Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Essay Review: Sociobiology: Twenty-Five Years Later. [REVIEW]Edward O. Wilson - 1975 - Journal of the History of Biology 33 (3):577-584.
  • Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts.Noel Carroll - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):93-99.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • II—John Tasioulas.John Tasioulas - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1):237-264.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • John Tasioulas.John Tasioulas - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1):237–264.
  • Words On Play.Bernard Suits - 1977 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 4 (1):117-131.
  • Is life a game we are playing?Bernard Suits - 1967 - Ethics 77 (3):209-213.
  • Two concepts of rules.John Rawls - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (1):3-32.
  • Wittgensteinian semantics.Michael Pelczar - 2000 - Noûs 34 (4):483–516.
    Wittgenstein emphasizes two points concerning his notion of family resemblance. One is that the use of a family resemblance expression resists characterization by certain kinds of rules; the other is that due to the prevalence of family resemblance in the philosophical lexicon, philosophical inquiry must in many cases proceed differently from how it traditionally has. This paper develops an interpretation of family resemblance that seeks to do justice to these claims. I argue that what is characteristic about family resemblance expressions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism.Martha C. Nussbaum - 1992 - Political Theory 20 (2):202-246.
    It will be seen how in place of the wealth and poverty of political economy come the rich human being and rich human need. The rich human being is simultaneously the human being in need of totality of human life-activities — the man in whom his own realization exists as an inner necessity, as need. Marx, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844 Svetaketu abstained from food for fifteen days. Then he came to his father and said, `What shall I say?' (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Philosophy of games.C. Thi Nguyen - 2017 - Philosophy Compass 12 (8):e12426.
    What is a game? What are we doing when we play a game? What is the value of playing games? Several different philosophical subdisciplines have attempted to answer these questions using very distinctive frameworks. Some have approached games as something like a text, deploying theoretical frameworks from the study of narrative, fiction, and rhetoric to interrogate games for their representational content. Others have approached games as artworks and asked questions about the authorship of games, about the ontology of the work (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Game Game.Mary Midgley - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (189):231 - 253.
    Some time ago, an Innocent Bystander, after glancing through a copy of Mind , asked me, ‘Why do philosophers talk so much about Games? Do they play them a lot or something?’.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Scorekeeping in a pornographic language game.Rae Langton & Caroline West - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (3):303 – 319.
    If, as many suppose, pornography changes people, a question arises as to how.1 One answer to this question offers a grand and noble vision. Inspired by the idea that pornography is speech, and inspired by a certain liberal ideal about the point of speech in political life, some theorists say that pornography contributes to that liberal ideal: pornography, even at its most violent and misogynistic, and even at its most harmful, is political speech that aims to express certain views about (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Game-Playing Without Rule-Following.A. J. Kreider - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 38 (1):55-73.
  • The Grasshopper’s Error: Or, On How Life is a Game.Avery Kolers - 2015 - Dialogue 54 (4):727-746.
    I here defend the thesis that the best life is the life that one plays as a game—specifically, a ‘Suitsian’ game that meets the definition proposed in The Grasshopper by Bernard Suits. Even more specifically, it is a nested, open, role-playing game where the life’s quality as a game partly depends on there being no more people than players. To defend this thesis I refute two powerful challenges to it, one from Thomas Hurka (2006) and another from within The Grasshopper (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Games and the good.Thomas Hurka - 2006 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1):217-235.
    Using Bernard Suits’s brilliant analysis (contra Wittgenstein) of playing a game, this paper examines the intrinsic value of game-playing. It argues that two elements in Suits’s analysis make success in games difficult, which is one ground of value, while a third involves choosing a good activity for the property that makes it good, which is a further ground. The paper concludes by arguing that game-playing is the paradigm modern (Marx, Nietzsche) as against classical (Aristotle) value: since its goal is intrinsically (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Family resemblances and criteria.Heather J. Gert - 1995 - Synthese 105 (2):177-190.
    In §66 ofPhilosophical Investigations Wittgenstein looks for something common to various games and finds only an interconnecting network of resemblances. These are family resemblances. Sympathetic as well as unsympathetic readers have interpreted him as claiming that games form a family in virtue of these resemblances. This assumes Wittgenstein inverted the relation between being a member of a family and bearing family resemblances to others of that family. (The Churchills bear family resemblances to one another because they belong to the same (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Good and Evil.Peter Geach - 1956 - Analysis 17 (2):33 - 42.
  • Natural Law and Natural Rights.Richard Tuck - 1981 - Philosophical Quarterly 31 (124):282-284.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • The Ethos of Games.Fred D'Agostino - 1981 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 8 (1):7-18.
  • "Work" and "play".Richard Burke - 1971 - Ethics 82 (1):33-47.
  • Scorekeeping in a Language Game.David Lewis - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (3):339.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   622 citations  
  • Mimesis as Make-Believe.Kendall L. Walton - 1996 - Synthese 109 (3):413-434.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   402 citations  
  • Sociobiology.Edward O. Wilson - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (2):305-306.
  • Play and the Theory of Basic Human Goods.Anthony J. Celano - 1991 - American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (2):137 - 146.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation