Results for 'Directed Acyclic Graphs'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. The Birth of Ontology and the Directed Acyclic Graph.Jobst Landgrebe - 2022 - Journal of Knowledge Structures and Systems 3 (1):72-75.
    Barry Smith recently discussed the diagraphs of book eight of Jacob Lorhard’s Ogdoas scholastica under the heading “birth of ontology” (Smith, 2022; this issue). Here, I highlight the commonalities between the original usage of diagraphs in the tradition of Ramus for didactic purposes and the the usage of their present-day successors–modern ontologies–for computational purposes. The modern ideas of ontology and of the universal computer were born just two generations apart in the breakthrough century of instrumental reason.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  14
    A transformational characterization of Markov equivalence for directed acyclic graphs with latent variables.Jiji Zhang & Peter Spirtes - unknown
    Different directed acyclic graphs may be Markov equivalent in the sense that they entail the same conditional independence relations among the observed variables. Chickering provided a transformational characterization of Markov equivalence for DAGs, which is useful in deriving properties shared by Markov equivalent DAGs, and, with certain generalization, is needed to prove the asymptotic correctness of a search procedure over Markov equivalence classes, known as the GES algorithm. For DAG models with latent variables, maximal ancestral graphs (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  18
    A characterization of Markov qquivalence classes for directed acyclic graphs with latent variables.Jiji Zhang - unknown
    Different directed acyclic graphs may be Markov equivalent in the sense that they entail the same conditional indepen- dence relations among the observed variables. Meek characterizes Markov equiva- lence classes for DAGs by presenting a set of orientation rules that can correctly identify all arrow orienta- tions shared by all DAGs in a Markov equiv- alence class, given a member of that class. For DAG models with latent variables, maxi- mal ancestral graphs provide a neat representation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  9
    Calculating TETRAD Constraints Implied by Directed Acyclic Graphs.Peter Spirtes - unknown
    Peter Spirtes. Calculating TETRAD Constraints Implied by Directed Acyclic Graphs.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  23
    Towards characterizing Markov equivalence classes for directed acyclic graphs with latent variables.Ayesha Ali, Thomas Richardson, Peter Spirtes & Jiji Zhang - unknown
    It is well known that there may be many causal explanations that are consistent with a given set of data. Recent work has been done to represent the common aspects of these explanations into one representation. In this paper, we address what is less well known: how do the relationships common to every causal explanation among the observed variables of some DAG process change in the presence of latent variables? Ancestral graphs provide a class of graphs that can (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  7
    NP-Hardness and fixed-parameter tractability of realizing degree sequences with directed acyclic graphs.Sepp Hartung & André Nichterlein - 2012 - In S. Barry Cooper (ed.), How the World Computes. pp. 283--292.
  7.  5
    Average-case analysis of best-first search in two representative directed acyclic graphs.Anup K. Sen, Amitava Bagchi & Weixiong Zhang - 2004 - Artificial Intelligence 155 (1-2):183-206.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  2
    Decomposition of structural learning about directed acyclic graphs.Xianchao Xie, Zhi Geng & Qiang Zhao - 2006 - Artificial Intelligence 170 (4-5):422-439.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  25
    Related Graphical Frameworks: Undircted, Directed Acyclic and Chain Graph Models.Christopher Meek - unknown
    Christopher Meek. Related Graphical Frameworks: Undircted, Directed Acyclic and Chain Graph Models.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  44
    Directed cyclic graphs, conditional independence, and non-recursive linear structural equation models.Peter Spirtes - unknown
    Recursive linear structural equation models can be represented by directed acyclic graphs. When represented in this way, they satisfy the Markov Condition. Hence it is possible to use the graphical d-separation to determine what conditional independence relations are entailed by a given linear structural equation model. I prove in this paper that it is also possible to use the graphical d-separation applied to a cyclic graph to determine what conditional independence relations are entailed to hold by a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. A Transformational Characterization of Markov Equivalence for Directed Maximal Ancestral Graphs.Jiji Zhang & Peter Spirtes - unknown
    The conditional independence relations present in a data set usually admit multiple causal explanations — typically represented by directed graphs — which are Markov equivalent in that they entail the same conditional independence relations among the observed variables. Markov equivalence between directed acyclic graphs (DAGs) has been characterized in various ways, each of which has been found useful for certain purposes. In particular, Chickering’s transformational characterization is useful in deriving properties shared by Markov equivalent DAGs, (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Dangerous Reference Graphs and Semantic Paradoxes.Landon Rabern, Brian Rabern & Matthew Macauley - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (5):727-765.
    The semantic paradoxes are often associated with self-reference or referential circularity. Yablo (Analysis 53(4):251–252, 1993), however, has shown that there are infinitary versions of the paradoxes that do not involve this form of circularity. It remains an open question what relations of reference between collections of sentences afford the structure necessary for paradoxicality. In this essay, we lay the groundwork for a general investigation into the nature of reference structures that support the semantic paradoxes and the semantic hypodoxes. We develop (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  13. A New Approach to Argument by Analogy: Extrapolation and Chain Graphs.Daniel Steel & S. Kedzie Hall - 2010 - Philosophy of Science 77 (5):1058-1069.
    In order to make scientific results relevant to practical decision making, it is often necessary to transfer a result obtained in one set of circumstances—an animal model, a computer simulation, an economic experiment—to another that may differ in relevant respects—for example, to humans, the global climate, or an auction. Such inferences, which we can call extrapolations, are a type of argument by analogy. This essay sketches a new approach to analogical inference that utilizes chain graphs, which resemble directed (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  14.  23
    A logical approach to context-specific independence.Jukka Corander, Antti Hyttinen, Juha Kontinen, Johan Pensar & Jouko Väänänen - 2019 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 170 (9):975-992.
    Directed acyclic graphs (DAGs) constitute a qualitative representation for conditional independence (CI) properties of a probability distribution. It is known that every CI statement implied by the topology of a DAG is witnessed over it under a graph-theoretic criterion of d-separation. Alternatively, all such implied CI statements are derivable from the local independencies encoded by a DAG using the so-called semi-graphoid axioms. We consider Labeled Directed Acyclic Graphs (LDAGs) modeling graphically scenarios exhibiting context-specific independence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  91
    Causal Models and Metaphysics - Part 1: Using Causal Models.Jennifer McDonald - forthcoming - Philosophy Compass.
    This paper provides a general introduction to the use of causal models in the metaphysics of causation, specifically structural equation models and directed acyclic graphs. It reviews the formal framework, lays out a method of interpretation capable of representing different underlying metaphysical relations, and describes the use of these models in analyzing causation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  24
    Causal diagrams and change variables.Eyal Shahar & Doron J. Shahar - 2012 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 18 (1):143-148.
  17.  13
    Defeasible inheritance systems and reactive diagrams.Dov Gabbay - 2008 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 17 (1):1-54.
    Inheritance diagrams are directed acyclic graphs with two types of connections between nodes: x → y and x ↛ y . Given a diagram D, one can ask the formal question of “is there a valid path between node x and node y?” Depending on the existence of a valid path we can answer the question “x is a y” or “x is not a y”. The answer to the above question is determined through a complex inductive (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18. Modelling mechanisms with causal cycles.Brendan Clarke, Bert Leuridan & Jon Williamson - 2014 - Synthese 191 (8):1-31.
    Mechanistic philosophy of science views a large part of scientific activity as engaged in modelling mechanisms. While science textbooks tend to offer qualitative models of mechanisms, there is increasing demand for models from which one can draw quantitative predictions and explanations. Casini et al. (Theoria 26(1):5–33, 2011) put forward the Recursive Bayesian Networks (RBN) formalism as well suited to this end. The RBN formalism is an extension of the standard Bayesian net formalism, an extension that allows for modelling the hierarchical (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  19.  96
    The Frugal Inference of Causal Relations.Malcolm Forster, Garvesh Raskutti, Reuben Stern & Naftali Weinberger - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (3):821-848.
