Switch to: Citations

References in:

Limits of thought and Husserl's phenomenology

Dissertation, Mcgill University (2011)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Nothing.P. L. Heath - 1967 - In Paul Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of philosophy. New York,: Macmillan. pp. 5--524.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Why Is There Anything At All?Peter van Inwagen & E. J. Lowe - 1996 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 70 (Supplementary):95-120.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Relativism, Truth and the Symmetry Thesis.William F. Vallicella - 1984 - The Monist 67 (3):452-466.
    The interest and longevity of philosophical positions and arguments often seem to be an inverse function of the clarity with which these positions and arguments are articulated. Frequently, the most interesting positions are those pregnant with ambiguity and ever teetering on the brink of incoherence. Examples are not hard to find in the history of philosophy. Kant’s philosophy is full of them: the role and status of the Ding an sich; the proof-structure of the transcendental deduction of the categories; the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intentional Analysis and the Noema.Robert Sokolowski - 1984 - Dialectica 38 (2, 3):113-129.
  • Immanent constitution in Husserl's lectures on time.Robert Sokolowski - 1964 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 24 (4):530-551.
    In this essay, we will discuss what Husserl mean when he says that immanent objects are “constituted” by inner temporality. Our discussion will amount to a study of how sensations and intentions come to be in out subjectivity, and how we are conscious of them; Husserl’s opinion on these points will be taken from his Lectures on the Phenomenology of Inner Time Consciousness.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Relativism, truth, and incoherence.Harvey Siegel - 1986 - Synthese 68 (2):225-259.
    There are many contemporary sources and defenders of epistemological relativism which have not been considered thus far. I have, for example, barely touched on the voluminous literature regarding frameworks, conceptual schemes, and Wittgensteinian forms of life. Davidson's challenge to the scheme/content distinction and thereby to conceptual relativism, Rorty's acceptance of the Davidsonian argument and his use of it to defend a relativistic position, Winchian and other sociological and anthropological arguments for relativism, recent work in the sociology of science, and Goodman's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Two concepts of psychologism.G. L. Pandit - 1971 - Philosophical Studies 22 (5-6):85 - 91.
  • Logic Without Ontology.Ernest Nagel - 1944 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 10 (1):16-18.
  • Concepts of Relative Truth.Jack W. Meiland - 1977 - The Monist 60 (4):568-582.
    It is sometimes said that our age is an age of relativism. For example, Paul Tillich has expressed his “uneasiness about the victory of relativism in all realms of thought and life today.” Karl Popper tells us that “the main philosophical malady of our time is an intellectual and moral relativism, the latter being at least in part based on the former.” What Popper refers to as “intellectual relativism” consists in part in a doctrine about truth which is sometimes expressed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • What Does Protention "Protend"?Dieter Lohmar - 2002 - Philosophy Today 46 (Supplement):154-167.
  • Husserl's sense of wonder.Mark Kingwell - 2000 - Philosophical Forum 31 (1):85–107.
  • Intentionality in general.Robert Jordan - 1974 - Research in Phenomenology 4 (1):7-12.
  • Boole and mill: differing perspectives on logical psychologism.John Richards - 1980 - History and Philosophy of Logic 1 (1-2):19-36.
    Logical psychologism is the position that logic is a special branch of psychology, that logical laws are descriptíons of experience to be arrived at through observation, and are a posteriori.The accepted arguments against logical psychologism are effective only when directed against this extreme version. However, the clauses in the above characterization are independent and ambiguous, and may be considered separately. This separation permits a reconsideration of less extreme attempts to tie logic to psychology, such as those defended by Mill and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Wonder, Time, and Idealization.Klaus Held - 2005 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (2):185-196.
    Following Heidegger’s lead, I first undertake a description of philosophical wonder. A second task emerges out of this, the task of describing the manner of experiencing time upon which this wonder is based. Here I attend specifically to Plato’s discussion thereof. In the third and final section of my considerations, I illustrate how “idealization” follows from wonder and the accordant experience of time, “idealization” being that mental operation which, according to Husserl, has determined the consequent development of European culture in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bergson's Analysis of the Concept of Nothing.Richard M. Gale - 1974 - Modern Schoolman 51 (4):269-300.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Husserl's notion of noema.Dagfinn Føllesdal - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (20):680-687.
