41 found
Order:
Disambiguations
David J. Stump [30]David Stump [12]David James Stump [1]David P. Stump [1]
See also
  1. The Disunity of science: boundaries, contexts, and power.Peter Galison & David J. Stump (eds.) - 1996 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
    Is science unified or disunified? This collection brings together contributions from prominent scholars in a variety of scientific disciplines to examine this important theoretical question. They examine whether the sciences are, or ever were, unified by a single theoretical view of nature or a methodological foundation and the implications this has for the relationship between scientific disciplines and between science and society.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  2. .Peter Galison & David Stump (eds.) - 1996
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  3.  74
    Conceptual Change and the Philosophy of Science: Alternative Interpretations of the a Priori.David J. Stump - 2015 - New York: Routledge.
    In this book, David Stump traces alternative conceptions of the a priori in the philosophy of science and defends a unique position in the current debates over conceptual change and the constitutive elements in science. Stump emphasizes the unique epistemological status of the constitutive elements of scientific theories, constitutive elements being the necessary preconditions that must be assumed in order to conduct a particular scientific inquiry. These constitutive elements, such as logic, mathematics, and even some fundamental laws of nature, were (...)
  4. Pierre Duhem’s virtue epistemology.David J. Stump - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (1):149-159.
    Duhem’s concept of “good sense” is central to his philosophy of science, given that it is what allows scientist to decide between competing theories. Scientists must use good sense and have intellectual and moral virtues in order to be neutral arbiters of scientific theories, especially when choosing between empirically adequate theories. I discuss the parallels in Duhem’s views to those of virtue epistemologists, who understand justified belief as that arrived at by a cognitive agent with intellectual and moral virtues, showing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  5.  25
    Fallibilism versus Relativism in the Philosophy of Science.David J. Stump - 2022 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 53 (2):187-199.
    In response to a recent argument by David Bloor, I argue that denying absolutes does not necessarily lead to relativism, that one can be a fallibilist without being a relativist. At issue are the empirical natural sciences and what might be called “framework relativism”, that is, the idea that there is always a conceptual scheme or set of practices in use, and all observations are theory-laden relative to the framework. My strategy is to look at the elements that define a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  70
    Henri Poincaré's philosophy of science.David Stump - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (3):335-363.
    Poincare’s arguments for his thesis of the conventionality of metric depend on a relationalist program for dynamics, not on any general philosophical interpretation of science. I will sketch Poincare’s development of the relationalist program and show that his arguments for the conventionality of metric do not depend on any global strategies such as a general empiricism or Duhemian underdetermination arguments. Poincare’s theory of space, while empirically false, is more philosophically sophisticated than his critics have claimed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  7. Defending conventions as functionally a priori knowledge.David J. Stump - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1149-1160.
    Recent defenses of a priori knowledge can be applied to the idea of conventions in science in order to indicate one important sense in which conventionalism is correctsome elements of physical theory have a unique epistemological status as a functionally a priori part of our physical theory. I will argue that the former a priori should be treated as empirical in a very abstract sense, but still conventional. Though actually coming closer to the Quinean position than recent defenses of a (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  8.  66
    Fallibilism versus Relativism in the Philosophy of Science.David J. Stump - 2021 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 52:1-13.
    In response to a recent argument by David Bloor, I argue that denying absolutes does not necessarily lead to relativism, that one can be a fallibilist without being a relativist. At issue are the empirical natural sciences and what might be called “framework relativism”, that is, the idea that there is always a conceptual scheme or set of practices in use, and all observations are theory-laden relative to the framework. My strategy is to look at the elements that define a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. The Kantian Elements in Arthur Pap’s Philosophy.David J. Stump - 2021 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 21 (1):71-83.
    Arthur Pap worked in analytic philosophy while maintaining a strong Kantian or neo-Kantian element throughout his career, stemming from his studying with Ernst Cassirer. I present these elements in the different periods of Pap’s works, showing him to be a consistent critic of logical empiricism, which Pap shows to be incapable of superseding the Kantian framework. Nevertheless, Pap’s work is definitely analytic philosophy, both in terms of the content and the style. According to Pap, the central topics of analytic philosophy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  47
    Fallibilism, naturalism and the traditional requirements for knowledge.David Stump - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 22 (3):451-469.
    In april 1872, with the caisson at a depth of seventy-odd feet and still no bedrock, two men died. The strain for Roebling was nearly unbearable, as his wife later said. On May 18, a third man died, and that same day Roebling made the most difficult and courageous decision of the project. Staking everything — the success of the bridge, his reputation, his career - he ordered a halt. The New York tower, he had concluded, could stand where it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  11. New perspectives on Pierre Duhem’s The aim and structure of physical theory.Anastasios Brenner, Paul Needham, David J. Stump & Robert Deltete - 2011 - Metascience 20 (1):1-25.
    New perspectives on Pierre Duhem’s The aim and structure of physical theory Content Type Journal Article DOI 10.1007/s11016-010-9467-3 Authors Anastasios Brenner, Department of Philosophy, Paul Valéry University-Montpellier III, Route De Mende, 34199 Montpellier cedex 5, France Paul Needham, Department of Philosophy, University of Stockholm, 10691 Stockholm, Sweden David J. Stump, Department of Philosophy, University of San Francisco, 2130 Fulton Street, San Francisco, CA 94117, USA Robert Deltete, Department of Philosophy, Seattle University, 901 12th Avenue, Seattle, WA 98122-1090, USA Journal Metascience (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Naturalized philosophy of science with a plurality of methods.David Stump - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (3):456-460.
    Naturalism implies unity of method--an application of the methods of science to the methodology of science itself and to value theory. Epistemological naturalists have tried to find a privileged discipline to be the methodological model of philosophy of science and epistemology. However, since science itself is not unitary, the use of one science as a model amounts to a reduction and distorts the philosophy of science just as badly as traditional philosophy of science distorted science, despite the fact that the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  75
    Arthur Pap’s Functional Theory of the A Priori.David J. Stump - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (2):273-290.
    Arthur Pap was not quite a Logical Empiricist. He wrote his dissertation in philosophy of science under Ernest Nagel, and he published a textbook in the philosophy of science at the end of his tragically short career, but most of his work would be classified as analytic philosophy. More important, he took some stands that went against Logical Empiricist orthodoxy and was a persistent if friendly critic of the movement. Pap diverged most strongly from Logical Empiricism in his theory of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  14
    Pragmatism Versus Social Construction: A Reply to Shahryari.David J. Stump - 2024 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 55 (1):153-157.
    In a response to my recent article in this journal, Shahram Shahryari argues that I fail to present a third position between absolutism and relativism. He makes two points: first, that fallibilism is insufficient as an alternative, because it is compatible with both relativism and absolutism. The second point is that my argument that experience can lead to objective judgment without being a new absolute fails. I discuss these in turn, showing that both critiques fail and that pragmatism is a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Poincaré's thesis of the translatability of euclidean and non-euclidean geometries.David Stump - 1991 - Noûs 25 (5):639-657.
    Poincaré's claim that Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries are translatable has generally been thought to be based on his introduction of a model to prove the consistency of Lobachevskian geometry and to be equivalent to a claim that Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries are logically isomorphic axiomatic systems. In contrast to the standard view, I argue that Poincaré's translation thesis has a mathematical, rather than a meta-mathematical basis. The mathematical basis of Poincaré's translation thesis is that the underlying manifolds of Euclidean and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16. Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900.David J. Stump - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (3):383-417.
    Standard histories of mathematics and of analytic philosophy contend that work on the foundations of mathematics was motivated by a crisis such as the discovery of paradoxes in set theory or the discovery of non-Euclidean geometries. Recent scholarship, however, casts doubt on the standard histories, opening the way for consideration of an alternative motive for the study of the foundations of mathematics—unification. Work on foundations has shown that diverse mathematical practices could be integrated into a single framework of axiomatic systems (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  46
    The Independence of the Parallel Postulate and Development of Rigorous Consistency Proofs.David J. Stump - 2007 - History and Philosophy of Logic 28 (1):19-30.
    I trace the development of arguments for the consistency of non-Euclidean geometries and for the independence of the parallel postulate, showing how the arguments become more rigorous as a formal conception of geometry is introduced. I analyze the kinds of arguments offered by Jules Hoüel in 1860-1870 for the unprovability of the parallel postulate and for the existence of non-Euclidean geometries, especially his reaction to the publication of Beltrami’s seminal papers, showing that Beltrami was much more concerned with the existence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  8
    Chasing Poincaré: Reflections on Interdisciplinary Research and Historiography.David J. Stump - 2023 - Philosophia Scientiae 27 (2):177-194.
    I will present two examples of influential (and incorrect) interpretations of Poincaré, pinpointing their errors and documenting some of their diffusion. The first example, which appears to have been initiated by Moritz Schlick, is the widespread misinterpretation of Poincaré’s argument for geometric conventionalism by basing it on the underdetermination of theories in science. The second example, having to do with Poincaré’s claim that Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries are inter-translatable, stems from Louis Rougier and was spread in the English language literature (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  73
    The Role of Skill in Experimentation: Reading Ludwik Fleck's Study of the Wasserman Reaction as an Example of Ian Hacking's Experimental Realism.David Stump - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:302 - 308.
    While Ludwik Fleck's Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact is mainly concerned with social elements in science, a central argument depends on his case study of the development of a serum test for syphilis, the Wasserman Reaction, which Fleck argues was the product of skill and of laboratory practice, not a simple discovery. Ian Hacking interprets the creation of new phenomena in science very differently, arguing that it can seen as an argument for scientific realism. Hacking's argument shows that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  50
    Socially constructed technology.David J. Stump - 2000 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 43 (2):217 – 224.
    The main innovation in Questioning Technology is Feenberg?s use of the results of various social constructivist accounts of science and technology to rethink the philosophy of technology. I agree with Feenberg that the social constructivist studies developed by historians and sociologists refute the essentialist account of technology that has been the mainstream position of philosophers of technology. The autonomy of technology seems to be nothing but a myth from the point of view of social construction, since social and political factors (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  29
    A Reconsideration of the Status of Newton's Laws.David J. Stump - 2011 - In Michael J. Shaffer & Michael Veber (eds.), What Place for the a Priori? Open Court. pp. 177.
    I look at the debates of the status of Newton's laws, whether they can each, or all together be considered emprical or a priori.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  24
    From the Values of Scientific Philosophy to the Value Neutrality of the Philosophy of Science.David Stump - 2002 - In Michael Heidelberger & Friedrich Stadler (eds.), History of Philosophy of Science: New Trends and Perspectives. pp. 147-158.
    Members of the Vienna Circle played a pivotal role in defining the work that came to be known as the philosophy of science, yet the Vienna Circle itself is now known to have had much broader concerns and to have been more rooted in philosophical tradition than was once thought. Like current and past philosophers of science, members of the Vienna Circle took science as the object of philosophical reflection but they also endeavored to render philosophy in general compatible with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  23
    Introduction - Forum: Pragmatism in the Philosophy of Science.David J. Stump - 2015 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 5 (1):70-71.
    Introduction to conference papers published in HOPOS.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    Pragmatism, Activism, and the Icy Slopes of Logic in George Reisch’s Portrait of the Philosophy of Science as a Young Field.David J. Stump - 2009 - Science & Education 18 (2):169-175.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  3
    Rationalism in Science.David Stump - 2005 - In Alan Jean Nelson (ed.), A Companion to Rationalism. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 408–424.
    I survey the debate over rationalism and empiricism in science. This chapter contains sections titled: The New Experimental Science as a Challenge to Intuition, Geometry and Intuition, The Mathematical Tradition and Theoretical Science.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  19
    Robert M. Makus, 1951-2002.David J. Stump - 2003 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 76 (5):163 - 164.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  30
    Scientific pluralism and metaphysics.David J. Stump - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 64:64-66.