    Recent approaches to causal modelling rely upon the causal Markov condition, which specifies which probability distributions are compatible with a directed acyclic graph. Further principles are required in order to choose among the large number of DAGs compatible with a given probability distribution. Here we present a principle that we call frugality. This principle tells one to choose the DAG with the fewest causal arrows. We argue that frugality has several desirable properties compared to the other principles that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  20.  51
    Homogeneity, selection, and the faithfulness condition.Daniel Steel - 2006 - Minds and Machines 16 (3):303-317.
    The faithfulness condition (FC) is a useful principle for inferring causal structure from statistical data. The usual motivation for the FC appeals to theorems showing that exceptions to it have probability zero, provided that some apparently reasonable assumptions obtain. However, some have objected that, the theorems notwithstanding, exceptions to the FC are probable in commonly occurring circumstances. I argue that exceptions to the FC are probable in the circumstances specified by this objection only given the presence of a condition that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21.  18
    Hopf Bifurcations in Directed Acyclic Networks of Linearly Coupled Hindmarsh–Rose Systems.N. Verdière, V. Lanza & N. Corson - 2016 - Acta Biotheoretica 64 (4):375-402.
    This paper addresses the existence of Hopf bifurcations in a directed acyclic network of neurons, each of them being modeled by a Hindmarsh–Rose neuronal model. The bifurcation parameter is the small parameter corresponding to the ratio of time scales between the fast and the slow dynamics. We first prove that, under certain hypotheses, the single uncoupled neuron can undergo a Hopf bifurcation. Hopf bifurcation occurrences in a directed acyclic network of HR neurons are then discussed. Numerical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  85
    Uniform consistency in causal inference.Richard Scheines & Peter Spirtes - unknown
    S There is a long tradition of representing causal relationships by directed acyclic graphs (Wright, 1934 ). Spirtes ( 1994), Spirtes et al. ( 1993) and Pearl & Verma ( 1991) describe procedures for inferring the presence or absence of causal arrows in the graph even if there might be unobserved confounding variables, and/or an unknown time order, and that under weak conditions, for certain combinations of directed acyclic graphs and probability distributions, are asymptotically, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  23. Molinism: Explaining our Freedom Away.Nevin Climenhaga & Daniel Rubio - 2022 - Mind 131 (522):459-485.
    Molinists hold that there are contingently true counterfactuals about what agents would do if put in specific circumstances, that God knows these prior to creation, and that God uses this knowledge in choosing how to create. In this essay we critique Molinism, arguing that if these theses were true, agents would not be free. Consider Eve’s sinning upon being tempted by a serpent. We argue that if Molinism is true, then there is some set of facts that fully explains both (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. Improving Bayesian statistics understanding in the age of Big Data with the bayesvl R package.Quan-Hoang Vuong, Viet-Phuong La, Minh-Hoang Nguyen, Manh-Toan Ho, Manh-Tung Ho & Peter Mantello - 2020 - Software Impacts 4 (1):100016.
    The exponential growth of social data both in volume and complexity has increasingly exposed many of the shortcomings of the conventional frequentist approach to statistics. The scientific community has called for careful usage of the approach and its inference. Meanwhile, the alternative method, Bayesian statistics, still faces considerable barriers toward a more widespread application. The bayesvl R package is an open program, designed for implementing Bayesian modeling and analysis using the Stan language’s no-U-turn (NUTS) sampler. The package combines the ability (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  30
    参照構造を持つ Xml 上の高速な到達可能性判定.Maita Tetsuya Nakamura Yusaku - 2007 - Transactions of the Japanese Society for Artificial Intelligence 22 (2):191-199.
    We propose an efficient algorithm for deciding the reachability between any nodes on XML data represented by connected directed graphs. We develop a technique to reduce the size of the reference table for the reachability test. Using the small table and the standard range labeling method for rooted ordered trees, we show that our algorithm answers almost queries in a constant time preserving the space efficiency and a reasonable preprocessing time.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. When is a brain like the planet?Clark Glymour - 2007 - Philosophy of Science 74 (3):330-347.
    Time series of macroscopic quantities that are aggregates of microscopic quantities, with unknown one‐many relations between macroscopic and microscopic states, are common in applied sciences, from economics to climate studies. When such time series of macroscopic quantities are claimed to be causal, the causal relations postulated are representable by a directed acyclic graph and associated probability distribution—sometimes called a dynamical Bayes net. Causal interpretations of such series imply claims that hypothetical manipulations of macroscopic variables have unambiguous effects on (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  27. Systems without a graphical causal representation.Daniel M. Hausman, Reuben Stern & Naftali Weinberger - 2014 - Synthese 191 (8):1925-1930.
    There are simple mechanical systems that elude causal representation. We describe one that cannot be represented in a single directed acyclic graph. Our case suggests limitations on the use of causal graphs for causal inference and makes salient the point that causal relations among variables depend upon details of causal setups, including values of variables.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  19
    Decision-theoretic foundations for statistical causality.Philip Dawid - 2021 - Journal of Causal Inference 9 (1):39-77.
    We develop a mathematical and interpretative foundation for the enterprise of decision-theoretic (DT) statistical causality, which is a straightforward way of representing and addressing causal questions. DT reframes causal inference as “assisted decision-making” and aims to understand when, and how, I can make use of external data, typically observational, to help me solve a decision problem by taking advantage of assumed relationships between the data and my problem. The relationships embodied in any representation of a causal problem require deeper justification, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  33
    Automated discovery of linear feedback models.Thomas Richardson - unknown
    The introduction of statistical models represented by directed acyclic graphs (DAGs) has proved fruitful in the construction of expert systems, in allowing efficient updating algorithms that take advantage of conditional independence relations (Pearl, 1988, Lauritzen et al. 1993), and in inferring causal structure from conditional independence relations (Spirtes and Glymour, 1991, Spirtes, Glymour and Scheines, 1993, Pearl and Verma, 1991, Cooper, 1992). As a framework for representing the combination of causal and statistical hypotheses, DAG models have shed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30. Strong-completeness and faithfulness in belief.Chris Meek - unknown
    independence facts implied by a particular directed acyclic graph; an alternative equivalent rule has been proposed by Lauritzen et al. (1990). Geiger et al. (1990) have shown that d-separation is atomic-complete for independence statements..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  54
    The Common Cause Principle. Explanation via Screening off.Leszek Wronski - 2010 - Dissertation, Jagiellonian University
    My Ph.D. dissertation written under the supervision of Prof. Tomasz Placek at the Institute of Philosophy of the Jagiellonian University in Kraków. In one of its most basic and informal shapes, the principle of the common cause states that any surprising correlation between two factors which are believed not to directly influence one another is due to their common cause. Here we will be concerned with a version od this idea which possesses a purely probabilistic formulation. It was introduced, in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  96
    Learning the structure of linear latent variable models.Peter Spirtes - unknown
    We describe anytime search procedures that (1) find disjoint subsets of recorded variables for which the members of each subset are d-separated by a single common unrecorded cause, if such exists; (2) return information about the causal relations among the latent factors so identified. We prove the procedure is point-wise consistent assuming (a) the causal relations can be represented by a directed acyclic graph (DAG) satisfying the Markov Assumption and the Faithfulness Assumption; (b) unrecorded variables are not caused (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  33.  25
    A feasible theory of truth over combinatory algebra.Sebastian Eberhard - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (5):1009-1033.
    We define an applicative theory of truth TPTTPT which proves totality exactly for the polynomial time computable functions. TPTTPT has natural and simple axioms since nearly all its truth axioms are standard for truth theories over an applicative framework. The only exception is the axiom dealing with the word predicate. The truth predicate can only reflect elementhood in the words for terms that have smaller length than a given word. This makes it possible to achieve the very low proof-theoretic strength. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  44
    On different intuitionistic calculi and embeddings from int to S.Uwe Egly - 2001 - Studia Logica 69 (2):249-277.
    In this paper, we compare several cut-free sequent systems for propositional intuitionistic logic Intwith respect to polynomial simulations. Such calculi can be divided into two classes, namely single-succedent calculi (like Gentzen's LJ) and multi-succedent calculi. We show that the latter allow for more compact proofs than the former. Moreover, for some classes of formulae, the same is true if proofs in single-succedent calculi are directed acyclic graphs (dags) instead of trees. Additionally, we investigate the effect of weakening (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  8
    Facial Expression Recognition Using Kernel Entropy Component Analysis Network and DAGSVM.Xiangmin Chen, Li Ke, Qiang Du, Jinghui Li & Xiaodi Ding - 2021 - Complexity 2021:1-12.
    Facial expression recognition plays a significant part in artificial intelligence and computer vision. However, most of facial expression recognition methods have not obtained satisfactory results based on low-level features. The existed methods used in facial expression recognition encountered the major issues of linear inseparability, large computational burden, and data redundancy. To obtain satisfactory results, we propose an innovative deep learning model using the kernel entropy component analysis network and directed acyclic graph support vector machine. We use the KECANet (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  66
    A uniformly consistent estimator of causal effects under the k-Triangle-Faithfulness assumption.Peter Spirtes & Jiji Zhang - unknown
    Spirtes, Glymour and Scheines [Causation, Prediction, and Search Springer] described a pointwise consistent estimator of the Markov equivalence class of any causal structure that can be represented by a directed acyclic graph for any parametric family with a uniformly consistent test of conditional independence, under the Causal Markov and Causal Faithfulness assumptions. Robins et al. [Biometrika 90 491–515], however, proved that there are no uniformly consistent estimators of Markov equivalence classes of causal structures under those assumptions. Subsequently, Kalisch (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  15
    Relative efficiency of propositional proof systems: resolution vs. cut-free LK.Noriko H. Arai - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 104 (1-3):3-16.
    Resolution and cut-free LK are the most popular propositional systems used for logical automated reasoning. The question whether or not resolution and cut-free LK have the same efficiency on the system of CNF formulas has been asked and studied since 1960 425–467). It was shown in Cook and Reckhow, J. Symbolic Logic 44 36–50 that tree resolution has super-polynomial speed-up over cut-free LK. Naturally, the current issue is whether or not resolution and cut-free LK expressed as directed acyclic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  81
    Causal Reasoning with Ancestral Graphical Models.Jiji Zhang - 2008 - Journal of Machine Learning Research 9:1437-1474.
    Causal reasoning is primarily concerned with what would happen to a system under external interventions. In particular, we are often interested in predicting the probability distribution of some random variables that would result if some other variables were forced to take certain values. One prominent approach to tackling this problem is based on causal Bayesian networks, using directed acyclic graphs as causal diagrams to relate post-intervention probabilities to pre-intervention probabilities that are estimable from observational data. However, such (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39.  9
    Decision-theoretic foundations for statistical causality: Response to Pearl.Philip Dawid - 2022 - Journal of Causal Inference 10 (1):296-299.
    I thank Judea Pearl for his discussion of my paper and respond to the points he raises. In particular, his attachment to unaugmented directed acyclic graphs has led to a misapprehension of my own proposals. I also discuss the possibilities for developing a non-manipulative understanding of causality.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  36
    Inference networks : Bayes and Wigmore.Philip Dawid, David Schum & Amanda Hepler - 2011 - In Philip Dawid, William Twining & Mimi Vasilaki (eds.), Evidence, Inference and Enquiry. Oup/British Academy. pp. 119.
    Methods for performing complex probabilistic reasoning tasks, often based on masses of different forms of evidence obtained from a variety of different sources, are being sought by, and developed for, persons in many important contexts including law, medical diagnosis, and intelligence analysis. The complexity of these tasks can often be captured and represented by graphical structures now called inference networks. These networks are directed acyclic graphs, consisting of nodes, representing relevant hypotheses, items of evidence, and unobserved variables, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  6
    Causal analysis as a bridge between qualitative and quantitative research.Rosemary Blersch, Neil Franchuk, Miranda Lucas, Christina M. Nord, Stephanie Varsanyi & Tyler R. Bonnell - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    Yarkoni argues that one solution is to abandon quantitative methods for qualitative ones. While we agree that qualitative methods are undervalued, we argue that both are necessary for thoroughgoing psychological research, complementing one another through the use of causal analysis. We illustrate how directed acyclic graphs can bridge qualitative and quantitative methods, thereby fostering understanding between different psychological methodologies.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  32
    Jon Williamson. Bayesian nets and causality: Philosophical and computational foundations.Kevin B. Korb - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (3):389-396.
