Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1691 citations  
  • Computing machinery and intelligence.Alan M. Turing - 1950 - Mind 59 (October):433-60.
    I propose to consider the question, "Can machines think?" This should begin with definitions of the meaning of the terms "machine" and "think." The definitions might be framed so as to reflect so far as possible the normal use of the words, but this attitude is dangerous, If the meaning of the words "machine" and "think" are to be found by examining how they are commonly used it is difficult to escape the conclusion that the meaning and the answer to (...)
    Direct download (18 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   999 citations  
  • Minds, Machines, and Gödel: A Retrospect.J. R. Lucas - 1996 - In Raffaela Giovagnoli (ed.), Etica E Politica. Clarendon Press. pp. 1.
    In this paper Lucas comes back to Gödelian argument against Mecanism to clarify some points. First of all, he explains his use of Gödel’s theorem instead of Turing’s theorem, showing how Gödel’ theorem, but not Turing’s theorem, raises questions concerning truth and reasoning that bear on the nature of mind and how Turing’s theorem suggests that there is something that cannot be done by any computers but not that it can be done by human minds. He considers moreover how Gödel’s (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On the imitation game.John G. Stevenson - 1976 - Philosophia 6 (1):131-33.
  • A simple comment regarding the Turing test.Benny Shanon - 1989 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 19 (June):249-56.
  • The truly total Turing test.Paul Schweizer - 1998 - Minds and Machines 8 (2):263-272.
    The paper examines the nature of the behavioral evidence underlying attributions of intelligence in the case of human beings, and how this might be extended to other kinds of cognitive system, in the spirit of the original Turing Test. I consider Harnad's Total Turing Test, which involves successful performance of both linguistic and robotic behavior, and which is often thought to incorporate the very same range of empirical data that is available in the human case. However, I argue that the (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • In defence of Turing.Geoffrey Sampson - 1973 - Mind 82 (October):592-94.
  • Turing tests for intelligence: Ned Block's defense of psychologism. [REVIEW]Robert C. Richardson - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 41 (May):421-6.
  • Beating the imitation game.R. Purthill - 1971 - Mind 80 (April):290-94.
  • Explaining computer behavior.James H. Moor - 1978 - Philosophical Studies 34 (October):325-7.
  • An analysis of the Turing test.James H. Moor - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 30 (4):249 - 257.
  • On the point of the imitation game.P. Millar - 1973 - Mind 82 (October):595-97.
  • Constructing Societies and Social Machines: Stepping Out of the Turing Test Discourse.P. B. Mcllvenny - 1993 - Journal of Intelligent Systems 3 (2-4):119-156.
  • Can machines think?W. Mays - 1952 - Philosophy 27 (April):148-62.
    Mr. A. M. Turing was quoted in The Times about a year ago as saying it would be interesting to discover the degree of intellectual activity of which a machine was capable and to what extent it could think for itself. He has now pressed this suggestion further and given the results of his researches in an article called “Computing Machines and Intelligence,” together with a brief account of a “child-machine” which he has attempted to educate . I intend to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The right stuff.J. Christopher Maloney - 1987 - Synthese 70 (March):349-72.
  • Minds, Machines and Gödel.George S. Boolos - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (4):613-615.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Minds, Machines and Gödel.J. R. Lucas - 1961 - Etica E Politica 5 (1):1.
    In this article, Lucas maintains the falseness of Mechanism - the attempt to explain minds as machines - by means of Incompleteness Theorem of Gödel. Gödel’s theorem shows that in any system consistent and adequate for simple arithmetic there are formulae which cannot be proved in the system but that human minds can recognize as true; Lucas points out in his turn that Gödel’s theorem applies to machines because a machine is the concrete instantiation of a formal system: therefore, for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • The light bulb and the Turing-tested machine.Justin Leiber - 1992 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 22 (1):25–39.
  • Shanon on the Turing test.Justin Leiber - 1989 - Journal of Social Behavior 19 (June):257-259.
  • On Turing's Turing test and why the matter matters.Justin Leiber - 1995 - Synthese 104 (1):59-69.
  • Thinking may be more than computing.Peter Kugel - 1986 - Cognition 22 (2):137-198.
