Results for 'David Sanford Horner'

944 found
Order:
  1. Cyborgs and cyberspace. Personal identity and moral agency.David Sanford Horner - 2001 - In Sally Munt (ed.), Technospaces: inside the new media. New York: Continuum.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  89
    Moral luck and computer ethics: Gauguin in cyberspace. [REVIEW]David Sanford Horner - 2010 - Ethics and Information Technology 12 (4):299-312.
    Issue Title: Moral Luck, Social Networking Sites, and Trust on the Web I argue that the problem of 'moral luck' is an unjustly neglected topic within Computer Ethics. This is unfortunate given that the very nature of computer technology, its 'logical malleability', leads to ever greater levels of complexity, unreliability and uncertainty. The ever widening contexts of application in turn lead to greater scope for the operation of chance and the phenomenon of moral luck. Moral luck bears down most heavily (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. Using Factor Analysis to Test a Measure of Student Metacognitive Ability Related to Critical Thinking and Intellectual Humility.Jeff Roberts, David E. Wright & Glenn M. Sanford - 2017 - Intersection of Assessment and Learning 2017 (Fall):31-37.
    Locally-developed measures represent great tools for institutions to use in assessing student outcomes. Such measures can be easy to administer, can be cost-effective, and can provide meaningful data for improving student learning. However, many institutions struggle with questions surrounding the quality of their locally-developed assessments. Are their instruments reliable? Are their instruments valid? Can the data generated from these instruments be trusted to drive change and improvement? The good news for faculty, staff, and assessment professionals is that there are steps (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  56
    If P, Then Q: Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning.David H. Sanford - 1989 - New York, NY, USA: Routledge.
    This new edition includes three new chapters, updating the book to take into account developments in the field over the past fifteen years.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  5. Is aquinas an act-ethicist or an agent-ethicist?David A. Horner - 2006 - The Thomist 70 (2):237-265.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  55
    Independent Predicates.David H. Sanford - 1981 - American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (2):171 - 174.
  7. If P then Q Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning.David Sanford - 1991 - Behavior and Philosophy 19 (2):103-107.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  8. Begging the Question.David H. Sanford - 1972 - Analysis 32 (6):197-199.
    A primary purpose of argument is to increase the degree of reasonable confidence that one has in the truth of the conclusion. A question begging argument fails this purpose because it violates what W. E. Johnson called an epistemic condition of inference. Although an argument of the sort characterized by Robert Hoffman in his response (Analysis 32.2, Dec 71) to Richard Robinson (Analysis 31.4, March 71) begs the question in all circumstances, we usually understand the charge that an argument is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  9. Monitoring and Anti-Reductionism in the Epistemology of Testimony.Sanford Goldberg & David Henderson - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (3):600 - 617.
    One of the central points of contention in the epistemology of testimony concerns the uniqueness (or not) of the justification of beliefs formed through testimony--whether such justification can be accounted for in terms of, or 'reduced to,' other familiar sort of justification, e.g. without relying on any epistemic principles unique to testimony. One influential argument for the reductionist position, found in the work of Elizabeth Fricker, argues by appeal to the need for the hearer to monitor the testimony for credibility. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  10. Temporal Parts. Temporal Portions, and Temporal Slices: An Exercise in Naive Mereology.David H. Sanford - 2000 - Acta Analytica 15:21-33.
    Naive mereology studies ordinary conceptions of part and whole. Parts, unlike portions, have objective boundaries and many things, such as dances and sermons have temporal parts. In order to deal with Mark Heller's claim that temporal parts "are ontologically no more or less basic than the wholes that they compose," we retell the story of Laplace's Genius, here named "Swifty." Although Swifty processes lots of information very quickly, his conceptual repertoire need not extend beyond fundamental physics. So we attempt to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. The direction of causation and the direction of conditionship.David H. Sanford - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (8):193-207.
    I criticize and emend J L Mackie's account of causal priority by replacing ‘fixity’ in its central clause by 'x is a causal condition of y, but y is not a causal condition of x'. This replacement works only if 'is a causal condition of' is not a symmetric relation. Even apart from our desire to account for causal priority, it is desirable to have an account of nonsymmetric conditionship. Truth, for example, is a condition of knowledge, but knowledge is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  12. Locke, Leibniz, and Wiggins on being in the same place at the same time.David H. Sanford - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (1):75-82.
    Locke thought it was a necessary truth that no two material bodies could be in the same place at the same time. Leibniz wasn't so sure. This paper sides with Leibniz. I examine the arguments of David Wiggins in defense of Locke on this point (Philosophical Review, January 1968). Wiggins’ arguments are ineffective.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13.  49
    What It Takes to be Great.David A. Horner - 1998 - Faith and Philosophy 15 (4):415-444.
