Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Against logical form.Zoltán Gendler Szabó - 2012 - In Gerhard Preyer (ed.), Donald Davidson on truth, meaning, and the mental. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On referring.Peter F. Strawson - 1950 - Mind 59 (235):320-344.
  • Beyond rigidity: the unfinished semantic agenda of Naming and necessity.Scott Soames - 2002 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this fascinating work, Scott Soames offers a new conception of the relationship between linguistic meaning and assertions made by utterances. He gives meanings of proper names and natural kind predicates and explains their use in attitude ascriptions. He also demonstrates the irrelevance of rigid designation in understanding why theoretical identities containing such predicates are necessary, if true.
  • Generality.Nathan Salmon - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 161 (3):471-481.
    A distinction is drawn among predicates, open sentences (or open formulas), and general terms, including general-term phrases. Attaching a copula, perhaps together with an article, to a general term yields a predicate. Predicates can also be obtained through lambda-abstraction on an open sentence. The issue of designation and semantic content for each type of general expression is investigated. It is argued that the designatum of a general term is a universal, e.g., a kind, whereas the designatum of a predicate is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Rigidity and general terms.Genoveva Marti - 2004 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104 (1):131-148.
    In this paper I examine two ways of defining the rigidity of general terms. First I discuss the view that rigid general terms express essential properties. I argue that the view is ultimately unsatisfactory, although not on the basis of the standard objections raised against it. I then discuss the characterisation in terms of sameness of designation in every possible world. I defend that view from two objections but I argue that the approach, although basically right, should be interpreted cautiously.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • General Terms as Designators.Bernard Linsky - 1984 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65 (3):259-276.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Rigidity and kind.Joseph LaPorte - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 97 (3):293-316.
  • Descriptions as predicates.Delia Graff Fara - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 102 (1):1-42.
    Although Strawson’s main aim in “On Referring” was to argue that definite descriptions can be used referentially – that is, “to mention or refer to some individual person or single object . . . , in the course of doing what we should normally describe as making a statement about that person [or] object” (1950, p. 320) – he denied that definite descriptions are always used referentially. The description in ‘Napoleon was the greatest French soldier’ is not used referentially, says (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Rigidity and essentiality.M. Gómez-Torrente - 2006 - Mind 115 (1):227--59.
    Is there a theoretically interesting notion that is a natural extension of the concept of rigidity to general terms? Such a notion ought to satisfy two Kripkean conditions. First, it must apply to typical general terms for natural kinds, stuffs, and phenomena, and fail to apply to most other general terms. Second, true 'identification sentences' (such as 'Cats are animals') containing general terms that the notion applies to must be necessary. I explore a natural extension of the notion of rigidity (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Rigid Application.Michael Devitt - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 125 (2):139-165.
    Kripke defines a rigid designator as one that designates the same object in every possible world in which that object exists. He argues that proper names are rigid. So also, he claims, are various natural kind terms. But we wonder how they could be. These terms are general and it is not obvious that they designate at all. It has been proposed that these kind terms rigidly designate abstract objects. This proposal has been criticized because all terms then seem to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • If 'cat' is a rigid designator, what does it designate?Monte Cook - 1980 - Philosophical Studies 37 (1):61-4.
  • Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Critica 17 (49):69-71.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1521 citations  
  • Naming and Necessity.S. Kripke - 1972 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 45 (4):665-666.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2690 citations  
  • The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds.Helen Beebee & Nigel Sabbarton-Leary (eds.) - 2010 - New York: Routledge.
    Essentialism--roughly, the view that natural kinds have discrete essences, generating truths that are necessary but knowable only _a posteriori_--is an increasingly popular view in the metaphysics of science. At the same time, philosophers of language have been subjecting Kripke’s views about the existence and scope of the necessary _a posteriori_ to rigorous analysis and criticism. Essentialists typically appeal to Kripkean semantics to motivate their radical extension of the realm of the necessary _a posteriori_; but they rarely attempt to provide any (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Rigidity, natural kind terms and metasemantics.Corine Besson - 2010 - In Helen Beebee & Nigel Sabbarton-Leary (eds.), The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds. Routledge. pp. 25--44.
    A paradigmatic case of rigidity for singular terms is that of proper names. And it would seem that a paradigmatic case of rigidity for general terms is that of natural kind terms. However, many philosophers think that rigidity cannot be extended from singular terms to general terms. The reason for this is that rigidity appears to become trivial when such terms are considered: natural kind terms come out as rigid, but so do all other general terms, and in particular all (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Comments on Nathan salmon “are general terms rigid”.Robert May - manuscript
    1. Nathan Salmon paper is entitled with a question: are general terms rigid? He asks this question in way of engaging the issue of the extension of the notion of rigidity beyond the domain of singular terms. While singular terms has been the province of most of the discussion of this rigidity since Naming and Necessity, it is well known that Kripke saw the notion extending to at least certain general terms such as terms for natural kinds. Scott Soames has (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Natural kinds, natural kind terms and the notion of rigidity.Ezequiel Zerbudis - 2012 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 31 (2):171-185.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation