Results for 'Descartes, Infinite, Paradox, Positivity, Ontology, God'

999 found
Order:
  1.  17
    Le paradoxe de l'infini cartésien.Jean-Baptiste Jeangène Vilmer - 2009 - Archives de Philosophie 72 (3):497-521.
    L’idée de l’infini est, chez Descartes, fort paradoxale: elle est à la fois la plus claire et distincte et la plus incompréhensible que l’on puisse avoir. Le paradoxe atteint même sa positivité, puisque l’in-fini s’énonce négativement. Ce problème a occupé de nombreux contemporains, et aujourd’hui encore certains interprètes y voient une contradiction au plus profond de la pensée cartésienne. Cet article expose le paradoxe de l’infini cartésien, puis montre comment Descartes l’avait déjà résolu et comment la postérité s’en saisira.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  11
    Meditationes de prima philosophia.Renâe Descartes & Universitáa Degli Studi di Lecce - 1944 - Paris,: J. Vrin. Edited by Geneviève Rodis-Lewis & Louis-Charles D'Albert Luynes.
    A dual-language edition presenting Descartes's original Latin text of his greatest work, with a facing-page authoritative English translation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  3.  4
    Leibniz’s Early Encounters with Descartes, Galileo, and Spinoza on Infinity.Ohad Nachtomy - 2018 - In Igor Agostini, Richard T. W. Arthur, Geoffrey Gorham, Paul Guyer, Mogens Lærke, Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Ohad Nachtomy, Sanja Särman, Anat Schechtman, Noa Shein & Reed Winegar (eds.), Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 131-154.
    This chapter seeks to highlight some of the main threads that Leibniz used in developing his views on infinity in his early years in Paris. In particular, I will be focusing on Leibniz’s encounters with Descartes, Galileo, and Spinoza. Through these encounters, some of the most significant features of Leibniz’s view of infinity will begin to emerge. Leibniz’s response to Descartes reveals his positive attitude to infinity. He rejects Descartes’s view that, since we are finite, we cannot comprehend the infinite (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  11
    Theoretical paradox and practical dilemma.Alphonso Lingis - 2004 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 12 (1):21 – 28.
    Emmanuel Levinas sets up alterity as a fundamental ontological category, irreducible to being and nothingess. There are two difficulties in understanding this ontological alterity. On the one hand, Levinas formulates it with negative terms - infinition, abstraction, ab-solutenes, trace of a past that has never been present. On the other hand, Levinas invokes the notions of the superlative, the Good, and God. These notions are very difficult to separate from the notion of a redoubling of the positivity by which the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  13
    The Ontology of the Offense: Rowan Williams and Johannes Climacus on Christology and Ontology.Casey Spinks - 2021 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 90 (1):19-41.
    In Christ the Heart of Creation, Rowan Williams argues that Christology as expounded by the classical tradition in Western theology holds a bounty for thinking in Christian ontology about the God-world relation. In particular, he uses the work of Søren Kierkegaard throughout to show that the relation between finite and infinite, immanent and transcendent, is not competitive, and thus there need be no metaphysical problem when holding that the incarnate God-man is both fully human and divine. This essay argues, however, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Between the Infinite and the Finite: God, Hegel and Disagreement.Anthony Joseph Carroll - 2019 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 11 (3):95-113.
    In this article, I consider the importance of philosophy in the dialogue between religious believers and non-believers. I begin by arguing that a new epistemology of epistemic peer disagreement is required if the dialogue is to progress. Rather than viewing the differences between the positions as due to a deficit of understanding, I argue that differences result from the existential anchoring of such enquiries in life projects and the under-determination of interpretations by experience. I then explore a central issue which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Force (God) in Descartes' physics.Gary C. Hatfield - 1979 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 10 (2):113-140.
    It is difficult to evaluate the role of activity - of force or of that which has causal efficacy - in Descartes’ natural philosophy. On the one hand, Descartes claims to include in his natural philosophy only that which can be described geometrically, which amounts to matter (extended substance) in motion (where this motion is described kinematically).’ Yet on the other hand, rigorous adherence to a purely geometrical description of matter in motion would make it difficult to account for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  8.  98
    Descartes's Ontological Proof: Cause and Divine Perfection.Darren Hynes - 2010 - Analecta Hermeneutica 2:1-24.
    Some commentators have worried that Descartes‘s ontological proof is a kind ofafterthought, redundancy, or even embarrassment. Descartes has everythingneeded to establish God as the ground of certainty by Meditation Three, so whybother with yet another proof in Meditation Five? Some have even gone so far asto doubt his sincerity.1Past literature on this topic is of daunting variety andmagnitude, dating back to the seventeenth century.2The current discussion hasfocused on Descartes‘s premises in relation to the coherence of his concept ofGod.3I wish to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  8
    Realismo sin empirismo.Antoni Defez I. Martín - 1994 - Logos. Anales Del Seminario de Metafísica [Universidad Complutense de Madrid, España] 28 (1):13-26.
    In this paper a non-paradoxical interpretation of Hobbes’s defence of scientific realism of materialistic type is proposed. It attempts to explain how this author was able to defend the truth of materialism and at the same time to deny that it could be demonstrated in a metaphysical way. The key to his position depends on the metaphorical use of the concept of ‘imitation’ and the treatment of the infinite and irresistible power as the philosophically relevant attribute of God. So Hobbes’s (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  27
    Force (God) in Descartes' Physics.Gary Hatfield - 1998 - In John Cottingham (ed.), Descartes. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 281-310.
    Reprint of: Gary Hatfield, Force (God) in Descartes' physics, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 10 (2):113-140 (1979) -/- Abstract. It is difficult to evaluate the role of activity - of force or of that which has causal efficacy - in Descartes’ natural philosophy. On the one hand, Descartes claims to include in his natural philosophy only that which can be described geometrically, which amounts to matter (extended substance) in motion (where this motion is described kinematically).’ Yet (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11.  9
    The Tomb of the Artisan God: On Plato's Timaeus.Serge Margel - 2019 - Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
    A far-reaching reinterpretation of Plato’s Timaeus and its engagement with time, eternity, body, and soul that in its original French edition profoundly influenced Derrida The Tomb of the Artisan God provides a radical rereading of Timaeus, Plato’s metaphysical text on time, eternity, and the relationship between soul and body. First published in French in 1995, the original edition of Serge Margel’s book included an extensive introductory essay by Jacques Derrida, who drew on Margel’s insights in developing his own concepts of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12. Does Malebranche need efficacious ideas? The cognitive faculties, the ontological status of ideas, and human attention.Susan Peppers-Bates - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (1):83-105.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 43.1 (2005) 83-105 [Access article in PDF] Does Malebranche Need Efficacious Ideas? The Cognitive Faculties, the Ontological Status of Ideas, and Human Attention Susan Peppers-Bates But whatever effort of mind I make, I cannot find an idea of force, efficacy, of power, save in the will of the infinitely perfect Being. Malebranche, Elucidation 15 One of the signatures of 17th century rationalists is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  28
    The Ontic and the Iterative: Descartes on the Infinite and the Indefinite.Anat Schechtman - 2018 - In Igor Agostini, Richard T. W. Arthur, Geoffrey Gorham, Paul Guyer, Mogens Lærke, Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Ohad Nachtomy, Sanja Särman, Anat Schechtman, Noa Shein & Reed Winegar (eds.), Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 27-44.
    Descartes’s metaphysics posits a sharp distinction between two types of non-finitude, or unlimitedness: whereas God alone is infinite, numbers, space, and time are indefinite. The distinction has proven difficult to interpret in a way that abides by the textual evidence and conserves the theoretical roles that the distinction plays in Descartes’s philosophy—in particular, the important role it plays in the causal proof for God’s existence in the Meditations. After formulating the interpretive task, I criticize extant interpretations of the distinction. I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14. A dialogue with Descartes: Newton's ontology of true and immutable natures.J. E. McGuire - 2007 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 45 (1):103-125.
    : This article is concerned with Newton's appropriation of Descartes' ontology of true and immutable natures in developing his theory of infinitely extended space. It contends that unless the part played by the Platonic distinction between "being a nature" and "having a nature" in Newton's thinking is properly appreciated the foundation of his doctrine of space in relation to God will not be fully understood. It also contends that Newton's Platonism is consistent with his empiricism once the mediating role is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  15. Newton's Ontology of Omnipresence and Infinite Space.J. E. McGuire & Edward Slowik - 2013 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 6:279-308.
    This essay explores the role of God’s omnipresence in Newton’s natural philosophy, with special emphasis placed on how God is related to space. Unlike Descartes’ conception, which denies the spatiality of God, or Gassendi and Charleton’s view, which regards God as completely whole in every part of space, it is argued that Newton accepts spatial extension as a basic aspect of God’s omnipresence. The historical background to Newton’s spatial ontology assumes a large part of our investigation, but with attention also (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  89
    God and Descartes’ Principle of Clear and Distinct Knowledge.Sara F. García-Gómez - 1988 - Philosophy Research Archives 14:283-302.
    In the present study of Descartes’ epistemological investigations, I have tried to show that his renowned principle of clarity and distinctness is not, in fact, one but two axioms. Most interpreters and critics have taken the two formulations of such a principle here considered as successive moments of it. At best, this position is insufficient, for each “version” of the principle of clarity and distinctness guarantees different kinds of cognitive content. Moreover, while the validity of one “version” is not dependent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  24
    God and Descartes’ Principle of Clear and Distinct Knowledge.Sara F. García-Gómez - 1988 - Philosophy Research Archives 14:283-302.
    In the present study of Descartes’ epistemological investigations, I have tried to show that his renowned principle of clarity and distinctness is not, in fact, one but two axioms. Most interpreters and critics have taken the two formulations of such a principle here considered as successive moments of it. At best, this position is insufficient, for each “version” of the principle of clarity and distinctness guarantees different kinds of cognitive content. Moreover, while the validity of one “version” is not dependent (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Meillassoux’s Virtual Future.Graham Harman - 2011 - Continent 1 (2):78-91.
    continent. 1.2 (2011): 78-91. This article consists of three parts. First, I will review the major themes of Quentin Meillassoux’s After Finitude . Since some of my readers will have read this book and others not, I will try to strike a balance between clear summary and fresh critique. Second, I discuss an unpublished book by Meillassoux unfamiliar to all readers of this article, except those scant few that may have gone digging in the microfilm archives of the École normale (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. Cutting It Up, Cartesian Style: Individuation and Motion in Descartes's Ontology of Body.Alice Sowaal - 2001 - Dissertation, University of California, Irvine
    When Descartes famously claimed that he could explain the world in terms of matter in motion, he was sounding the mantra of seventeenth century science. Though his enthusiasm about this new science has been appreciated and is well documented, the details of his contribution are viewed as riddled with paradox. These purported paradoxes revolve around Descartes's circular definition of 'motion' and 'a body', which seems to render his account of individuation implausible. ;I argue for a new interpretation of the Cartesian (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  8
    De l'homme à l'animal: Montaigne et Descartes ou les paradoxes de la philosophie moderne sur la nature des animaux.Thierry Gontier - 1998 - Paris: Vrin.
    Cet ouvrage porte sur l'auto-comprehension de l'homme moderne dans son rapport a la dimension de l'animalite. L'auteur part du statut paradoxal des discours philosophiques de la Renaissance et de l'Age Classique sur la nature des animaux. Ce caractere paradoxal a ete bien caracterise par Pierre Bayle qui, dans l'article Pereira de son Dictionnaire, place son lecteur devant une alternative inconfortable entre les deux positions extremes que sont l'opinion tres dangereuse de Montaigne (qui affirme la superiorite des animaux sur les hommes) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  15
    Positive thinking as an experience of personal development.Sandu Frunza - 2017 - Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies 16 (47):19-31.
    Positive thinking is one of the most valuable tools that postmodern man possesses for personal development and transforming community life. Positive thinking is based on the harmonious relation of the individual with himself, with the others, and with the surrounding reality. It comes at the end of a process of conscious change which the individual goes through in gradual steps, and becomes nuanced as thinking and personal practices develop. Our starting point is the role of thinking as laid out by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. The Hypercategorematic Infinite.Maria Rosa Antognazza - 2015 - The Leibniz Review 25:5-30.