    The revival of virtue ethics is largely inspired by Aristotle, but few---especially Christians---follow him in seeing virtue supremely exemplified in the “magnanimous” man. However, Aristotle raises a matter of importance: the character traits and type of psychological stance exemplified in those who aspire to acts of extraordinary excellence. I explore the accounts of magnanimity found in both Aristotle and Aquinas, defending the intelligibility and acceptability of some central elements of a broadly Aristotelian conception of magnanimity. Aquinas, I argue, provides insight (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14.  40
    The asymmetry of the by-relation.David H. Sanford - 1984 - Mind 93 (371):410-411.
    Sam signaled a turn by extending his arm out the window. Difficulties in explaining the asymmetry of the by-relation in such examples by reference to acceptable and unacceptable counterfactual conditionals are explored by Hugh McCann in "The Trouble with Level-Generation" ("Mind", October 1982). I refine and defend the following alternative account of one-way dependence of y on x: not only is x necessary for y, but something else, independent from x, is also necessary for y; but there is nothing independent (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  61
    Causation and Intelligibility.David H. Sanford - 1994 - Philosophy 69 (267):55 - 67.
    Hume, in "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding", holds (1) that all causal reasoning is based on experience and (2) that causal reasoning is based on nothing but experience. (1) does not imply (2), and Hume's good reasons for (1) are not good reasons for (2). This essay accepts (1) and argues against (2). A priori reasoning plays a role in causal inference. Familiar examples from Hume and from classroom examples of sudden disappearances and radical changes do not show otherwise. A (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  45
    Fusion confusion.David H. Sanford - 2003 - Analysis 63 (1):1-4.
    Two fusions can be in the same place at the same time. So long as a house made of Tinkertoys is intact, the fusion of all its Tinkertoys parts coincides with the fusion of it walls and its roof. If none of the Tinkertoys is destroyed, their fusion persists through the complete disassembly of the house. (So the house is not a fusion of its Tinkertoy parts.) The fusion of the walls and roof does not persist through the complete disassembly (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  17. The problem of the many, many composition questions, and naive mereology.David H. Sanford - 1993 - Noûs 27 (2):219-228.
    Naive mereology studies ordinary, common-sense beliefs about part and whole. Some of the speculations in this article on naive mereology do not bear directly on Peter van Inwagen's "Material Beings". The other topics, (1) and (2), both do. (1) Here is an example of Peter Unger's "Problem of the Many". How can a table be a collection of atoms when many collections of atoms have equally strong claims to be that table? Van Inwagen invokes fuzzy sets to solve this problem. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  18.  36
    Begging the question as involving actual belief and inconceivable without it.David H. Sanford - 1988 - Metaphilosophy 19 (1):32–37.
    This article answers John Biro's "Knowability, Believability, and Begging the Question: a Reply to Sanford" in "Metaphilosophy" 15 (1984). Biro and I agree that of two argument instances with the same form and content, one but not the other can beg the question, depending on other factors. These factors include actual beliefs, or so I maintain (against Biro) with the help of some analysed examples. Brief selections from Archbishop Whatley and J S Mill suggest that they also regard reference (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  19.  52
    Review of R eal Time.David H. Sanford - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):289.
  20.  51
    Volume and solidity.David Sanford - 1967 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 45 (3):329 – 340.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  21.  23
    From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief.David H. Sanford - 1986 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (1):149-154.
  22. Being Human: Groundwork for a Theological Anthropology for the Twenty-First Century.David Kirchhoffer, Robyn Horner & Patrick McArdle (eds.) - 2013 - Preston: Mosaic Press.
    What does it mean to be human? The traditional answers from the past remain only theoretical possibilities unless they come to mean something to today's generation. Moreover, in light of new knowledge and circumstances, a new generation may call these old answers into question, and seek to reinterpret, or, indeed, provide alternatives to them. In the 1960's, the Catholic Church's Second Vatican Council attempted such a reinterpretation, an aggiornamento, for the post-war generation of the mid-twentieth century by proposing, in Gaudium (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Les activités du Centre National de Recherches de Logique en 1971.David H. Sanford - 1970 - Logique Et Analyse 13 (52):(1970:déc.).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Determinates vs. determinables.David H. Sanford - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Everything red is colored, and all squares are polygons. A square is distinguished from other polygons by being four-sided, equilateral, and equiangular. What distinguishes red things from other colored things? This has been understood as a conceptual rather than scientific question. Theories of wavelengths and reflectance and sensory processing are not considered. Given just our ordinary understanding of color, it seems that what differentiates red from other colors is only redness itself. The Cambridge logician W. E. Johnson introduced the terms (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  25.  76
    Coulds, mights, ifs and cans, revisited.David H. Sanford - 1991 - Noûs 25 (2):208-211.
  26.  54
    Symposium contribution on events and their names by Jonathan Bennett.Review author[S.]: David H. Sanford - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (3):633-636.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  50
    Borderline Logic.David H. Sanford - 1975 - American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1):29-39.
    To accommodate vague statements and predicates, I propose an infinite-valued, non-truth-functional interpretation of logic on which the tautologies are exactly the tautologies of classical two-valued logic. iI introduce a determinacy operator, analogous to the necessity operator in alethic modal logic, to allow the definition of first-order and higher-order borderline cases. On the interpretation proposed for determinacy, every statement corresponding to a theorem of modal system T is a logical truth, and I conjecture that every logical truth on the interpretation corresponds (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  28.  65
    Time May Have a Stop.David H. Sanford - 1969 - Analysis 29 (6):206.
    In "Time to Stop" (Analysis, 29,2, December 1968) Vernon Pratt argues that on a relativistic view of time the universe could not become static. He does not distinguish "it might be true at some time later than t that such-and-such is not the case" from "it might not be true that such-and-such is the case at some time later than t," and this distinction undermines his argument.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  58
    What could have happened.David H. Sanford - 1976 - Noûs 10 (3):313-326.
    Morton White proposes two patterns of expansion for sentences of the form "Possible (x is Q)" in "On What Could Have Happened" (Philosophical Review, 1968). His attempts in "Ands and Cans" (Mind, 1974) and in "Positive Freedom, Negative Freedom, and Possibility" (Journal of Philosophy, 1973) to simplify these two patterns and his argument for abandoning the first pattern are mistaken. Although I question a number of White's claims, my purpose is to improve his treatment of possibility rather than to refute (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. What is a Truth Functional Component?David H. Sanford - 1970 - Logique Et Analyse 52:4483-486.
    Although the truth value (falsity) of "Henry knows that (dogs live in trees and beavers chew wood)" remains unchanged no matter what sentence is substituted in it for "beavers chew wood", we want not to regard the second as a truth functional component (tfc) of the first. Many definitions of "tfc" (e.g., Quine's) fail to insure satisfaction of the following principle: if p is a component of r which is in turn a component of q, then p is a tfc (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. (1 other version)Does Locke Think Hardness is a Primary Quality?David H. Sanford - 1970 - The Locke Newsletter 1:17-29.
  32. Uses and abuses of fuzziness in philosophy.David H. Sanford - 1995 - International Journal of General Systems 23 (1):271.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  24
    Causal Asymmetries. [REVIEW]David H. Sanford - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (1):243-246.
    Time and cause present apparent asymmetries. What happens later depends on what happens earlier, and not the other way around. Effects depend on their causes, and not the other way around.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  34.  7
    6. Self-Deception as Rationalization.David H. Sanford - 1988 - In Amelie Oksenberg Rorty & Brian P. McLaughlin (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception. University of California Press. pp. 157-169.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  45
    The Fallacy of Begging the Question: A Reply to Barker.David H. Sanford - 1977 - Dialogue 16 (3):485-498.
    According to John A Barker, whether an argument begs the question is purely a matter of logical form. According to me, it is also a matter of epistemic conditions; some arguments which beg the question in some contexts need not beg the question in every context. I point out difficulties in Barker's treatment and defend my own views against some of his criticisms. In the concluding section, "Alleged difficulties with disjunctive syllogism," I defend the validity of disjunctive syllogism against the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36. Contraries and subcontraries.David H. Sanford - 1968 - Noûs 2 (1):95-96.
    If two statements are contraries if and only if they cannot both be true, but can both be false, then some corresponding A and E categorical statements are not contraries, even on the presupposition that something exists which satisfies the subject term. For some such statements are necessarily true and thus cannot be false. There is a similar problem with subcontraries.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37. Infinity and vagueness.David H. Sanford - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (4):520-535.
    Many philosophic arguments concerned with infinite series depend on the mutual inconsistency of statements of the following five forms: (1) something exists which has R to something; (2) R is asymmetric; (3) R is transitive; (4) for any x which has R to something, there is something which has R to x; (5) only finitely many things are related by R. Such arguments are suspect if the two-place relation R in question involves any conceptual vagueness or inexactness. Traditional sorites arguments (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  38. (1 other version)Causal necessity and logical necessity.David H. Sanford - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (2):185 - 194.
