Results for 'Humberstone's paradox'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  39
    Variations on a Theme of Curry.Lloyd Humberstone - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (1):101-131.
    After an introduction to set the stage, we consider some variations on the reasoning behind Curry's Paradox arising against the background of classical propositional logic and of BCI logic and one of its extensions, in the latter case treating the "paradoxicality" as a matter of nonconservative extension rather than outright inconsistency. A question about the relation of this extension and a differently described (though possibly identical) logic intermediate between BCI and BCK is raised in a final section, which closes (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2. Béziau's Translation Paradox.Lloyd Humberstone - 2005 - Theoria 71 (2):138-181.
    Jean-Yves Béziau (‘Classical Negation can be Expressed by One of its Halves’, Logic Journal of the IGPL 7 (1999), 145–151) has given an especially clear example of a phenomenon he considers a sufficiently puzzling to call the ‘paradox of translation’: the existence of pairs of logics, one logic being strictly weaker than another and yet such that the stronger logic can be embedded within it under a faithful translation. We elaborate on Béziau’s example, which concerns classical negation, as well (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  3.  73
    Humberstone’s Paradox and Conjunction.Eric T. Updike - 2024 - Erkenntnis 89 (3):1183-1195.
    Humberstone has shown that if some set of agents is collectively omniscient (every true proposition is known by at least one agent) then one of them alone must be omniscient. The result is paradoxical as it seems possible for a set of agents to partition resources whereby at the level of the whole community they enjoy eventual omniscience. The Humberstone paradox only requires the assumption that knowledge distributes over conjunction and as such can be viewed as a reductio against (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  86
    Hempel meets Wason.I. L. Humberstone - 1994 - Erkenntnis 41 (3):391-402.
    The adverse reaction to Hempel's 'ravens paradox' embodied in giving it that description is compared with the usual reaction of experimental subjects to the Wason selection task.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. Benevides, MRF, 343 Berk, L., 323 Boėr, SE, 43 Calabrese, PG.S. Chopra, A. G. Cohn, R. P. de Freitas, H. Field, A. Ghose, L. Goble, V. Halbach, L. Humberstone, N. Kamide & S. Kovac - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (669).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  16
    Critical notice.Review author[S.]: I. L. Humberstone - 1987 - Mind 96 (381):99-107.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. 1. Zeno's Metrical Paradox. The version of Zeno's argument that points to possible trouble in measure theory may be stated as follows: 1. Composition. A line segment is an aggregate of points. 2. Point-length. Each point has length 0. 3. Summation. The sum of a (possibly infinite) collection of 0's is. [REVIEW]Zeno'S. Metrical Paradox Revisited - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55:58-73.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  34
    The Modal Logic of Agreement and Noncontingency.Lloyd Humberstone - 2002 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 43 (2):95-127.
    The formula A (it is noncontingent whether A) is true at a point in a Kripke model just in case all points accessible to that point agree on the truth-value of A. We can think of -based modal logic as a special case of what we call the general modal logic of agreement, interpreted with the aid of models supporting a ternary relation, S, say, with OA (which we write instead of A to emphasize the generalization involved) true at a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  9. Antonelli, GA, 277 Bamber, D., 1 Bell, JL, 585 Correia, F., 295.I. Düntsch, G. F. Díez, K. Fine, M. Gómez-Torrente, S. M. Glaister, L. Goble, T. Hailperin, S. O. Hansson, L. Humberstone & T. Hyttinen - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (637).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  55
    Note on Supervenience and Definability.Lloyd Humberstone - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (2):243-252.
    The idea of a property's being supervenient on a class of properties is familiar from much philosophical literature. We give this idea a linguistic turn by converting it into the idea of a predicate symbol's being supervenient on a set of predicate symbols relative to a (first order) theory. What this means is that according to the theory, any individuals differing in respect to whether the given predicate applies to them also differ in respect to the application of at least (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11.  34
    For Want of an ‘And’: A Puzzle about Non-Conservative Extension.Lloyd Humberstone - 2005 - History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (3):229-266.
    Section 1 recalls a point noted by A. N. Prior forty years ago: that a certain formula in the language of a purely implicational intermediate logic investigated by R. A. Bull is unprovable in that logic but provable in the extension of the logic by the usual axioms for conjunction, once this connective is added to the language. Section 2 reminds us that every formula is interdeducible with (i.e. added to intuitionistic logic, yields the same intermediate logic as) some conjunction-free (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  23
    An observation concerning porte's rule in modal logic.Rohan French & Lloyd Humberstone - 2015 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 44 (1/2):25-31.