    Darstellung des Noema in 12 Thesen.\nverwendete Textstellen: Ideen 1: S. 203, 22-23; S. 204, 20-21; S. 357, 19-20: Handlungen sind zielgerichtet. Dabei bedarf eines keines physischen Objekts. Husserl setzt and diese Stelle das Noema. Somit wird auch zielgerichtetes Handeln aufgrund einer Halluzination m{ö}glich, Zielgerichtet zu sein bedeutet ein Noema zu haben.\n1. Follesdal´sche These: Noema ist eine intensionale Entit{ä}t, eine Generalisierung des Begriffs Sinn/Bedeutung.\n2. These: Das Noema hat zwei Bestandteile, a) der noematische Sinn, der allen thetischen Handlungen (erinnern, sich vorstellen usw.) (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • A phenomenology of cognitive desire.Daniel Dwyer - 2006 - Idealistic Studies 36 (1):47-60.
    In this article I articulate how phenomenology can and should appropriate the theme of Platonic cognitive erôs. Erôs has two principal meanings: sexual passion and the desire for the whole that characterizes the philosophical life; in its cognitive sense, it implies dissatisfaction with partial truth and aiming at the givenness of the whole. The kind of lived-experience in which the being-true of the world is presented to and affectively allures the knower is a phenomenological analogue to what in Plato is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Phenomenology of Cognitive Desire.Daniel Dwyer - 2006 - Idealistic Studies 36 (1):47-60.
    In this article I articulate how phenomenology can and should appropriate the theme of Platonic cognitive erôs. Erôs has two principal meanings: sexual passion and the desire for the whole that characterizes the philosophical life; in its cognitive sense, it implies dissatisfaction with partial truth and aiming at the givenness of the whole. The kind of lived-experience in which the being-true of the world is presented to and affectively allures the knower is a phenomenological analogue to what in Plato is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The emergence of an absolute consciousness in Husserl's early writings on time-consciousness.John Brough - 1972 - Man and World 5 (3):298-326.
    The collection of Edmund Husserl's sketches on time-consciousness from the years 1893-1917, edited by Rudolf Boehm and published as Volume X in the Husserliana series, affords significant new material for the study of the evolution of Husserl's thought. Specifically, the sketches suggest that in the course of analyzing the consciousness of temporal objects Husserl became convinced that a distinction must be drawn between an ultimate or absolute flow of consciousness and the immanent temporal objects or contents -- sense-data, appearances of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Realism and psychologism in 19th century logic.Richard R. Brockhaus - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (3):493-524.
  • Is the present ever present? Phenomenology and the metaphysics of presence.Rudolf Bernet & Wilson Brown - 1982 - Research in Phenomenology 12 (1):85-112.
  • Desiring to know through intuition.Rudolf Bernet - 2003 - Husserl Studies 19 (2):153-166.
    The major part of this paper is devoted to the task of showing that Husserl's account of knowledge and truth in terms of a synthesis of fulfilment falls prey neither to a form of “metaphysics of presence” nor to a “myth of interiority” or mentalism. Husserl's presentation of the desire to know, his awareness of irreducible forms of absence at the heart of the intuitive presence of the object of knowledge and his formulation of general rules concerning the possible accomplishment (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • An intentionality without subject or object?Rudolf Bernet - 1994 - Man and World 27 (3):231-255.
  • Wittgenstein.Ludwig Wittgenstein & Thomas H. Macho - 1996
  • Realism and Psychologism in 19th Century Logic.Richard R. Brockhaus - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (3):493-524.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Husserl's Phenomenological Method.Klaus Held - 2003 - In Donn Welton (ed.), The New Husserl: A Critical Reader. Indiana University Press.
  • Objektivierende und nicht-objektivierende Akte.Ullrich Melle - 1989 - In Samuel IJsseling (ed.), Husserl-Ausgabe Und Husserl-Forschung. pp. 35--49.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • What is metaphysics?Martin Heidegger - 1988 - In Existence and Being. Kampmann.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Psychologism the Philosophical Shibboleth.Dale Jacquette - 1997 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 30 (3):312 - 331.
    Psychologism is the target of vehement disapproval in much of mainstream philosophy from Kant to the present day. Yet although antipsychologistic rhetoric is adamant, there is little substantive argument against psychologism to be discovered in contemporary discussions of the problem. Many recent influential philosophical projects, moreover, including intuitionistic logic, conceptualism in the ontology of mathematics and the program to naturalize epistemology, are in different ways efforts to apply modern psychology in the service of philosophical theory. In this essay, I critically (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Relevance of Psychology to Logic.R. B. Braithwaite, Bertrade Russell & Friedrich Waismann - 1938 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 17:19-68.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The horizon of reason.Gordon Bearn - 1989 - In M. Krausz (ed.), Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation. Notre Dame University Press. pp. 205--231.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations