166 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Catherine Wilson [196]Catherine E. Wilson [2]Catherine Warren Wilson [1]
  1.  16
    The Invisible World: Early Modern Philosophy and the Invention of the Microscope.Catherine Wilson - 1995 - Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    In the seventeenth century the microscope opened up a new world of observation, and, according to Catherine Wilson, profoundly revised the thinking of scientists and philosophers alike. The interior of nature, once closed off to both sympathetic intuition and direct perception, was now accessible with the help of optical instruments. The microscope led to a conception of science as an objective, procedure-driven mode of inquiry and renewed interest in atomism and mechanism. Focusing on the earliest forays into microscopical research, from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  2. The Invisible World: Early Modern Philosophy and the Invention of the Microscope.Catherine Wilson - 1995 - Journal of the History of Biology 29 (3):466-468.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  3. Epicureanism at the origins of modernity.Catherine Wilson - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This landmark study examines the role played by the rediscovery of the writings of the ancient atomists, Epicurus and Lucretius, in the articulation of the major philosophical systems of the seventeenth century, and, more broadly, their influence on the evolution of natural science and moral and political philosophy. The target of sustained and trenchant philosophical criticism by Cicero, and of opprobrium by the Christian Fathers of the early Church, for its unflinching commitment to the absence of divine supervision and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  4.  39
    Moral Psychology: Feminist Ethics and Social Theory.Sandra Lee Bartky, Paul Benson, Sue Campbell, Claudia Card, Robin S. Dillon, Jean Harvey, Karen Jones, Charles W. Mills, James Lindemann Nelson, Margaret Urban Walker, Rebecca Whisnant & Catherine Wilson (eds.) - 2004 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    Moral psychology studies the features of cognition, judgement, perception and emotion that make human beings capable of moral action. Perspectives from feminist and race theory immensely enrich moral psychology. Writers who take these perspectives ask questions about mind, feeling, and action in contexts of social difference and unequal power and opportunity. These essays by a distinguished international cast of philosophers explore moral psychology as it connects to social life, scientific studies, and literature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  5. Moral Progress Without Moral Realism.Catherine Wilson - 2010 - Philosophical Papers 39 (1):97-116.
    This paper argues that we can acknowledge the existence of moral truths and moral progress without being committed to moral realism. Rather than defending this claim through the more familiar route of the attempted analysis of the ontological commitments of moral claims, I show how moral belief change for the better shares certain features with theoretical progress in the natural sciences. Proponents of the better theory are able to convince their peers that it is formally and empirically superior to its (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  6.  2
    Leibniz's Metaphysics.Catherine Wilson - 1989 - Princeton Up.
    This study of the metaphysics of G. W. Leibniz gives a clear picture of his philosophical development within the general scheme of seventeenth-century natural philosophy. Catherine Wilson examines the shifts in Leibniz's thinking as he confronted the major philosophical problems of his era. Beginning with his interest in artificial languages and calculi for proof and discovery, the author proceeds to an examination of Leibniz's early theories of matter and motion, to the phenomenalistic turn in his theory of substance and his (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  7.  20
    Leibniz's Metaphysics: A Historical and Comparative Study.Catherine Wilson - 1990 - Princeton University Press.
    This study of the metaphysics of G. W. Leibniz gives a clear picture of his philosophical development within the general scheme of seventeenth-century natural philosophy. Catherine Wilson examines the shifts in Leibniz's thinking as he confronted the major philosophical problems of his era. Beginning with his interest in artificial languages and calculi for proof and discovery, the author proceeds to an examination of Leibniz’s early theories of matter and motion, to the phenomenalistic turn in his theory of substance and his (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  8. Literature and Knowledge.Catherine Wilson - 1983 - Philosophy 58 (226):489 - 496.
    There is probably no subject in the philosophy of art which has prompted more impassioned theorizing than the question of the ‘cognitive value’ of works of art. ‘In the end’, one influential critic has stated, ‘I do not distinguish between science and art except as regards method. Both provide us with a view of reality and both are indispensable to a complete understanding of the universe.’ If a man is not prepared to distinguish between science and art one may well (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  9. Leibniz’s Metaphysics: A Historical and Comparative Study.Catherine Wilson - 1989 - Philosophy 65 (253):377-378.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  10.  12
    Descartes and Cartesianism: Essays in Honour of Desmond Clarke.Stephen Gaukroger & Catherine Wilson (eds.) - 2017 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    This collection of original essays deals with Cartesian themes and problems, especially as these arise in connection with Cartesian natural science and the theory of perception, agency, mentality, divinity, and the passions. It focuses in particular on Desmond Clarke's important contributions to these aspects of Descartes's writings.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  31
    13 The reception of Leibniz in the eighteenth century.Catherine Wilson - 1994 - In Nicholas Jolley (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 442.
  12.  17
    Epicureanism: A Very Short Introduction.Catherine Wilson - 2015 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK.
    Epicureanism is commonly associated with a carefree view of life and the pursuit of pleasures, particularly the pleasures of the table. However it was a complex and distinctive system of philosophy that emphasized simplicity and moderation, and considered nature to consist of atoms and the void. Epicureanism is a school of thought whose legacy continues to reverberate today.In this Very Short Introduction, Catherine Wilson explains the key ideas of the School, comparing them with those of the rival Stoics and with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. (2 other versions)Leibnizian optimism.Catherine Wilson - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy 80 (11):765-783.
  14. The moral epistemology of Locke's Essay.Catherine Wilson - 2007 - In Lex Newman (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Locke's "Essay Concerning Human Understanding". New York: Cambridge University Press.
  15. Lucretius and the history of science.Monte Johnson & Catherine Wilson - 2007 - In Stuart Gillespie & Philip Hardie (eds.), The Cambridge companion to Lucretius. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    An overview of the influence of Lucretius poem On the Nature of Things (De Rerum Natura) on the renaissance and scientific revolution of the seventeenth century, and an examination of its continuing influence over physical atomism in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  42
    (1 other version)Plenitude and Compossibility in Leibniz.Catherine Wilson - 2000 - The Leibniz Review 10:1-20.
    Leibniz entertained the idea that, as a set of “striving possibles” competes for existence, the largest and most perfect world comes into being. The paper proposes 8 criteria for a Leibniz-world. It argues that a) there is no algorithm e.g., one involving pairwise compossibility-testing that can produce even possible Leibniz-worlds; b) individual substances presuppose completed worlds; c) the uniqueness of the actual world is a matter of theological preference, not an outcome of the assembly-process; and d) Goedel’s theorem implies that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17. Descartes and the Corporeal Mind: Some Implications of the Regius Affair.Catherine Wilson - 2000 - In Stephen Gaukroger, John Andrew Schuster & John Sutton (eds.), Descartes' Natural Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 659--79.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18. De ipsa natura: Leibniz on Substance, Force and Activity.Catherine Wilson - 1987 - Studia Leibnitiana 19:148.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  19.  86
    Love of God and Love of Creatures: The Masham-Astell Debate.Catherine Wilson - 2004 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 21 (3):281-298.
  20.  27
    (1 other version)Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon.Catherine Wilson - 2018 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 25:71-87.
    Reversing centuries of methodological caution and skepticism, philosophers have begun to explore the possibility that experience in some form is widely distributed in the universe. It has been proposed that consciousness may pertain to machines, rocks, elementary particles, and perhaps the universe itself. This paper shows why philosophers have good reason to suppose that experiences are widely distributed in living nature, including worms and insects, but why panpsychism extending to non-living nature is an implausible doctrine.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  44
    On Some Alledged Limitations to Moral Endeavor.Catherine Wilson - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (6):275-289.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22. The Oxford handbook of philosophy in early modern Europe.Desmond M. Clarke & Catherine Wilson (eds.) - 2011 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    In this Handbook twenty-six leading scholars survey the development of philosophy between the middle of the sixteenth century and the early eighteenth century.
  23.  71
    Darwin and Nietzsche: Selection, Evolution, and Morality.Catherine Wilson - 2013 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 44 (2):354-370.
    ABSTRACT This article discusses Nietzsche's interpretation of Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection and the basis for his rejection of the major elements of Darwin's overall scheme on observational grounds. Nietzsche's further opposition to the attempt of Darwin and many of his followers to reconcile the “struggle for existence” with Christian ethics is the subject of the second half of the essay.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  34
    Ideas and Animals: The Hard Problem of Leibnizian Metaphysics.Glenn A. Hartz & Catherine Wilson - 2005 - Studia Leibnitiana 37 (1):1 - 19.
    Die Ansicht, dass Leibniz urn 1700 oder einige Zeit danach ein überzeugter Idealist war oder wurde, der allein an die Realität der Geister und ihrer Ideen glaubte, hält sich merkwürdigerweise in der neueren Sekundärliteratur. In diesem Beitrag beurteilen wir die Textgrundlage für diese Behauptung nach von uns für solide gehaltenen Kriterien einer historischen Interpretation, wobei sich die Behauptung unserer Ansicht nach als unzureichend erweist. Obwohl Leibniz zur Überzeugung gelangt war, dass wirkliche "Atome" der Natur keine Ausdehnung hätten, war er sein (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25.  49
    Another Darwinian Aesthetics.Catherine Wilson - 2016 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 74 (3):237-252.
    I offer a Darwinian perspective on the existence of aesthetic interests, tastes, preferences, and productions. It is distinguished from the approaches of Denis Dutton and Geoffrey Miller, drawing instead on Richard O. Prum's notion of biotic artworlds. The relevance of neuroaesthetics to the philosophy of art is defended.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  59
    Berkeley and the Microworld.Catherine Wilson - 1994 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 76 (1):37-64.
  27.  46
    Hume and vital materialism.Catherine Wilson - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (5):1002-1021.
    ABSTRACTHume was not a philosopher famed for what are sometimes called ‘ontological commitments'. Nevertheless, few contemporary scholars doubt that Hume was an atheist, and the present essay tenders the view that Hume was favourably disposed to the 'vital materialism' of post-Newtonian natural philosophers in England, Scotland and France. Both internalist arguments, collating passages from a range of Hume's works, and externalist arguments, reviewing the likely sources of his knowledge of ancient materialism and his association with his materialistic contemporaries are employed.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  65
    Managing Expectations: Locke on the Material Mind and Moral Mediocrity.Catherine Wilson - 2016 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 78:127-146.
    Locke's insistence on the limits of knowledge and the ‘mediocrity’ of our epistemological equipment is well understood; it is rightly seen as integrated with his causal theory of ideas and his theory of judgment. Less attention has been paid to the mediocrity theme as it arises in his theory of moral agency. Locke sees definite limits to human willpower. This is in keeping with post-Puritan theology with its new emphasis on divine mercy as opposed to divine justice and recrimination. It (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  76
    Motion, sensation, and the infinite: The lasting impression of Hobbes on Leibniz.Catherine Wilson - 1997 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 5 (2):339 – 351.
  30.  32
    Visual Surface and Visual Symbol: the Microscope and the Occult in Early Modern Science.Catherine Wilson - 1988 - Journal of the History of Ideas 49 (1):85.
  31.  9
    Leibniz.Catherine Wilson - 2001 - Dartmouth Publishing Company.
    A collection of essays covering a range of topics related to Leibniz. The monads and the pre-established harmony make numerous appearances, and so do Leibniz's discussions of causality, relations, individuation, nature, freedom, consciousness, and divinity. In addition to sections on Leibniz's physics and his theory of substance, a number of papers are included on his philosophy of mind that draw heavily on the New Essays, along with several articles on metaphysical and theological issues, and a section on Leibniz's relationships with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  34
    Descartes's Meditations: An Introduction.Catherine Wilson - 2003 - Cambridge University Press.
    In this introduction to a classic philosophical text, Catherine Wilson examines the arguments of Descartes' famous Meditations, the book which launched modern philosophy. Drawing on the reinterpretations of Descartes' thought of the past twenty-five years, she shows how Descartes constructs a theory of the mind, the body, nature, and God from a premise of radical uncertainty. She discusses in detail the historical context of Descartes' writings and their relationship to early modern science, and at the same time she introduces concepts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  53
    V—Moral Truth: Observational or Theoretical?Catherine Wilson - 2011 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111 (1pt1):97-114.
    Moral properties are widely held to be response‐dependent properties of actions, situations, events and persons. There is controversy as to whether the putative response‐dependence of these properties nullifies any truth‐claims for moral judgements, or rather supports them. The present paper argues that moral judgements are more profitably compared with theoretical judgements in the natural sciences than with the judgements of immediate sense‐perception. The notion of moral truth is dependent on the notion of moral knowledge, which in turn is best understood (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. 'Compossibility, Expression, Accommodation'.Catherine Wilson - 2005 - In Donald Rutherford & J. A. Cover (eds.), Leibniz: nature and freedom. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 108--20.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35. Kant on civilization, culture and moralisation.Catherine Wilson - 2014 - In Alix Cohen (ed.), Kant's Lectures on Anthropology: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. Leibniz and the Animalcula.Catherine Wilson - 1997 - In Michael Alexander Stewart (ed.), Studies in seventeenth-century European philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 153--76.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37. The role of a merit principle in distributive justice.Catherine Wilson - 2003 - The Journal of Ethics 7 (3):277-314.