    It is well known that no consistent normal modal logic contains (as theorems) both ♦A and ♦¬A (for any formula A). Here we observe that this claim can be strengthened to the following: for any formula A, either no consistent normal modal logic contains ♦A, or else no consistent normal modal logic contains ♦¬A.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  9
    " To be an object" means" to have properties." Thus, any object has at least one property. A good formalization of this simple conclusion is a thesis of second-order logic:(1) Vx3P (Px) This formalization is based on two assumptions:(a) object variables. [REVIEW]Russell'S. Paradox - 2006 - In J. Jadacki & J. Pasniczek (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School: The New Generation. Reidel. pp. 6--129.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Two Sorts of 'Ought's.I. L. Humberstone - 1971 - Analysis 32 (1):8 - 11.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  15. The revival of rejective negation.Lloyd Humberstone - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4):331-381.
    Whether assent ("acceptance") and dissent ("rejection") are thought of as speech acts or as propositional attitudes, the leading idea of rejectivism is that a grasp of the distinction between them is prior to our understanding of negation as a sentence operator, this operator then being explicable as applying to A to yield something assent to which is tantamount to dissent from A. Widely thought to have been refuted by an argument of Frege's, rejectivism has undergone something of a revival in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  16. Smiley's distinction between rules of inference and rules of proof.Lloyd Humberstone - 2010 - In Jonathan Lear & Alex Oliver (eds.), The Force of Argument: Essays in Honor of Timothy Smiley. Routledge. pp. 107--126.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17. Contra-classical logics.Lloyd Humberstone - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (4):438 – 474.
    Only propositional logics are at issue here. Such a logic is contra-classical in a superficial sense if it is not a sublogic of classical logic, and in a deeper sense, if there is no way of translating its connectives, the result of which translation gives a sublogic of classical logic. After some motivating examples, we investigate the incidence of contra-classicality (in the deeper sense) in various logical frameworks. In Sections 3 and 4 we will encounter, originally as an example of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  18.  66
    Heterogeneous logic.I. L. Humberstone - 1988 - Erkenntnis 29 (3):395 - 435.
    This paper considers the question: what becomes of the notion of a logic as a way of codifying valid arguments when the customary assumption is dropped that the premisses and conclusions of these arguments are statements from some single language? An elegant treatment of the notion of a logic, when this assumption is in force, is that provided by Dana Scott's theory of consequence relations; this treatment is appropriately generalized in the present paper to the case where we do not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  19.  13
    Modal Logics That Are Both Monotone and Antitone: Makinson’s Extension Results and Affinities between Logics.Lloyd Humberstone & Steven T. Kuhn - 2022 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 63 (4):515-550.
    A notable early result of David Makinson establishes that every monotone modal logic can be extended to LI, LV, or LF, and every antitone logic can be extended to LN, LV, or LF, where LI, LN, LV, and LF are logics axiomatized, respectively, by the schemas □α↔α, □α↔¬α, □α↔⊤, and □α↔⊥. We investigate logics that are both monotone and antitone (hereafter amphitone). There are exactly three: LV, LF, and the minimum amphitone logic AM axiomatized by the schema □α→□β. These logics, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  50
    Zolin and Pizzi: Defining Necessity from Noncontingency.Lloyd Humberstone - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (6):1275-1302.
    The point of the present paper is to draw attention to some interesting similarities, as well as differences, between the approaches to the logic of noncontingency of Evgeni Zolin and of Claudio Pizzi. Though neither of them refers to the work of the other, each is concerned with the definability of a (normally behaving, though not in general truth-implying) notion of necessity in terms of noncontingency, standard boolean connectives and additional but non-modal expressive resources. The notion of definability involved is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21. Wanting as believing.I. L. Humberstone - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (March):49-62.
    An account of desire as a species of belief may owe its appeal to the details of its proposal as to precisely what sort of beliefs desires are to be identified with, and its downfall may be due to those details it does provide. For example, it may be proposed that the desire that α is in fact the belief that it ought to be that α, or is morally good or desirable that it should be the case that α. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  22.  24
    Power Matrices and Dunn--Belnap Semantics: Reflections on a Remark of Graham Priest.Lloyd Humberstone - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Logic 11 (1).
    The plurivalent logics considered in Graham Priest's recent paper of that name can be thought of as logics determined by matrices whose underlying algebras are power algebras, where the power algebra of a given algebra has as elements textit{subsets} of the universe of the given algebra, and the power matrix of a given matrix has has the power algebra of the latter's algebra as its underlying algebra, with its designated elements being selected in a natural way on the basis of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  23.  55
    Sufficiency and Excess.Lloyd Humberstone - 2006 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1):265-320.
    This paper assembles examples and considerations bearing on such questions as the following. Are statements to the effect that someone is too young (for instance) or that someone is old enough always to be understood in terms of someone's being too young or too old for such-and-such-for example, for them to join a particular organization? And when a 'such-and-such' has been specified, is it always at least tacitly modal in force-in the case just given, too young or old enough to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  9
    Wanting as Believing.I. L. Humberstone - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):49-62.
    An account of desire as a species of belief may owe its appeal to the details of its proposal as to precisely what sort of beliefs desires are to be identified with, and its downfall may be due to those details it does provide. For example, it may be proposed that the desire that α is in fact the belief that it ought to be that α, or is morally good or desirable that it should be the case that α. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  25.  74
    Geach’s Categorial Grammar.Lloyd Humberstone - 2004 - Linguistics and Philosophy 28 (3):281 - 317.
    Geach’s rich paper ‘A Program for Syntax’ introduced many ideas into the arena of categorial grammar, not all of which have been given the attention they warrant in the thirty years since its first publication. Rather surprisingly, one of our findings (Section 3 below) is that the paper not only does not contain a statement of what has widely come to be known as “Geach’s Rule”, but in fact presents considerations which are inimical to the adoption of the rule in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  95
    Variation on a Trivialist Argument of Paul Kabay.Lloyd Humberstone - 2011 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 20 (1):115-132.
    Impossible worlds are regarded with understandable suspicion by most philosophers. Here we are concerned with a modal argument which might seem to show that acknowledging their existence, or more particularly, the existence of some hypothetical (we do not say “possible”) world in which everything was the case, would have drastic effects, forcing us to conclude that everything is indeed the case—and not just in the hypothesized world in question. The argument is inspired by a metaphysical (rather than modal-logical) argument of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27.  51
    Prior’s OIC nonconservativity example revisited.Lloyd Humberstone - 2014 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 24 (3):209-235.
    In his 1964 note, ‘Two Additions to Positive Implication’, A. N. Prior showed that standard axioms governing conjunction yield a nonconservative extension of the pure implicational intermediate logic OIC of R. A. Bull. Here, after reviewing the situation with the aid of an adapted form of the Kripke semantics for intuitionistic and intermediate logics, we proceed to illuminate this example by transposing it to the setting of modal logic, and then relate it to the propositional logic of what have been (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  49
    On a conservative extension argument of Dana Scott.Lloyd Humberstone - 2011 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 19 (1):241-288.
    Exegesis, analysis and discussion of an argument deployed by Dana Scott in his 1973 paper ‘Background to Formalization’, rovide an ideal setting for getting clear about some subtleties in the apparently simple idea of conservative extension. There, Scott claimed in respect of two fundamental principles concerning implication that any generalized consequence relation respecting these principles is always extended conservatively by some similarly fundamental principles concerning conjunction and disjunction. This claim appears on the face of it to conflict with cases in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29. Sufficiency and Exess.Lloyd Humberstone & Herman Cappelen - 2006 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80:265-320.
    This paper assembles examples and considerations bearing on such questions as the following. Are statements to the effect that someone is too young or that someone is old enough always to be understood in terms of someone's being too young or too old for such-and-such-for example, for them to join a particular organization? And when a 'such-and-such' has been specified, is it always at least tacitly modal in force-in the case just given, too young or old enough to be able (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. Dana Scott's work with generalized consequence relations.Ian Humberstone - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  46
    Functional dependencies, supervenience, and consequence relations.I. L. Humberstone - 1993 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 2 (4):309-336.
    An analogy between functional dependencies and implicational formulas of sentential logic has been discussed in the literature. We feel that a somewhat different connexion between dependency theory and sentential logic is suggested by the similarity between Armstrong's axioms for functional dependencies and Tarski's defining conditions for consequence relations, and we pursue aspects of this other analogy here for their theoretical interest. The analogy suggests, for example, a different semantic interpretation of consequence relations: instead of thinking ofB as a consequence of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  11
    A recently recurring mistake over Russell's theory of descriptions.Lloyd Humberstone - forthcoming - Analytic Philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  18
    Contrariety re-encountered: nonstandard contraries and internal negation*.Lloyd Humberstone - 2023 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 31 (6):1084-1134.
    This discussion explores the possibility of distinguishing a tighter notion of contrariety evident in the Square of Opposition, especially in its modal incarnations, than as that binary relation holding statements that cannot both be true, with or without the added rider ‘though can both be false’. More than one theorist has voiced the intuition that the paradigmatic contraries of the traditional Square are related in some such tighter way—involving the specific role played by negation in contrasting them—that distinguishes them from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Equivalential Interpolation.Lloyd Humberstone - unknown
    By a consequence relation on a set L of formulas we understand a relation I — c p(L) x L satisfying the conditions called 'Overlap', 'Dilution', and 'Cut for Sets' at p.15 of [25]; we do not repeat the conditions here since we are simply fixing notation and the concept of a consequence relation is well known in any case. (The characterization in [25] amounts to that familiar from Tarski's work, except that there is no 'finitariness' restriction to the effect (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The consequence relation of tautological entailment is maximally relevant: Answering a question of Graham Priest.Lloyd Humberstone - manuscript
    Graham Priest has asked whether the consequence relation associated with the Anderson–Belnap system of Tautological Entailment,1 in the language with connectives ¬, ∧, ∨, and countably many propositional variables as tomic formulas, maximal amongst the substitution-invariant relevant consequence relations on this language. Here a consequence relation is said to be relevant just in case whenever for a set of formulas Γ and formula B, we have Γ B only if some propositional variable occurring in B occurs in at least one (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  55
    When is a Schema Not a Schema? On a Remark by Suszko.Lloyd Humberstone & Allen Hazen - 2020 - Studia Logica 108 (2):199-220.
    A 1971 paper by Roman Suszko, ‘Identity Connective and Modality’, claimed that a certain identity-free schema expressed the condition that there are at most two objects in the domain. Section 1 here gives that schema and enough of the background to this claim to explain Suszko’s own interest in it and related conditions—via non-Fregean logic, in which the objects in question are situations and the aim is to refrain from imposing this condition. Section 3 shows that the claim is false, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  22
    A Basic System of Congruential-to-Monotone Bimodal Logic and Two of Its Extensions.I. L. Humberstone - 1996 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 37 (4):602-612.
    If what is known need not be closed under logical consequence, then a distinction arises between something's being known to be the case (by a specific agent) and its following from something known (to that subject). When each of these notions is represented by a sentence operator, we get a bimodal logic in which to explore the relations between the two notions.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  53
    The pleasures of anticipation: Enriching intuitionistic logic. [REVIEW]Lloyd Humberstone - 2001 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 30 (5):395-438.
    We explore a relation we call 'anticipation' between formulas, where A anticipates B (according to some logic) just in case B is a consequence (according to that logic, presumed to support some distinguished implicational connective →) of the formula A → B. We are especially interested in the case in which the logic is intuitionistic (propositional) logic and are much concerned with an extension of that logic with a new connective, written as "a", governed by rules which guarantee that for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  39.  53
    Identical twins, deduction theorems, and pattern functions: Exploring the implicative BCsK fragment of S. [REVIEW]Lloyd Humberstone - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (5):435 - 487.
    We recapitulate (Section 1) some basic details of the system of implicative BCSK logic, which has two primitive binary implicational connectives, and which can be viewed as a certain fragment of the modal logic S5. From this modal perspective we review (Section 2) some results according to which the pure sublogic in either of these connectives (i.e., each considered without the other) is an exact replica of the material implication fragment of classical propositional logic. In Sections 3 and 5 we (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40. Moore’s Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person.Mitchell S. Green & John N. Williams (eds.) - 2007 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    G. E. Moore observed that to assert, 'I went to the pictures last Tuesday but I don't believe that I did' would be 'absurd'. Over half a century later, such sayings continue to perplex philosophers. In the definitive treatment of the famous paradox, Green and Williams explain its history and relevance and present new essays by leading thinkers in the area.