  • Reflections on the Turing test.Charles Karelis - 1986 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 16 (July):161-72.
  • A Turing test conversation.Dale Jacquette - 1993 - Philosophy 68 (264):231-33.
  • Alan Turing.Andrew Hodges - 2000 - Minds and Machines.
  • Chauvinism and science: Another reply to Shannon.Tracy B. Henley - 1990 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 20 (1):93–95.
  • Virtual symposium on virtual mind.Patrick Hayes, Stevan Harnad, Donald Perlis & Ned Block - 1992 - Minds and Machines 2 (3):217-238.
    When certain formal symbol systems (e.g., computer programs) are implemented as dynamic physical symbol systems (e.g., when they are run on a computer) their activity can be interpreted at higher levels (e.g., binary code can be interpreted as LISP, LISP code can be interpreted as English, and English can be interpreted as a meaningful conversation). These higher levels of interpretability are called "virtual" systems. If such a virtual system is interpretable as if it had a mind, is such a "virtual (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Searle's Chinese Box: Debunking the Chinese Room Argument. [REVIEW]Larry Hauser - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (2):199-226.
    John Searle's Chinese room argument is perhaps the most influential andwidely cited argument against artificial intelligence (AI). Understood astargeting AI proper – claims that computers can think or do think– Searle's argument, despite its rhetorical flash, is logically andscientifically a dud. Advertised as effective against AI proper, theargument, in its main outlines, is an ignoratio elenchi. It musterspersuasive force fallaciously by indirection fostered by equivocaldeployment of the phrase "strong AI" and reinforced by equivocation on thephrase "causal powers" (at least) equal (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reaping the whirlwind. [REVIEW]L. Hauser - 1993 - Minds and Machines 3 (2):219-237.
    Harnad 's proposed "robotic upgrade" of Turing's Test, from a test of linguistic capacity alone to a Total Turing Test of linguistic and sensorimotor capacity, conflicts with his claim that no behavioral test provides even probable warrant for attributions of thought because there is "no evidence" [p.45] of consciousness besides "private experience" [p.52]. Intuitive, scientific, and philosophical considerations Harnad offers in favor of his proposed upgrade are unconvincing. I agree with Harnad that distinguishing real from "as if" thought on the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The imitation game.Keith Gunderson - 1964 - Mind 73 (April):234-45.
  • Turing's sexual guessing game.Judith Genova - 1994 - Social Epistemology 8 (4):313 – 326.
  • Response to Anderson and Keith.Judith Genova - 1994 - Social Epistemology 8 (4):341 – 343.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Subcognition and the limits of the Turing test.Robert M. French - 1990 - Mind 99 (393):53-66.
  • Simulating convesations: The communion game. [REVIEW]Stephen J. Cowley & Karl MacDorman - 1995 - AI and Society 9 (2-3):116-137.
    In their enthusiasm for programming, computational linguists have tended to lose sight of what humansdo. They have conceived of conversations as independent of sound and the bodies that produce it. Thus, implicit in their simulations is the assumption that the text is the essence of talk. In fact, unlike electronic mail, conversations are acoustic events. During everyday talk, human understanding depends both on the words spoken and on fine interpersonal vocal coordination. When utterances are analysed into sequences of word-based forms, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The curious case of the chinese gym.B. Jack Copeland - 1993 - Synthese 95 (2):173-86.
    Searle has recently used two adaptations of his Chinese room argument in an attack on connectionism. I show that these new forms of the argument are fallacious. First I give an exposition of and rebuttal to the original Chinese room argument, and then a brief introduction to the essentials of connectionism.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Turing-like indistinguishability tests for the validation of a computer simulation of paranoid processes.Kenneth Mark Colby, Franklin Dennis Hilf, Sylvia Weber & Helena C. Kraemer - 1972 - Artificial Intelligence 3:199-221.
  • Modeling a paranoid mind.Kenneth Mark Colby - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):515-534.
  • Artificial intelligence and personal identity.David Cole - 1991 - Synthese 88 (September):399-417.