    This paper aims to show that a proper understanding of what Leibniz meant by “hypercategorematic infinite” sheds light on some fundamental aspects of his conceptions of God and of the relationship between God and created simple substances or monads. After revisiting Leibniz’s distinction between (i) syncategorematic infinite, (ii) categorematic infinite, and (iii) actual infinite, I examine his claim that the hypercategorematic infinite is “God himself” in conjunction with other key statements about God. I then discuss the issue of whether the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  23.  8
    Descartes’s ens summe perfectum et infinitum and its Scholastic Background.Igor Agostini - 2018 - In Igor Agostini, Richard T. W. Arthur, Geoffrey Gorham, Paul Guyer, Mogens Lærke, Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Ohad Nachtomy, Sanja Särman, Anat Schechtman, Noa Shein & Reed Winegar (eds.), Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 9-25.
    This chapter presents some important facets of the scholastic background to Descartes’s conception of infinity. In particular, this chapter considers Francisco Suárez’s role in the late medieval debate over the concept of the relationship between God’s status as a perfect being and God’s status as an infinite being. Although I do not argue that Descartes knew Suárez’s position when he originally wrote the Meditations, I show that Suárez’s position lies behind Caterus’s criticisms of Descartes in the Objections and Replies that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  90
    Descartes, skepticism, and Husserl's hermeneutic practice.John Burkey - 1990 - Husserl Studies 7 (1):1-27.
    In the preceding pages, Husserl's objections to the content of Descartes'Meditations on First Philosophy have been reconstructed over the line ofargument in that work. The tone of his interpretation moved from ambivalence to outfight rejection. Husserl's ambivalence manifested itself intwo of the three meditations to which he pays significant attention. We sawthe much heralded methodological strategy of the First Meditation, uponclose examination, is not endorsed by Husserl, that he finds reason toprotest against the content of each individual skeptical argument and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  63
    The Ontological Proof and the Notion of Experience in Schelling.Alessandro Medri - 2011 - Idealistic Studies 41 (1-2):69 - 82.
    In this article I show how Schelling elaborates the fundamental topic of the ontological proof, from the first phase of his philosophy on. I make clear how he keenly penetrates the formulation of Descartes, establishing that it is insufficient in order to demonstrate the existence of God. The fact is, Descartes says that it would be contradictory with the nature of the prefect being that he existed only accidentally; so that it can exist only necessarily. But it is different to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  17
    Descartes Et la Connaissance de Dieu.Laurence Devillairs - 2004 - Libr. Philosophique J. Vrin.
    Comment connaître Dieu? Est-il légitime de faire de son essence l’objet de la méthode, d’appliquer à sa nature et à ses attributs les modes de connaissance définis par cette méthode, à savoir l’induction, la déduction voire l’intuition? Comment défendre la possibilité d’une intellection claire et distincte de l’essence de Dieu, telle que la représente son idée, et faire droit à l’incompréhensibilité attachée à son infinité? Le paradoxe de la métaphysique cartésienne consiste à la fois à revendiquer la possibilité de connaître (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  31
    The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental Tradition (review).Jeffrey Edwards - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (4):609-610.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental TraditionJeffrey EdwardsDavid Carr. The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental Tradition. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Pp. xii + 150. Cloth, $35.00.This book presents a response to contemporary attacks on the concept of the subject. Carr investigates the historical background to the criticisms of the "Metaphysics of the Subject" that are found in French post-structuralist thought (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  33
    The indefinite in the Descartes-More correspondence.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (3):453-471.
    In this article, I consider Descartes’ enigmatic claim that we must assert that the material world is indefinite rather than infinite. The focus here is on the discussion of this claim in Descartes’ late correspondence with More. One puzzle that emerges from this correspondence is that Descartes insists to More that we are not in a position to deny the indefinite universe has limits, while at the same time indicating that we conceive a contradiction in the notion that the universe (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The Actual Infinite as a Day or the Games.Pascal Massie - 2007 - Review of Metaphysics 60 (3):573-596.
    It is commonly assumed that Aristotle denies any real existence to infinity. Nothing is actually infinite. If, in order to resolve Zeno’s paradoxes, Aristotle must talk of infinity, it is only in the sense of a potentiality that can never be actualized. Aristotle’s solution has been both praised for its subtlety and blamed for entailing a limitation of mathematic. His understanding of the infinite as simply indefinite (the “bad infinite” that fails to reach its accomplishment), his conception of the cosmos (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  23
    The Influence of Cogito and Position of God to Subjects of Knowledge and Belief in Descartes’ Philosophy.Naciye Atış - 2015 - Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):01.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  9
    Die Möglichkeit Gottes und die Kompossibilität von Ideen. Wie Leibniz den ontologischen Gottesbeweis Descartes’ zu verbessern versucht (Teil 1).Walter Mesch - 2017 - Studia Leibnitiana 49 (1):28.
    As is well known, Leibniz criticises Descartes for not having shown that God (considered as ens perfectissimum ) is possible, and tries to fill this gap by proving God’s possibility on the basis of absolutely positive and simple perfections. For many readers, however, these perfections have appeared problematic or unintelligible. In my paper, I primarily want to show, that they can be made comprehensible by working out their foundations in Plato’s theory of ideas. On this basis, I want to explain, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  28
    The Ontological Argument of St. Anselm.S. A. Grave - 1952 - Philosophy 27 (100):30-38.
    The first aim of this paper is to try and determine what St. Anselm meant in his original argument in the Proslogion. This needs to be done because not only are the writers who expound his demonstration divided in their interpretations of it, and these interpretations quite different, but, very strangely, one does not find that they mention that there is any ambiguity and that other writers construe Anselm's words differently from themselves. Since there are in fact two arguments in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  17
    The Ontological Status of Cartesian Possibilia.Daniel Stermer, Marc Bobro & Liz Goodnick - unknown
    In this paper I present a novel view of the ontological status of possible objects for Descartes. Specifically, I claim that possible objects just are innate ideas considered objectively. In the act of creation, God creates possibilities—in all its richness—in the form of innate ideas. Thus, in acts of thinking, one may clearly and distinctly perceive, via one’s innate ideas, that such and such is possible. To argue this, I first analyze and critique two competing views—one from Calvin Normore who (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  5
    The problem of the origin of error and its status in Descartes' Meditations on First Philosophy.Denis Prokopov - 2005 - Sententiae 12 (1):23-39.
    According to Descartes, the use of free will is a key way to avoid the errors that arise from the will's attempts to outrun the intellect. The main cause of errors is the combination of infinite will and limited intelligence in man. This combination allows a person to avoid defining the error as an accident and, at the same time, attributing to it the "evil intentions" of God. The author emphasizes that Descartes considers error not only as an epistemological phenomenon, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Spinoza’s Arguments for the Existence of God.Martin Lin - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2):269-297.
    It is often thought that, although Spinoza develops a bold and distinctive conception of God (the unique substance, or Natura Naturans, in which all else inheres and which possesses infinitely many attributes, including extension), the arguments that he offers which purport to prove God’s existence contribute nothing new to natural theology. Rather, he is seen as just another participant in the seventeenth century revival of the ontological argument initiated by Descartes and taken up by Malebranche and Leibniz among others. That (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36.  33
    Apologii︠a︡ Sofistov: Reli︠a︡tivizm Kak Ontologicheskai︠a︡ Sistema.Igorʹ Rassokha - 2009 - Kharʹkov: Kharkivsʹka Nat͡sionalʹna Akademii͡a Misʹkoho Hospodarstva.
    Sophists’ apologia. -/- Sophists were the first paid teachers ever. These ancient Greek enlighteners taught wisdom. Protagoras, Antiphon, Prodicus, Hippias, Lykophron are most famous ones. Sophists views and concerns made a unified encyclopedic system aimed at teaching common wisdom, virtue, management and public speaking. Of the contemporary “enlighters”, Deil Carnegy’s educational work seems to be the most similar to sophism. Sophists were the first intellectuals – their trade was to sell knowledge. They introduced a new type of teacher-student relationship – (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  57
    Cartesian Reflections: Essays on Descartes's Philosophy.Deborah J. Brown - 2010 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):731-734.
    HOME . ABOUT US . CONTACT US HELP . PUBLISH WITH US . LIBRARIANS Search in or Explore Browse Publications A-Z Browse Subjects A-Z Advanced Search University of Cambridge SIGN IN Register | Why Register? | Sign Out | Got a Voucher? prev abstract next Two Approaches to Reading the Historical Descartes A Devout Catholic? Knowledge of The Mental Thought and Language Descartes as A Natural Philosopher Substance Dualism Notes Two Approaches to Reading the Historical Descartes Author: Desmond M. Clarke (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. A computationally-discovered simplification of the ontological argument.Paul Oppenheimer & Edward N. Zalta - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (2):333 - 349.
    The authors investigated the ontological argument computationally. The premises and conclusion of the argument are represented in the syntax understood by the automated reasoning engine PROVER9. Using the logic of definite descriptions, the authors developed a valid representation of the argument that required three non-logical premises. PROVER9, however, discovered a simpler valid argument for God's existence from a single non-logical premise. Reducing the argument to one non-logical premise brings the investigation of the soundness of the argument into better focus. Also, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  39. Newton on God's Relation to Space and Time: The Cartesian Framework.Geoffrey Gorham - 2011 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (3):281-320.
    Beginning with Berkeley and Leibniz, philosophers have been puzzled by the close yet ambivalent association in Newton's ontology between God and absolute space and time. The 1962 publication of Newton's highly philosophical manuscript De Gravitatione has enriched our understanding of his subtle, sometimes cryptic, remarks on the divine underpinnings of space and time in better-known published works. But it has certainly not produced a scholarly consensus about Newton's exact position. In fact, three distinct lines of interpretation have emerged: Independence: space (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  11
    The Monstrosity of Christ: Paradox or Dialectic?Creston Davis (ed.) - 2009 - MIT Press.
    "What matters is not so much that Žižek is endorsing a demythologized, disenchanted Christianity without transcendence, as that he is offering in the end a heterodox version of Christian belief."--John Milbank"To put it even more bluntly, my claim is that it is Milbank who is effectively guilty of heterodoxy, ultimately of a regression to paganism: in my atheism, I am more Christian than Milbank."--Slavoj ŽižekIn this corner, philosopher Slavoj Žižek, a militant atheist who represents the critical-materialist stance against religion's illusions; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  4
    The Monstrosity of Christ: Paradox or Dialectic?Creston Davis (ed.) - 2011 - MIT Press.
    "What matters is not so much that Žižek is endorsing a demythologized, disenchanted Christianity without transcendence, as that he is offering in the end a heterodox version of Christian belief."--John Milbank"To put it even more bluntly, my claim is that it is Milbank who is effectively guilty of heterodoxy, ultimately of a regression to paganism: in my atheism, I am more Christian than Milbank."--Slavoj ŽižekIn this corner, philosopher Slavoj Žižek, a militant atheist who represents the critical-materialist stance against religion's illusions; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Descartes's Ontological Proof of God's Existence.Cecilia Wee - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (1):23-40.
    This paper argues that an examination of the ontology that underpins Descartes’s Fifth Meditation ontological proof of God’s existence will contribute to a better understanding of the nature and structure of the proof. Attention to the Cartesian meditator’s development of this ontology in earlier meditations also makes clear why this proof could not have been asserted before the Fifth Meditation. Finally, it is argued that Kant’s objections against the ontological proof have no force against Descartes’ particular version of the proof.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  56
    Descartes's Ontological Proof of God's Existence.Cecilia Wee - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (1):23-40.
    This paper argues that an examination of the ontology that underpins Descartes’s Fifth Meditation ontological proof of God’s existence will contribute to a better understanding of the nature and structure of the proof. Attention to the Cartesian meditator’s development of this ontology in earlier meditations also makes clear why this proof could not have been asserted before the Fifth Meditation. Finally, it is argued that Kant’s objections against the ontological proof have no force against Descartes’ particular version of the proof.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  23
    Dialogue and Being—an Ontological Investigation.John Rensenbrink - 2013 - Dialogue and Universalism 23 (3):7-22.
