Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Twenty-five basic theorems in situation and world theory.Edward N. Zalta - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (4):385-428.
    The foregoing set of theorems forms an effective foundation for the theory of situations and worlds. All twenty-five theorems seem to be basic, reasonable principles that structure the domains of properties, relations, states of affairs, situations, and worlds in true and philosophically interesting ways. They resolve 15 of the 19 choice points defined in Barwise (1989) (see Notes 22, 27, 31, 32, 35, 36, 39, 43, and 45). Moreover, important axioms and principles stipulated by situation theorists are derived (see Notes (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Meinongian type theory and its applications.Edward N. Zalta - 1982 - Studia Logica 41 (2-3):297-307.
    In this paper I propose a fundamental modification of standard type theory, produce a new kind of type theoretic language, and couch in this language a comprehensive theory of abstract individuals and abstract properties and relations of every type. I then suggest how to employ the theory to solve the four following philosophical problems: the identification and ontological status of Frege's Senses; the deviant behavior of terms in propositional attitude contexts; the non-identity of necessarily equivalent propositions, and the paradox of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A comparison of two intensional logics.Edward N. Zalta - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (1):59-89.
    The author examines the differences between the general intensional logic defined in his recent book and Montague's intensional logic. Whereas Montague assigned extensions and intensions to expressions (and employed set theory to construct these values as certain sets), the author assigns denotations to terms and relies upon an axiomatic theory of intensional entities that covers properties, relations, propositions, worlds, and other abstract objects. It is then shown that the puzzles for Montague's analyses of modality and descriptions, propositional attitudes, and directedness (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Beyond possible worlds.Takashi Yagisawa - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 53 (2):175 - 204.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Ways Things Can't Be.Greg Restall - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (4):583-596.
    Paraconsistent logics are often semantically motivated by considering "impossible worlds." Lewis, in "Logic for equivocators," has shown how we can understand paraconsistent logics by attributing equivocation of meanings to inconsistent believers. In this paper I show that we can understand paraconsistent logics without attributing such equivocation. Impossible worlds are simply sets of possible worlds, and inconsistent believers (inconsistently) believe that things are like each of the worlds in the set. I show that this account gives a sound and complete semantics (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The Logic of Inconsistency.N. Rescher & R. Brandom - 1980 - Blackwell.
  • Simplified semantics for basic relevant logics.Graham Priest & Richard Sylvan - 1992 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 21 (2):217 - 232.
  • Against extended modal realism.Kenneth J. Perszyk - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (2):205 - 214.
  • Systems of modal logic for impossible worlds.Charles G. Morgan - 1973 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 16 (1-4):280 – 289.
    The intuitive notion behind the usual semantics of most systems of modal logic is that of ?possible worlds?. Loosely speaking, an expression is necessary if and only if it holds in all possible worlds; it is possible if and only if it holds in some possible world. Of course, contradictory expressions turn out to hold in no possible worlds, and logically true expressions turn out to hold in every possible world. A method is presented for transforming standard modal systems into (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Naturalized platonism versus platonized naturalism.Bernard Linsky & Edward N. Zalta - 1995 - Journal of Philosophy 92 (10):525-555.
    In this paper, we develop an alternative strategy, Platonized Naturalism, for reconciling naturalism and Platonism and to account for our knowledge of mathematical objects and properties. A systematic (Principled) Platonism based on a comprehension principle that asserts the existence of a plenitude of abstract objects is not just consistent with, but required (on transcendental grounds) for naturalism. Such a comprehension principle is synthetic, and it is known a priori. Its synthetic a priori character is grounded in the fact that it (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Who's Afraid of Impossible Worlds?Edwin D. Mares - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (4):516-526.
    A theory of ersatz impossible worlds is developed to deal with the problem of counterpossible conditionals. Using only tools standardly in the toolbox of possible worlds theorists, it is shown that we can construct a model for counterpossibles. This model is a natural extension of Lewis's semantics for counterfactuals, but instead of using classical logic as its base, it uses the logic LP.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • The interpretation of some Lewis systems of modal logic.M. J. Cresswell - 1967 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 45 (2):198 – 206.
  • The Interpretation of Some Lewis Systems of Modal Logic.M. J. Cresswell - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (2):417-418.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intensional logics and logical truth.M. J. Cresswell - 1972 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (1):2 - 15.
  • What is a non-normal world?Graham Priest - 1992 - Logique Et Analyse 35:291-302.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The modal object calculus and its interpretation.Edward N. Zalta - 1997 - In M. de Rijke (ed.), Advances in Intensional Logic. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 249--279.
    The modal object calculus is the system of logic which houses the (proper) axiomatic theory of abstract objects. The calculus has some rather interesting features in and of itself, independent of the proper theory. The most sophisticated, type-theoretic incarnation of the calculus can be used to analyze the intensional contexts of natural language and so constitutes an intensional logic. However, the simpler second-order version of the calculus couches a theory of fine-grained properties, relations and propositions and serves as a framework (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Non-Standard Possible Worlds, Generalised Quantifiers, and Modal Logic.Jacek Paśniczek - 1994 - In Jan Wolenski (ed.), Philosophical Logic in Poland. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 187--198.