Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Gesammelte Schriften. Kant - 1912 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 73:105-106.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   215 citations  
  • Freedom immediately after Kant.Owen Ware - 2019 - European Journal of Philosophy 27 (4):865-881.
    Kant’s effort to defend the co-existence of transcendental freedom and natural necessity is one of the crowning achievements of the first Critique. Yet by identifying the will with practical reason in his moral philosophy, he lent support to the view that the moral law is the causal law of a free will – the result of which, as Reinhold argued, left immoral action impossible. However, Reinhold’s attempt to separate the will from practical reason generated difficulties of its own, which Maimon (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Apostate Rationalism and Maimon’s Hume.Peter Thielke - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (4):pp. 591-618.
    The paper examines the way in which Salomon Maimon (1753-1800) combines Humean skepticism and Leibnizian rationalism to mount an innovative challenge to Kant. Maimon’s position can be described as an “apostate rationalism,” which holds that reason makes unavoidable demands on us that are nonetheless not satisfied in experience. An appreciation of Maimon’s arguments also sheds new and interesting light on the surprising role that this apostate rationalism plays as a component of Hume’s skeptical naturalism.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Salomon Maimon’s Attempt at a New Presentation of the Principle of Morality and a New Deduction of Its Reality.Timothy Sean Quinn - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (1):155-182.
    ABSTRACTThis essay is a translation of one of Salomon Maimon’s ethical writings, accompanied by a brief introduction. In it, Maimon proposes a correction of the Kantian moral principle of duty, as it is articulated both by Kant’s Groundwork for a Metaphysics of Morals and his Critique of Practical Reason. In particular, Maimon’s essay reveals the influence of Reinhold’s critique of Kant’s moral philosophy, especially regarding the role of incentives behind moral action. It reveals as well Maimon’s commitment to the primacy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Salomon Maimon’s Attempt at a New Presentation of the Principle of Morality and a New Deduction of Its Reality.Timothy Sean Quinn - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (1):155-182.
    This essay is a translation of one of Salomon Maimon’s ethical writings, accompanied by a brief introduction. In it, Maimon proposes a correction of the Kantian moral principle of duty, as it is articulated both by Kant’s Groundwork for a Metaphysics of Morals and his Critique of Practical Reason. In particular, Maimon’s essay reveals the influence of Reinhold’s critique of Kant’s moral philosophy, especially regarding the role of incentives behind moral action. It reveals as well Maimon’s commitment to the primacy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Common Possession of the Earth and Cosmopolitan Right.Alice Pinheiro Walla - 2016 - Kant Studien 107 (1):160-178.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Kant-Studien Jahrgang: 107 Heft: 1 Seiten: 160-178.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Maimon’s ‘Law of Determinability’ and the Impossibility of Shared Attributes.Yitzhak Melamed - 2021 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 109 (1):49-62.
    Apart from his critique of Kant, Maimon’s significance for the history of philosophy lies in his crucial role in the rediscovery of Spinoza by the German Idealists. Specifically, Maimon initiated a change from the common eighteenth-century view of Spinoza as the great ‘atheist’ to the view of Spinoza as an ‘acosmist’, i.e., a thinker who propounded a deep, though unorthodox, religious view denying the reality of the world and taking God to be the only real being. I have discussed this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wahlverwandtschaften zwischen Fichtes, Maimons und Erhards Rechtslehren.Faustino Oncina Coves - 1997 - Fichte-Studien 11:63-84.
    Schiller kam im Jahre 1789 als Professor nach Jena und erregte mit seiner Antrittsvorlesung an der Universität Aufsehen. Darin stellt er den »Brotgelehrten«, der nur einen bequemen und gutbesoldeten Posten beansprucht, dem »philosophischen Kopf« gegenüber, der keine Mühe um der Wahrheit willen scheut. Brotgelehrte waren Erhard und Maimon mit Sicherheit nicht. Der eine war Jakobiner und Arzt, der andere jüdischer Autodidakt und unermüdlicher Wahrheitspilger. Gerade Fichte war derjenige, der aus den beiden Außenseitern Mitstreiter gemacht und ihnen den Rang philosophischer Köpfe (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Ethics of Salomon Maimon.David Baumgardt - 1963 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 1 (2):199-210.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Ethics of Salomon Maimon (1753-1800) DAVID BAUMGARDT* SALOMON MAIMON is now generally considered the most acute mind among the earliest critics of Kant. Kant himself had praised his acumen,1 though later qualifying his regard decisively.2 Johann Gottfried Herder called * We have just learned of the death of the author. David Baumgardt, born in Germany on April 20, 1890, studied in Vienna and in Berlin and taught philosophy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals.Immanuel Kant - 1785/2002 - In Practical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 37-108.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   798 citations  
  • The Metaphysics of Natural Right in Spinoza.John R. T. Grey - 2021 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 10:37-60.
    In the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus (TTP), Spinoza argues that an individual’s natural right extends as far as their power. Subsequently, in the Tractatus Politicus (TP), he offers a revised argument for the same conclusion. Here I offer an account of the reasons for the revision. In both arguments, an individual’s natural right derives from God’s natural right. However, the TTP argument hinges on the claim that each individual is part of the whole of nature (totius naturae), and for this reason inherits (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Common Possession of the Earth and Cosmopolitan Right.Alice Pinheiro Walla - 2018 - Las Torres de Lucca. International Journal of Political Philosophy 7 (13):255-276.
    La posesión común de la tierra fue una idea prominente en la filosofía moderna del siglo xvii. En este artículo, sostendré que Kant no sólo propuso una versión secular de la posesión común de la tierra, sino que también se diferenció de forma radical de la concepción iusnaturalista de sus predecesores. Propongo que la revisión kantiana del derecho cosmopolita se dirige al mismo problema que el derecho de necesidad de Grocio, a saber, la implausibilidad de asumir derechos adquiridos absolutos cuando (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Salomon Maimon.Yitzhak Y. Melamed & Peter Thielke - 2015