    This essay affirms the proposition that dialogue emerges from being itself. There are five parts: being and nature; how it follows that dialogue emerges from being itself; full dialogue; why it is that dialogue has faltered; and ground for optimism, given the noticeable turn in recent decades to an ontology of relationship. We, the human species, are part of nature. We are part of an evolutionary development. The full comprehension of this reality leads to critique of the separation between nature (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  28
    Concerning the Ontological Argument.Albert G. A. Balz - 1953 - Review of Metaphysics 7 (2):207 - 224.
    For the materials of my discussion, I fall back upon Descartes. This philosopher demonstrates the existence of God in his Third Meditation. The ontological argument, however, is given not in the Third but in the Fifth Meditation. It is there expressed in a curious manner. It would seem, to go by literary expression, that he at this point unexpectedly thought of the argument, stumbled upon it, as it were. "Of the essence of material things, et derechef, de Dieu, qu'il existe"--and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  12
    A Computationally-Discovered Simplification of the Ontological Argument.Paul E. Oppenheimer - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (2):333-349.
    The authors investigated the ontological argument computationally. The premises and conclusion of the argument are represented in the syntax understood by the automated reasoning engine PROVER9. Using the logic of definite descriptions, the authors developed a valid representation of the argument that required three non-logical premises. PROVER9, however, discovered a simpler valid argument for God's existence from a single non-logical premise. Reducing the argument to one non-logical premise brings the investigation of the soundness of the argument into better focus. Also, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  47.  86
    Transitions to a modern cosmology: Meister Eckhart and Nicholas of cusa on the intensive infinite.Elizabeth Brient - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (4):575-600.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Transitions to a Modern Cosmology: Meister Eckhart and Nicholas of Cusa on the Intensive InfiniteElizabeth BrientThe Epochal Transition from the late medieval to the early modern world has long been thought in terms of the gradual “infinitization” of the cosmos. Traditionally this process has been studied by focusing on the pre-history and the aftermath of the Copernican revolution, that is, by describing the transition from the finite, hierarchically ordered (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  24
    Cancelled - The Ontological Status of Cartesian Possibilia.Daniel Stermer, Marc Bobro & Liz Goodnick - unknown
    In this paper I present a novel view of the ontological status of possible objects for Descartes. Specifically, I claim that possible objects just are innate ideas considered objectively. In the act of creation, God creates possibilities—in all its richness—in the form of innate ideas. Thus, in acts of thinking, one may clearly and distinctly perceive, via one’s innate ideas, that such and such is possible. To argue this, I first analyze and critique two competing views—one from Calvin Normore who (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  27
    O discurso racional cartesiano na segunda prova da existência de Deus (The racional cartesian discourse on the second proof of God's existence).Monica Fernandes Abreu - 2010 - Horizonte 8 (16):153-165.
    Esta reflexão pretende mostrar o discurso racional cartesiano na segunda prova da existência de Deus. Para tanto, Descartes se depara com uma pergunta central: qual a causa da existência da res cogitans que é finita e possui a ideia de infinito? A resposta é encontrada na desproporcionalidade ontológica entre o finito e o infinito. Essa desproporcionalidade é elucidada mediante dois conceitos: o princípio de causalidade que determina que a causa deve ser igual ou superior a coisa causada e o princípio (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  6
    La possibilité de Dieu et la compossibilité des idées. Comment Leibniz essaie d’améliorer la preuve ontologique de Descartes (2e partie). Die Möglichkeit Gottes und die Kompossibilität von Ideen. Wie Leibniz den ontologischen Gottesbeweis Descartes’ zu verbessern versucht (Teil 2). [REVIEW]Walter Mesch - 2017 - Studia Leibnitiana 49 (2):177.
    Leibniz tries to prove God’s possibility on the basis of absolutely positive and simple perfections. I primarily want to show, how these controversial perfections can be made comprehensible by working out their foundations in Plato’s theory of ideas. After having concentrated on the Cartesian proof and Leibniz’s criticism in the first part of my paper, I now focus on his own version of the proof and its Platonic background. First, I discuss the structure, the advantages and disadvantages of the famous (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999