    The claim that the level of well-beingeach enjoys ought to be to some extent afunction of individuals'' talents, efforts,accomplishments, and other meritoriousattributes faces serious challenge from bothegalitarians and libertarians, but also fromskeptics, who point to the poor historicalrecord of attempted merit assays and theubiquity of attribution biases arising fromlimited sweep, misattribution, custom andconvention, and mimicry. Yet merit-principlesare connected with reactive attitudes andinnate expectations, giving them some claim torecognition and there is a widespread beliefthat their use indirectly promotes thewell-being of all. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38. Is the history of philosophy good for philosophy?Catherine Wilson - 2005 - In Tom Sorell & Graham Alan John Rogers (eds.), Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Constancy, emergence, and illusions: Obstacles to a naturalistic theory of vision.Catherine Wilson - 1993 - In Causation in Early Modern Philosophy. University Park: Penn St University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  25
    (1 other version)Introduction.Catherine Wilson - 1999 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (Supplement):1-30.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  87
    Prospects for non-cognitivism.Catherine Wilson - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (3):291 – 314.
    This essay offers a defence of the non-cognitivist approach to the interpretation of moral judgments as disguised imperatives corresponding to social rules. It addresses the body of criticism that faced R. M. Hare, and that currently faces moral anti-realists, on two levels, by providing a full semantic analysis of evaluative judgments and by arguing that anti-realism is compatible with moral aspiration despite the non-existence of obligations as the externalist imagines them. A moral judgment consists of separate descriptive and prescriptive components (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  36
    Leibniz and Kant.Catherine Wilson - 2023 - Philosophical Review 132 (1):151-154.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  52
    Kant and Leibniz.Catherine Wilson - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  44.  59
    The Doors of Perception and the Artist within.Catherine Wilson - 2015 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 89 (1):1-20.
    This paper discusses the significance for the philosophy of perception and aesthetics of certain productions of the ‘offline brain’. These are experienced in hypnagogic and other trance states, and in disease- or drug-induced hallucination. They bear a similarity to other visual patterns in nature, and reappear in human artistry, especially of the craft type. The reasons behind these resonances are explored, along with the question why we are disposed to find geometrical complexity and ‘supercolouration’ beautiful. The paper concludes with a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  69
    What is the importance of Descartes’s meditation six?Catherine Wilson - 2005 - Philosophica 76 (2).
    In this essay, I argu e that Descartes considered his theory that the body is an inn ervated machine – in which the soul is situated – to be his most original contribution to philosophy. His ambition to prove the immortality of the soul was very poorly realized, a predictable outcome, insofar as his aims were ethical, not theological. His dualism accordingly requires reassessment.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46. Causation in Early Modern Philosophy.Catherine Wilson - 1993 - University Park: Penn St University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  35
    Moral animals: ideals and constraints in moral theory.Catherine Wilson - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Yet many, though not all, moral claims are susceptible of confirmation to the extent that they command the agreement of well-informed inquirers." "With this foundation in place, Wilson turns to a defence of egalitarianism intended to address the objection that the importance of our nonmoral projects, our natural acquisitiveness and partiality, and our meritocratic commitments render social equality a mere abstract ideal. Employing the basic notion of a symmetrical division of the co-operative surplus, she argues that social justice with respect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  31
    Perceptual Acquaintance from Descartes to Reid. [REVIEW]Catherine Wilson - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (1):105.
  49. De Ipsa Natura. Sources of Leibniz's Doctrines of Force, Activity and Natural Law.Catherine Wilson - 1987 - Studia Leibnitiana 19 (2):148-172.
    Leibniz beschreibt sein philosophisches Anliegen oft als Versuch, bestimmte Formen, die von den modernen Philosophen verbannt waren, wieder herzustellen. Dieser Aufsatz erörtert den historischen Gang dieser Verbannung und Leibniz' Bemühen um eine Rehabilitierung der Begriffe Natur, Form und Kraft, wobei er jedoch okkulte, “barbarische” und überflüssige Zutaten zur Naturphilosophie vermeidet.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  31
    Evolutionary ethics.Catherine Wilson - 2004 - In Christopher Stephens & Mohan Matthen (eds.), Elsevier Handbook in Philosophy of Biology. Elsevier. pp. 219.
1 — 50 / 166