  41.  8
    Chapman and Butler on Quine's 'so-called paradox'.S. Venketsamy - 1974 - Philosophical Papers 3 (1):51-53.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Humphrey's paradox and the interpretation of inverse conditional propensities.Christopher S. I. Mccurdy - 1996 - Synthese 108 (1):105 - 125.
    The aim of this paper is to distinguish between, and examine, three issues surrounding Humphreys's paradox and interpretation of conditional propensities. The first issue involves the controversy over the interpretation of inverse conditional propensities — conditional propensities in which the conditioned event occurs before the conditioning event. The second issue is the consistency of the dispositional nature of the propensity interpretation and the inversion theorems of the probability calculus, where an inversion theorem is any theorem of probability that makes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43. Hempel's paradox and Wason's selection task: Logical and psychological puzzles of confirmation.Raymond S. Nickerson - 1996 - Thinking and Reasoning 2 (1):1 – 31.
    Hempel's paradox of the ravens has to do with the question of what constitutes confirmation from a logical point of view; Wason 's selection task has been used extensively to investigate how people go about attempting to confirm or disconfirm conditional claims. This paper presents an argument that the paradox is resolved, and that people's typical performance in the selection task can be explained, by consideration of what constitutes an effective strategy for seeking evidence of the tenability of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  44.  88
    Moore's many paradoxes.Mitchell S. Green - 1999 - Philosophical Papers 28 (2):97-109.
    Over the last two decades J.N. Williams has developed an account of the absurdity of such utterances as Its raining but I dont believe it that is both intuitively plausible and applicable to a wide variety of forms that this so-called Moorean absurdity can take. His approach is also noteworthy for making only minimal appeal to principles of epistemic or doxastic logic in its account of such absurdity. We first show that Williams places undue emphasis upon assertion and belief: It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Simpson's Paradox and Causality.Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay, Mark Greenwood, Don Dcruz & Venkata Raghavan - 2015 - American Philosophical Quarterly 52 (1):13-25.
    There are three questions associated with Simpson’s Paradox (SP): (i) Why is SP paradoxical? (ii) What conditions generate SP?, and (iii) What should be done about SP? By developing a logic-based account of SP, it is argued that (i) and (ii) must be divorced from (iii). This account shows that (i) and (ii) have nothing to do with causality, which plays a role only in addressing (iii). A counterexample is also presented against the causal account. Finally, the causal and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  67
    Collecting truths: A paradox in two guises.Eric Updike - 2022 - Analytic Philosophy 63 (3):156-173.
    Two proofs are given which show that if some set of truths fall under finitely many concepts (so-called Collectivity), then they all fall under at least one of them even if we do not know which one. Examples are given in which the result seems paradoxical. The first proof crucially involves Moorean propositions while the second is a reconstruction and generalization of a proof due to Humberstone free from any reference to such propositions. We survey a few solution routes including (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. Mathematics, Models and Zeno's Paradoxes.Joseph S. Alper & Mark Bridger - 1997 - Synthese 110 (1):143-166.
    A version of nonstandard analysis, Internal Set Theory, has been used to provide a resolution of Zeno's paradoxes of motion. This resolution is inadequate because the application of Internal Set Theory to the paradoxes requires a model of the world that is not in accordance with either experience or intuition. A model of standard mathematics in which the ordinary real numbers are defined in terms of rational intervals does provide a formalism for understanding the paradoxes. This model suggests that in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  25
    The 'mental eye' defence of an infinitized version of Yablo's paradox.S. Bringsjord & B. V. Heuveln - 2003 - Analysis 63 (1):61-70.
  49.  29
    Probability and Lycan’s Paradox.S. K. Wertz - 1988 - Southwest Philosophy Review 4 (2):85-85.
  50. Truths about Simpson's Paradox - Saving the Paradox from Falsity.Don Dcruz, Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay, Venkata Raghavan & Gordon Brittain Jr - 2015 - In M. Banerjee & S. N. Krishna (eds.), LNCS 8923. pp. 58-75.
    There are three questions associated with Simpson’s paradox (SP): (i) Why is SP paradoxical? (ii) What conditions generate SP? and (iii) How to proceed when confronted with SP? An adequate analysis of the paradox starts by distinguishing these three questions. Then, by developing a formal account of SP, and substantiating it with a counterexample to causal accounts, we argue that there are no causal factors at play in answering questions (i) and (ii). Causality enters only in connection with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000