    Bayesian networks are computer programs which represent probabilitistic relationships graphically as directed acyclic graphs, and which can use those graphs to reason probabilistically , often at relatively low computational cost. Almost every expert system in the past tried to support probabilistic reasoning, but because of the computational difficulties they took approximating short-cuts, such as those afforded by MYCIN's certainty factors. That all changed with the publication of Judea Pearl's Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems, in 1988, which (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. An anytime algorithm for causal inference.Peter Spirtes - unknown
    The Fast Casual Inference (FCI) algorithm searches for features common to observationally equivalent sets of causal directed acyclic graphs. It is correct in the large sample limit with probability one even if there is a possibility of hidden variables and selection bias. In the worst case, the number of conditional independence tests performed by the algorithm grows exponentially with the number of variables in the data set. This affects both the speed of the algorithm and the accuracy (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44. A polynomial time algorithm for determining Dag equivalence in the presence of latent variables and selection bias.Peter Spirtes - unknown
    if and only if for every W in V, W is independent of the set of all its non-descendants conditional on the set of its parents. One natural question that arises with respect to DAGs is when two DAGs are “statistically equivalent”. One interesting sense of “statistical equivalence” is “d-separation equivalence” (explained in more detail below.) In the case of DAGs, d-separation equivalence is also corresponds to a variety of other natural senses of statistical equivalence (such as representing the same (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  42
    Generalized do-calculus with testable causal assumptions.Jiji Zhang - unknown
    A primary object of causal reasoning concerns what would happen to a system under certain interventions. Specifically, we are often interested in estimating the probability distribution of some random variables that would result from forcing some other variables to take certain values. The renowned do-calculus gives a set of rules that govern the identification of such post-intervention probabilities in terms of pre-intervention probabilities, assuming available a directed acyclic graph that represents the underlying causal structure. However, a DAG causal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  42
    Automated Search for Causal Relations - Theory and Practice.Peter Spirtes, Clark Glymour & Richard Scheines - unknown
    nature of modern data collection and storage techniques, and the increases in the speed and storage capacities of computers. Statistics books from 30 years ago often presented examples with fewer than 10 variables, in domains where some background knowledge was plausible. In contrast, in new domains, such as climate research where satellite data now provide daily quantities of data unthinkable a few decades ago, fMRI brain imaging, and microarray measurements of gene expression, the number of variables can range into the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  20
    Constructing Bayesian Network Models of Gene Expression Networks from Microarray Data.Pater Spirtes, Clark Glymour, Richard Scheines, Stuart Kauffman, Valerio Aimale & Frank Wimberly - unknown
    Through their transcript products genes regulate the rates at which an immense variety of transcripts and subsequent proteins occur. Understanding the mechanisms that determine which genes are expressed, and when they are expressed, is one of the keys to genetic manipulation for many purposes, including the development of new treatments for disease. Viewing each gene in a genome as a distinct variable that is either on or off, or more realistically as a continuous variable, the values of some of these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Heuristic greedy search algorithms for latent variable models.Peter Spirtes - unknown
    A Bayesian network consists of two distinct parts: a directed acyclic graph (DAG or belief-network structure) and a set of parameters for the DAG. The DAG in a Bayesian network can be used to represent both causal hypotheses and sets of probability distributions. Under the causal interpretation, a DAG represents the causal relations in a given population with a set of vertices V when there is an edge from A to B if and only if A is a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. with Unmeasured Variables.Peter Spirtes & Clark Glymour - unknown
    In recent papers we have described a framework for inferring causal structure from relations of statistical independence among a set of measured variables. Using Pearl's notion of the perfect representation of a set of independence relations by a directed acyclic graph we proved..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  25
    On the causal structure of information bias and confounding bias in randomized trials.Eyal Shahar & Doron J. Shahar - 2009 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (6):1214-1216.
1 — 50 / 1000