    Considerations of personal identity bear on John Searle's Chinese Room argument, and on the opposed position that a computer itself could really understand a natural language. In this paper I develop the notion of a virtual person, modelled on the concept of virtual machines familiar in computer science. I show how Searle's argument, and J. Maloney's attempt to defend it, fail. I conclude that Searle is correct in holding that no digital machine could understand language, but wrong in holding that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Turing Test as a Novel Form of Hermeneutics.Timothy Clark - 1992 - International Studies in Philosophy 24 (1):17-31.
  • Psychologism and behaviorism.Ned Block - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (1):5-43.
    Let psychologism be the doctrine that whether behavior is intelligent behavior depends on the character of the internal information processing that produces it. More specifically, I mean psychologism to involve the doctrine that two systems could have actual and potential behavior _typical_ of familiar intelligent beings, that the two systems could be exactly alike in their actual and potential behavior, and in their behavioral dispositions and capacities and counterfactual behavioral properties (i.e., what behaviors, behavioral dispositions, and behavioral capacities they would (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  • Prospects for the cyberiad: Certain limits on human self-knowledge in the cybernetic age.John Barresi - 1987 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 17 (March):19-46.
  • Is the chinese room the real thing?David Anderson - 1987 - Philosophy 62 (July):389-93.
  • Mentality and Machines.Keith Gunderson - 1972 - Doubleday.
    This edition's postscript includes further reflections on these themes and others, and relates them to recent writings of other philosophers and computer ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The Turing Test and the Frame Problem: AI's Mistaken Understanding of Intelligence.Larry Crockett - 1994 - Ablex.
    I have discussed the frame problem and the Turing test at length, but I have not attempted to spell out what I think the implications of the frame problem ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Reflections On Language.Noam Chomsky - 1975 - Temple Smith.
    Presents observations on and analyses of the purposes, methods, and implications of linguistic studies, the concerns and findings of recent work, and current problems and controversies.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   317 citations  
  • The Turing test is not a trick: Turing indistinguishability is a scientific criterion.Stevan Harnad - 1992 - SIGART Bulletin 3 (4):9-10.
    It is important to understand that the Turing Test is not, nor was it intended to be, a trick; how well one can fool someone is not a measure of scientific progress. The TT is an empirical criterion: It sets AI's empirical goal to be to generate human-scale performance capacity. This goal will be met when the candidate's performance is totally indistinguishable from a human's. Until then, the TT simply represents what it is that AI must endeavor eventually to accomplish (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Does mind piggyback on robotic and symbolic capacity?Stevan Harnad - 1995 - In H. Morowitz & J. Singer (eds.), The Mind, the Brain, and Complex Adaptive Systems. Addison Wesley.
    Cognitive science is a form of "reverse engineering" (as Dennett has dubbed it). We are trying to explain the mind by building (or explaining the functional principles of) systems that have minds. A "Turing" hierarchy of empirical constraints can be applied to this task, from t1, toy models that capture only an arbitrary fragment of our performance capacity, to T2, the standard "pen-pal" Turing Test (total symbolic capacity), to T3, the Total Turing Test (total symbolic plus robotic capacity), to T4 (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Minds, Brains, and Programs.John Searle - 1980 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   666 citations  
  • The mind as the software of the brain.Ned Block - 1995 - In Daniel N. Osherson, Lila Gleitman, Stephen M. Kosslyn, S. Smith & Saadya Sternberg (eds.), An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Second Edition, Volume 3. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. pp. 377-425.
    In this section, we will start with an influential attempt to define `intelligence', and then we will move to a consideration of how human intelligence is to be investigated on the machine model. The last part of the section will discuss the relation between the mental and the biological.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Minds, machines and Searle.Stevan Harnad - 1989 - Journal of Theoretical and Experimental Artificial Intelligence 1:5-25.
    Searle's celebrated Chinese Room Argument has shaken the foundations of Artificial Intelligence. Many refutations have been attempted, but none seem convincing. This paper is an attempt to sort out explicitly the assumptions and the logical, methodological and empirical points of disagreement. Searle is shown to have underestimated some features of computer modeling, but the heart of the issue turns out to be an empirical question about the scope and limits of the purely symbolic (computational) model of the mind. Nonsymbolic modeling (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Intentionality and computationalism: Minds, machines, Searle and Harnad.Michael G. Dyer - 1990 - Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 2:303-19.