    Essay review of Stephanie Ruphy, Scientific Pluralism Reconsidered: A New Approach to the (Dis)Unity of Science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  40
    Science and Hypothesis: The Complete Text by Henri Poincaré (New translation).Mélanie Frappier, Andrea Smith & David J. Stump (eds.) - 2017 - London: Bloomsbury.
    New Translation of Henri Poincaré's Science and Hypothesis, including new material and editorial commentary. New Introduction by David J. Stump.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  39
    Reflection on Exaptation—More Missing Terms.David P. Stump - 2010 - Biological Theory 5 (1):15-17.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  5
    The Role of Skill in Experimentation: Reading Ludwik Fleck’s Study of the Wasserman Reaction as an Example of Ian Hacking’s Experimental Realism.David Stump - 1988 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988 (1):302-308.
    Ludwik Fleck’s Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact is an extended argument for the inclusion of social factors in the history and philosophy of science. Fleck uses the history of syphilis as his case study, which falls into two parts. In the first two chapters of his book, Fleck presents a history of the change of the concept of syphilis as a “carnal scourge with strong moralistic connotations” in the middle ages to the modern concept of syphilis as an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  71
    Get Real! A new pragmatist vision for the philosophy of science. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 2023 - Metascience:1-5.
    Essay review of Hasok Chang, Realism for Realistic People: A New Pragmatist Philosophy of Science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Herbert Marcuse, Technology, War and Fascism: Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse, Volume One Reviewed by. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 1999 - Philosophy in Review 19 (3):210-211.
    This is a review of the first volume of Herbert Marcuse's collected works. Highlights include correspondence with Heidegger, who refuses to repudiate the Nazis.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Gila Sher, The Bounds of Logic: a Generalized Viewpoint. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 1995 - Philosophy in Review 15 (6):426-428.
  34. Theory and Practice of Feminist Postcolonial Science Studies. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 2001 - Radical Philosophy Review 4 (1-2):263-265.
  35.  35
    Michael Heidelberger and Gregor Schiemann, eds. The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2009. Pp. viii+376. $109.00 (cloth). [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1):129-132.
  36.  9
    André Kukla. Social Constructivism and the Philosophy of Science. xii + 170 pp., bibl., index. London/New York: Routledge, 2000. $85, Can $128 ; $25.99, Can $38.99. [REVIEW]David Stump - 2004 - Isis 95 (3):538-539.
  37.  40
    A Life in Science, Philosophy, and the Public Domain: Three Biographies of PoincaréJeremy J. Gray. Henri Poincaré: A Scientific Biography. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2013. Pp. xii+592. $35.00/£24.95 .Ferdinand Verhulst. Henri Poincaré: Impatient Genius. New York: Springer, 2012. Pp. xi+260. $49.95 ; $39.95 .Jean-Marc Ginoux and Christian Gerini. 2012. Henri Poincaré: Une biographie au quotidien. Paris: Ellipses, 2012. Pp. iv+298. €24.00 . [Henri Poincaré: A Biography through the Daily Papers. Singapore: World Scientific, 2013. Pp. 260. $29.00 ; $22.00 .]. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 2016 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 6 (2):309-318.
  38. Bertrand Russell, An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 1997 - Philosophy in Review 17 (5):364-366.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Douglas M. Jesseph, Berkeley's Philosophy of Mathematics. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 1995 - Philosophy in Review 15 (2):113-115.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  23
    John H. Zammito. A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Postpositivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour. x + 390 pp., bibl., index. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004. [REVIEW]David Stump - 2005 - Isis 96 (1):159-160.
    State‐of‐the‐art surveys such as John H. Zammito has produced are usually read prior to engaging seriously upon some course of study. Yet his book will be even more helpful, perhaps, to those who can look retrospectively upon the field of science studies in order to consider how the field has changed and whether postmodernism remains the threat that Zammito thinks it. By explicitly including the history of the development of the philosophy of language in a history of science studies, he (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  19
    Michel Fichant; Sophie Roux . Louis Couturat : Mathématiques, langage, philosophie. 363 pp., apps., bibl., index. Paris: Classiques Garnier, 2017. €46. [REVIEW]David J. Stump - 2018 - Isis 109 (1):195-196.