    Myles Brand and Marshall Swain advocate the principle that if A is the set of conditions individually necessary and jointly sufficient for the occurrence of B, then if C is a set of conditions individually necessary for the occurrence of B, every member of C is a member of A. I agree with John Barker and Risto Hilpinen who each argue that this principle is not true for causal necessity and sufficiency, but I disagree with their claim that it is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39. (1 other version)Disjunctive Predicates.David H. Sanford - 1970 - American Philosophical Quarterly 7 (2):162-170.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40. Causation.David H. Sanford - 1994 - In Jaegwon Kim, Ernest Sosa & Gary S. Rosenkrantz (eds.), A Companion to Metaphysics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Twenty-one paragraphs in this entry begin with a statement of a view about causation. To help organize the entry, the next sentence then classifies the view as 'prevailing, majority, controversial', or 'minority'. The following brief discussions attempt to be clear and fair. Respect for fairness, however, does not prevent the author from referring to his own views. For example, the author classifies "There is no element of genuine a priori reasoning in causal inference" as a majority view. After expounded the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  45
    The Inductive Support of Inductive Rules: Themes from Max Black.David H. Sanford - 1990 - Dialectica 44 (1‐2):23-41.
    Overall, Max Black's defense of the inductive support of inductive rules succeeds. Circularity is best explained in terms of epistemic conditions of inference. When an inference is circular, another inference token of the same type may, because of a difference of surrounding circumstances, not be circular. Black's inductive arguments in support of inductive rules fit this pattern: a token circular in some circumstances may be noncircular in other circumstances.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  57
    Can there be one-way causal conditionship?David H. Sanford - 1988 - Synthese 76 (3):397 - 408.
    I defend my attempt to explain causal priority by means of one-way causal conditionship by answering an argument by J. A. Cover about Charles'' law. Then I attempt to say what makes a philosophical analysis a counterfactual analysis, so I can understand Cover''s claim that my account is at its base a counterfactual one. Finally I examine Cover''s discussion of my contention that necessary for in the circumstances is nontransitive.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  26
    God’s Call: Moral Realism, God’s Commands, and Human Autonomy.David A. Horner - 2006 - Philosophia Christi 8 (1):186-190.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Infinite regress arguments.David Sanford - 1984 - In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Principles of philosophical reasoning. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld. pp. 93--117.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  45. Nostalgia for the ordinary: Comments on papers by Unger and Wheeler.David H. Sanford - 1979 - Synthese 41 (2):175 - 184.
    Unger claims that we can block sorites arguments for the conclusion that there are no ordinary things only by invoking some kind of miracle, but no such miracle is needed if we reject the principle that every statement has a truth value. Wheeler's argument for the nonexistence of ordinary things depends on the assumptions that if ordinary things exist, they comprise real kinds, and that if ordinary predicates really apply to things, the predicates refer to real properties. If we accept (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  32
    Distinctness and non-identity.David H. Sanford - 2005 - Analysis 65 (4):269-274.
    The following statement (A) is usually abbreviated with symbols: (A) There are items X and Y, each is F, X is not identical to Y, and everything F is identical to X or is identical to Y. (A) is neither necessary nor sufficient for the existence of exactly two distinct things that are F. Some things are neither identical nor distinct. The difference between distinctness and nonidentity makes a difference in asking questions about counting, constitution, and persistence.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  47.  28
    The anastylosis of reason: Fitting together Stich's fragments.David H. Sanford - 1992 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 35 (1):113 – 137.
    Anastylosis is the reconstruction of a monument using the original fragments and filling in the missing parts with an easily distinguishable modern material. This long review of "The Fragmentation of Reason; Preface to a Pragmatic Theory of Cognitive Evaluation" (MIT, 1990) by Stephen P Stich reconstructs, while preserving their original shapes, the conceptions of reason, truth, and rationality that Stich attempts to shatter. The review agrees with Stich's Chapter 3 which is itself highly critical of some philosophical views about evolution (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. The primary objects of perception.David H. Sanford - 1976 - Mind 85 (April):189-208.
    The primary objects of hearing are sounds: everything we hear we hear by hearing a sound. (This claim differs from Berkeley’s that we hear only sounds and from Aristotle’s that we only hear sounds.) Colored regions are primary objects of sight, and pressure resistant regions are primary objects of perception by touch. By definition, the primary objects of perception are physical. The properties of the primary objects of perception are exactly the properties sense-datum theories attribute to sense-data. Indirect Realism holds (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  49. Chisholm on Brentano's thesis.David H. Sanford - 1997 - In Lewis Edwin Hahn (ed.), The Philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm. Chicago: Open Court. pp. 25--201.
    Roderick Chisholm provides, in different places, two formulations of Brentano's thesis about the relation between the psychological and the intentional: (1) all and only psychological sentences are intentional; (2) no psychological intentional sentence is equivalent to a nonintentional sentence. Chisholm also presents several definitions of intentionality. Some of these allow that a sentence is intentional while its negation is nonintentional, which ruins the prospects of defending the more plausible and interesting thesis (2). A generalization of the notion of logical independence (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  15
    Abstract of Comments: Lotteries, Horseraces, Probability, and Projection.David H. Sanford - 1983 - Noûs 17 (1):70 - 71.
1 — 50 / 944