exists” one can conclude that God does exist. In my paper I analyze two ways of defending the claim that somebody’s belief in God is a prima facie reason to believe. Kelly takes the fact of the commonness of the belief in God as a datum to explain and argues that the best explanation has to indicate the truthfulness of the theistic belief. Trinkaus Zagzebski grounds her defence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • God and Modal Concretism.Richard Davis - 2008 - Philosophia Christi 10 (1):57-74.
    According to David Lewis, we all believe there are countless ways in which things might have been different from the way they are in fact. Surely, for example, the world could have existed even if, say, Quine had been a politician, or if there had been one less page in Word and Object, or indeed if there had been no such person as Quine at all. All these things, we are inclined to think, might have been the case. And thus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • God and the Platonic Horde.Richard Davis - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (2):289-303.
    In this paper I shall argue two things. First, it is plausible to think that Conceptualism holds with respect to propositions; in any event, it does a much better job than its closest competitors (Platonism and Nominalism) in accounting for the truthbearing nature of propositions. Secondly, it is wholly implausible (so I say) to take the added step and equate properties and relations with divine concepts. Here I offer additional reasons, beyond “divine bootstrapping,” for theists to resist this tempting reduction. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Omnificence.J. Bigelow - 2005 - Analysis 65 (3):187-196.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Should CSR Give Atheists Epistemic Assurance? On Beer-Goggles, BFFs, and Skepticism Regarding Religious Beliefs.Justin L. Barrett & Ian M. Church - 2013 - The Monist 96 (3):311-324.
    Recent work in cognitive science of religion (CSR) is beginning to converge on a very interesting thesis—that, given the ordinary features of human minds operating in typical human environments, we are naturally disposed to believe in the existence of gods, among other religious ideas (e.g., seeAtran [2002], Barrett [2004; 2012], Bering [2011], Boyer [2001], Guthrie [1993], McCauley [2011], Pyysiäinen [2004; 2009]). In this paper, we explore whether such a discovery ultimately helps or hurts the atheist position—whether, for example, it lends (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Lord of Noncontradiction: An Argument for God from Logic.James N. Anderson & Greg Welty - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (2):321 - 338.
    In this paper we offer a new argument for the existence of God. We contend that the laws of logic are metaphysically dependent on the existence of God, understood as a necessarily existent, personal, spiritual being; thus anyone who grants that there are laws of logic should also accept that there is a God. We argue that if our most natural intuitions about them are correct, and if they are to play the role in our intellectual activities that we take (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Review of Robert Merrihew Adams: The virtue of faith and other essays in philosophical theology[REVIEW]Kenneth Seeskin - 1988 - Ethics 99 (1):184-185.
  • Divine necessity.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy 80 (11):741-752.
  • The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem.Mark Steiner - 2000 - Mind 109 (434):390-394.
  • Philosophical Explanations. [REVIEW]Robert Nozick - 1981 - Ethics 94 (2):326-327.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   704 citations  
  • In defence of scientism.Don Ross, James Ladyman & David Spurrett - 2007 - In James Ladyman (ed.), Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford University Press.