Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1693 citations  
  • Rules and representations.Noam Chomsky (ed.) - 1980 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    In Rules and Representations, first published in 1980, Noam Chomsky lays out many of the concepts that have made his approach to linguistics and human cognition so instrumental to our understanding of language.Chomsky arrives at his well-known position that there is a universal grammar, structured in the human mind and common to all human languages. Based on Chomsky's 1978 Woodbridge Lectures, this edition contains revised versions of the lectures and two new essays.
  • Putnam and Clarke and mind and body.Yorick Wilks - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (3):213-225.
  • Autonomous psychology and the belief/desire thesis.Stephen P. Stich - 1978 - The Monist 61 (October):573-591.
    A venerable view, still very much alive, holds that human action is to be explained at least in part in terms of beliefs and desires. Those who advocate the view expect that the psychological theory which explains human behavior will invoke the concepts of belief and desire in a substantive way. I will call this expectation the belief-desire thesis. Though there would surely be a quibble or a caveat here and there, the thesis would be endorsed by an exceptionally heterogeneous (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • Simulation games.William E. Smythe - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):448-449.
  • How to turn an information processor into an understander.Aaron Sloman & Monica Croucher - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):447-448.
  • What is an intentional state?John R. Searle - 1979 - Mind 88 (January):74-92.
  • Intrinsic intentionality.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):450-457.
  • Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):111-32.
    The computational view of mind rests on certain intuitions regarding the fundamental similarity between computation and cognition. We examine some of these intuitions and suggest that they derive from the fact that computers and human organisms are both physical systems whose behavior is correctly described as being governed by rules acting on symbolic representations. Some of the implications of this view are discussed. It is suggested that a fundamental hypothesis of this approach is that there is a natural domain of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   662 citations  
  • Physical symbol systems.Allen Newell - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (2):135-83.
    On the occasion of a first conference on Cognitive Science, it seems appropriate to review the basis of common understanding between the various disciplines. In my estimate, the most fundamental contribution so far of artificial intelligence and computer science to the joint enterprise of cognitive science has been the notion of a physical symbol system, i.e., the concept of a broad class of systems capable of having and manipulating symbols, yet realizable in the physical universe. The notion of symbol so (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   485 citations  
  • The functionalist reply.William G. Lycan - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):434-435.
  • Programs, causal powers, and intentionality.John Haugeland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):432-433.
  • The milk of human intentionality.Daniel Dennett - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):428-430.
  • Programs in the explanation of behavior.Robert Cummins - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (June):269-87.
    The purpose of this paper is to set forth a sense in which programs can and do explain behavior, and to distinguish from this a number of senses in which they do not. Once we are tolerably clear concerning the sort of explanatory strategy being employed, two rather interesting facts emerge; (1) though it is true that programs are "internally represented," this fact has no explanatory interest beyond the mere fact that the program is executed; (2) programs which are couched (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Rules and representations.Noam A. Chomsky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (127):1-61.
    The book from which these sections are excerpted is concerned with the prospects for assimilating the study of human intelligence and its products to the natural sciences through the investigation of cognitive structures, understood as systems of rules and representations that can be regarded as These mental structui′es serve as the vehicles for the exercise of various capacities. They develop in the mind on the basis of an innate endowment that permits the growth of rich and highly articulated structures along (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   958 citations  
  • Rules and representations.Noam Chomsky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):1-15.
    The book from which these sections are excerpted is concerned with the prospects for assimilating the study of human intelligence and its products to the natural sciences through the investigation of cognitive structures, understood as systems of rules and representations that can be regarded as “mental organs.” These mental structui′es serve as the vehicles for the exercise of various capacities. They develop in the mind on the basis of an innate endowment that permits the growth of rich and highly articulated (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1153 citations  
  • Semantic Information Processing.Marvin Lee Minsky (ed.) - 1968 - MIT Press.
  • The mind-body problem.Jerry Fodor - 1981 - Scientific American 244 (1):114-25.
  • Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2231 citations  
  • The Mind, Matter, and Models paper.M. Minsky - 1968 - In Marvin L. Minsky (ed.), Semantic Information Processing. MIT Press. pp. 227--270.
  • Confusions of Symbolization in Mental Representation.Paul A. Kolers - 1980 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1980:267 - 284.
    Standard views usually propose that there is something in the mind that is the representation, typically a picture of some sort or a proposition. An alternate view supported here is that the ability to carry out procedures skillfully provides a better account of performance than presence of a fixed mental object does. Evidence from some experiments in the cognitive domain supports the claim.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations