Results for 'I. Propositions'

986 found
Order:
  1.  9
    Paolo Crivelli.I. Propositions - 2012 - In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oup Usa. pp. 113.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Wanting, getting, having.I. L. Humberstone - 1990 - Philosophical Papers 99 (August):99-118.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  3.  27
    Propositions and Davidson's Account of Indirect Discourse.I. G. McFetridge - 1976 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76:131 - 145.
    I. G. McFetridge; VII*—Propositions and Davidson's Account of Indirect Discourse, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 76, Issue 1, 1 June 1976, Page.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  4.  37
    VII*—Propositions and Davidson's Account of Indirect Discourse.I. G. McFetridge - 1976 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1):131-146.
    I. G. McFetridge; VII*—Propositions and Davidson's Account of Indirect Discourse, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 76, Issue 1, 1 June 1976, Page.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  5.  74
    Empirical propositions and hypothetical statements.I. Berlin - 1950 - Mind 59 (235):289-312.
  6.  12
    Outline of a Nominalist Theory of Propositions.I. G. Mcfetridge - 1982 - Philosophical Books 23 (1):41-42.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Notes historiques sur les propositions modales.I. M. Bochenski - 1937 - Revue des Sciences Philosophiques Et Théologiques 26:673-692.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  29
    Both rules and associations are required to predict human behaviour.I. P. L. McLaren - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (2):216-217.
    I argue that the dual-process account of human learning rejected by Mitchell et al. in the target article is informative and predictive with respect to human behaviour in a way that the authors' purely propositional account is not. Experiments that reveal different patterns of results under conditions that favour either associative or rule-based performance are the way forward.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  94
    Objective Knowledge in Science and the Humanities.Harold I. Brown - 1977 - Diogenes 25 (97):85-102.
    Philosophy of science is still, in the minds of many, identified with positivism. This is understandable since twentieth century philosophy of science originates with the work of the Vienna Circle. Positivism is most famous for the verification theory of meaning, the doctrine that the meaning of any proposition is the method by which it is verified, and that any nonanalytic locution which cannot be proven or disproven by some empirical test has no cognitive significance. Positivism is an attempt to construct (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. I wish to express here my gratitude to various members of the Department of Mathematics of Cornell University who obliged me by critically reading various drafts of this paper. Bibliography.I. Alonzo Church - 1965 - In Martin Davis (ed.), The Undecidable: Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable Problems, and Computable Functions. Dover Publication. pp. 230.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Wanting as believing.I. L. Humberstone - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (March):49-62.
    An account of desire as a species of belief may owe its appeal to the details of its proposal as to precisely what sort of beliefs desires are to be identified with, and its downfall may be due to those details it does provide. For example, it may be proposed that the desire that α is in fact the belief that it ought to be that α, or is morally good or desirable that it should be the case that α. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  12.  16
    Strong representability of fork algebras, a set theoretic foundation.I. Nemeti - 1997 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 5 (1):3-23.
    This paper is about pairing relation algebras as well as fork algebras and related subjects. In the 1991-92 fork algebra papers it was conjectured that fork algebras admit a strong representation theorem . Then, this conjecture was disproved in the following sense: a strong representation theorem for all abstract fork algebras was proved to be impossible in most set theories including the usual one as well as most non-well-founded set theories. Here we show that the above quoted conjecture can still (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  8
    Wanting as Believing.I. L. Humberstone - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):49-62.
    An account of desire as a species of belief may owe its appeal to the details of its proposal as to precisely what sort of beliefs desires are to be identified with, and its downfall may be due to those details it does provide. For example, it may be proposed that the desire that α is in fact the belief that it ought to be that α, or is morally good or desirable that it should be the case that α. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  14. A causal theory of knowing.Alvin I. Goldman - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (12):357-372.
    Since Edmund L. Gettier reminded us recently of a certain important inadequacy of the traditional analysis of "S knows that p," several attempts have been made to correct that analysis. In this paper I shall offer still another analysis (or a sketch of an analysis) of "S knows that p," one which will avert Gettier's problem. My concern will be with knowledge of empirical propositions only, since I think that the traditional analysis is adequate for knowledge of nonempirical truths.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   372 citations  
  15.  11
    From Naming to Saying: The Unity of the Proposition.Martha I. Gibson - 2004 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    _From Naming to Saying_ explores the classicquestion of the unity of the proposition, combining an historical approach with contemporary causal theories to offer a unique and novel solution. Presents compelling and sophisticated answers to questions about how language represents the world. Defends a novel approach to the classical question about the unity of the proposition. Examines three key historical theories: Frege’s doctrine of concept and object, Russell’s analysis of the sentence, and Wittgenstein’s picture theory of meaning. Combines an historical approach (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  16. The psychology of folk psychology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):15-28.
    The central mission of cognitive science is to reveal the real nature of the mind, however familiar or foreign that nature may be to naive preconceptions. The existence of naive conceptions is also important, however. Prescientific thought and language contain concepts of the mental, and these concepts deserve attention from cognitive science. Just as scientific psychology studies folk physics (McCloskey 1983, Hayes 1985), viz., the common understanding (or misunderstanding) of physical phenomena, so it must study folk psychology, the common understanding (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   216 citations  
  17.  18
    The fuzzy logic of chaos and probabilistic inference.I. Antoniou & Z. Suchanecki - 1997 - Foundations of Physics 27 (3):333-362.
    The logic of a physical system consists of the elementary observables of the system. We show that for chaotic systems the logic is not any more the classical Boolean lattice but a kind of fuzzy logic which we characterize for a class of chaotic maps. Among other interesting properties the fuzzy logic of chaos does not allow for infinite combinations of propositions. This fact reflects the instability of dynamics and it is shared also by quantum systems with diagonal singularity. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  14
    Christus qui mentiri non potest.I. C. Levy - 1999 - Recherches de Theologie Et Philosophie Medievales 66 (2):316-334.
    John Wyclif’s rejection of the doctrine of transubstantiation has received a considerable amount of attention over the last six centuries. To this day scholars continue to reflect upon it, offering a variety of perspectives on Wyclif’s rationale. This study specifically considers the question in connection with Wyclif’s opposition to the more radical element in the fourteenth-century schools. Vehemently opposed to the reckless application of logical-grammatical methods which had led some to question of the truth of biblical propositions, Wyclif would (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. From Naming to Saying: The Unity of the Proposition 2nd Edition.Martha I. Gibson - 2008 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    _From Naming to Saying _explores the classicquestion of the unity of the proposition, combining an historical approach with contemporary causal theories to offer a unique and novel solution. Presents compelling and sophisticated answers to questions about how language represents the world. Defends a novel approach to the classical question about the unity of the proposition. Examines three key historical theories: Frege’s doctrine of concept and object, Russell’s analysis of the sentence, and Wittgenstein’s picture theory of meaning. Combines an historical approach (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20.  12
    Hegel and Contemporary Logic.I. S. Narskii - 1971 - Russian Studies in Philosophy 9 (4):354-373.
    This is a very rewarding topic when we consider the history of dialectical logic, although it may seem to be unrewarding if it is formal logic that is under discussion. We are familiar with Hegel's hypercritical writings on this subject, with his evaluation of the use of symbols in cognition as "empty play," and with his — to say the least — skeptical reaction to early attempts at the mathematization of logic. He characterized the construction of calculi as "reduction" of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  23
    Choice of primitives: A note on axiomatizing intuitionistic logic.I. L. Humberstone - 1998 - History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (1):31-40.
    A purported axiomatization, by P. Gärdenfors, of intuitionistic propositional logic is shown to be incomplete, and that the mistaken claim to completeness is seen to result from carelessness in the choice of primitive logical vocabulary. This leads to a consideration of various ways of conceiving the distinction between primitive and defined vocabularies, along with the bearing of these differences on such matters as are discussed in connection with Gärdenfors.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Presupposition.David I. Beaver - 1997 - In Johan van Bentham & Alice ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language. MIT Press.
    We discuss presupposition, the phenomenon whereby speakers mark linguistically the information that is presupposed or taken for granted, rather than being part of the main propositional content of a speech act. Expressions and constructions carrying presuppositions are called “presupposition triggers”, forming a large class including definites and factive verbs. The article first introduces the range of triggers, the basic properties of presuppositions such as projection and cancellability, and the diagnostic tests used to identify them. The reader is then introducedto major (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  23.  33
    Causal Propensity: A Review.I. J. Good - 1984 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984:829 - 850.
    The causal propensity of an event F to cause another event E is explicated as the weight of evidence against F if E does not occur, given the state of the universe just before F occurred. This definition, first given in 1961, is sharpened, defended, and applied to several examples. In this definition the concept of weight of evidence in favor of a proposition, provided by another one, is to be understood in a technical sense that is intended to capture (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Extensions of some theorems of Godel and church.I. Alonzo Church - 1965 - In Martin Davis (ed.), The Undecidable: Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable Problems, and Computable Functions. Dover Publication. pp. 230.
  25.  20
    Paradigmatic Propositions.Harold I. Brown - 1975 - American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1):85 - 90.
  26. The intentionality of cognitive states.Fred I. Dretske - 1980 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1):281-294.
  27. Argumentation and social epistemology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1994 - Journal of Philosophy 91 (1):27-49.
    What is a good argument? That depends on what is meant by 'argument'. In formal logic, an argument is a set of sentences or propositions, one designated as conclusion and the remainder as premises. On this conception of argument, there are two kinds of goodness. An argument is good in a weak sense if the conclusion either follows deductively from the premises or receives strong evidential support from them. An argument is good in a strong sense if, in addition (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  28.  7
    Omniscience.George I. Mavrodes - 2010 - In Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper & Philip L. Quinn (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 251–257.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Works cited.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29. Doxastic desire and Attitudinal Monism.Douglas I. Campbell - 2018 - Synthese 195 (3):1139-1161.
    How many attitudes must be posited at the level of reductive bedrock in order to reductively explain all the rest? Motivational Humeans hold that at least two attitudes are indispensable, belief and desire. Desire-As-Belief theorists beg to differ. They hold that the belief attitude can do the all the work the desire attitude is supposed to do, because desires are in fact nothing but beliefs of a certain kind. If this is correct it has major implications both for the philosophy (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30. DÜRR, K. - The Propositional Logic of Boethius. [REVIEW]I. Thomas - 1955 - Mind 64:274.
  31.  7
    Review: Antoni Korcik, The Theory of the Syllogism of Assertoric Propositions in Aristotle Against the Background of Traditional Logic. A Historical and Critical Study. [REVIEW]I. M. Bochenski - 1950 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (4):263-264.
  32.  21
    Review: Kazimierz Klosak, The Theory of Ontological Indeterminism and the Three-Valued Logic of Propositions of Prof. Jan Lukasiewicz; Kazimierz Klosak, The Necessity of Going Beyond the Two-Valued Logic. [REVIEW]I. M. Bocheński - 1950 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (4):263-263.
  33.  5
    Review: Takeo Sugihara, Particular and Indefinite Propositions in Aristotelian Logic. [REVIEW]I. M. Bochenski - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (2):172-172.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  5
    Review: A. A. Zinov'ev, A Method of Describing the Truth-Functions of the n-Valued Propositional Calculus. [REVIEW]I. Rosenberg - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (4):691-691.
  35.  74
    Natural deduction rules for a logic of vagueness.J. A. Burgess & I. L. Humberstone - 1987 - Erkenntnis 27 (2):197-229.
    Extant semantic theories for languages containing vague expressions violate intuition by delivering the same verdict on two principles of classical propositional logic: the law of noncontradiction and the law of excluded middle. Supervaluational treatments render both valid; many-Valued treatments, Neither. The core of this paper presents a natural deduction system, Sound and complete with respect to a 'mixed' semantics which validates the law of noncontradiction but not the law of excluded middle.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  36.  39
    First-order definability in modal logic.R. I. Goldblatt - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (1):35-40.
    It is shown that a formula of modal propositional logic has precisely the same models as a sentence of the first-order language of a single dyadic predicate iff its class of models is closed under ultraproducts. as a corollary, any modal formula definable by a set of first-order conditions is always definable by a single such condition. these results are then used to show that the formula (lmp 'validates' mlp) is not first-order definable.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37.  45
    Précis of Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading.Alvin I. Goldman - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 144 (3):431-434.
    In the second half of the twentieth-century, the traditional problem of other minds was re-focused on special problems with propositional attitudes and how we attribute them to others. How do ordinary people, with no education in scientific psychology, understand and ascribe such complex, unobservable states? In different terminology, how do they go about "interpreting" their peers?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  38.  9
    Epistemic legitimizing strategies, commitment and accountability in discourse.Juana I. Marín-Arrese - 2011 - Discourse Studies 13 (6):789-797.
    Hart offers a biologically based explanation for the use of an ‘epistemic positioning strategy’ aimed by speakers/writers at the legitimization of assertions, at persuading addressees of the veracity of the propositions, as a prior condition for the discursive legitimization of actions. This article focuses on various issues addressed in Hart’s article, among them the degree of commitment invoked in speakers/writers’ choice of epistemic stance expressions as legitimization strategies, as well as the expression of subjectivity/intersubjectivity in discourse and the degree (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  78
    Knowledge and Faith in Thomas Aquinas.John I. Jenkins - 1997 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    This book offers a revisionary account of key epistemological concepts and doctrines of St Thomas Aquinas, particularly his concept of scientia, and proposes an interpretation of the purpose and composition of Aquinas's most mature and influential work, the Summa theologiae, which presents the scientia of sacred doctrine, i.e. Christian theology. Contrary to the standard interpretation of it as a work for neophytes in theology, Jenkins argues that it is in fact a pedagogical work intended as the culmination of philosophical and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  40.  75
    A Value-based Framework for Understanding Managerial Tolerance of Bribery in Latin America.Juan I. Sanchez, Carolina Gomez & Guillermo Wated - 2008 - Journal of Business Ethics 83 (2):341-352.
    The cross-cultural literature is reviewed and integrated together with attitude theories, thereby outlining a model through which certain values influence the intervening variables that ultimately lead managers to tolerate employee bribery. The case of Latin America is employed to illustrate how regionally dominant cultural values may shape managers' attitudes, subjective norms, and perceived behavioral control, which in turn affect tolerance of employee bribery. A series of research propositions and practical recommendations are derived from the model.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  60
    What Does it Mean to be an Ontological Naïve Realist?Ícaro M. I. Machado - 2023 - Philosophia 51 (4):2035-2063.
    Although meritorious, Naïve Realism faces theoretical issues stemming from the lack of clarity in the concepts forming its propositions and the relevant (but not usually acknowledged) diversity of its theses. In this paper, my goal is to provide a groundwork that mitigates these theoretical complications. One such distinction concerns its subject matter, in particular, whether it deals with the nature of perceptual episodes or their phenomenology. My first goal is to acknowledge such distinctions by delimiting the former option, which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  31
    Plausibility, necessity and identity: A logic of relative plausibility.L. I. Xiaowu & W. E. N. Xuefeng - 2007 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 2 (4):629-644.
    We construct a Hilbert style system RPL for the notion of plausibility measure introduced by Halpern J, and we prove the soundness and completeness with respect to a neighborhood style semantics. Using the language of RPL, we demonstrate that it can define well-studied notions of necessity, conditionals and propositional identity.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  15
    The Possibility of Transmission of Speech in the Qurʾān.Muhammed İsa Yüksek - 2019 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 23 (1):273-290.
    In terms of classical tafsir literature, it is possible that the speeches made to a person or group in the Qurʾān carry messages for other individuals or groups. According to some approaches that emerged in the modern period, when the speech was made and to whom it was directed not only determine the meaning, but also limits it. This dilemma has to be based on the theoretical dimension. The most obvious example of the transition of the speech from direct counterpart (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Justification magnets.C. S. I. Jenkins - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (1):93-111.
    David Lewis is associated with the controversial thesis that some properties are more eligible than others to be the referents of our predicates solely in virtue of those properties’ being more natural; independently, that is, of anything to do with our patterns of usage of the relevant predicates. On such a view, the natural properties act as ‘reference magnets’. In this paper I explore (though I do not endorse) a related thesis in epistemology: that some propositions are ‘justification magnets’. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  56
    Observation and the Foundations of Objectivity.Harold I. Brown - 1979 - The Monist 62 (4):470-481.
    Traditional empiricist analyses of the source of scientific objectivity were based on two guiding themes: that a claim can be objective only if it is tested against some independent touchstone, and that observation provides that touchstone. The issue of objectivity arises here only for beliefs that are formulated as propositions or sets of propositions, and the standard view demands that objective beliefs make claims about entities that exist independently of those beliefs, and whose properties can be determined and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. A New Source of Data About Singular Thought.Mihnea D. I. Capraru - 2013 - Philosophia 41 (4):1159-1172.
    Philosophers have justified extant theories of singular thought in at least three ways: they have invoked wide-ranging theories motivated by data from other philosophical areas, they have elicited direct intuitions about which thoughts are singular, and they have subjected propositional attitude reports to tests such as Russellian substitution and Quinean exportation. In these ways, however, we haven’t yet been able to tell what it takes to have singular thoughts, nor have we been able to tell which of our thoughts they (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  75
    Retributivism, Justification and Credence: The Epistemic Argument Revisited.Sofia M. I. Jeppsson - 2020 - Neuroethics 14 (2):177-190.
    Harming other people is prima facie wrong. Unless we can be very certain that doing so is justified under the circumstances, we ought not to do it. In this paper, I argue that we ought to dismantle harsh retributivist criminal justice systems for this reason; we cannot be sufficiently certain that the harm is justified. Gregg Caruso, Ben Vilhauer and others have previously argued for the same conclusion; however, my own version sidesteps certain controversial premises of theirs. Harsh retributivist criminal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  52
    Epistemic concepts: A naturalistic approach.Harold I. Brown - 1991 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 34 (3-4):323 – 351.
    Several forms of naturalism are currently extant. Proponents of the various approaches disagree on matters of strategy and detail but one theme is common: we have not received any revelations about the nature of the world -- including our own nature. Whatever knowledge we have has been acquired through a fallible process of conjecture and revision. This common theme will bring to mind the writings of Karl Popper and, in many respects, Popper is the father of contemporary naturalism. Along with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49. The Subject of Black Subjectivity.I. I. Victor Peterson - forthcoming - Human Affairs.
    In multiple essays, CLR James lays out what a theory of subjectivity must account for to resolve issues stemming from reducing subjectivity to a singular identity. Most proposals for a theory of subjectivity do so by making the subject the object of another’s propositions or claims about the world. I argue that this is an identity claim. The converse of this process is also true, that the subject who claims another as the object of their proposition must also be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  10
    A Ruscello on Russell [review of Michele di Francesco, Introduzione a Russell and Il realismo analytico: logica, ontologica e significato nel primo Russell ].I. Grattan-Guinness - 1992 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 12 (2):222-223.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:222 Reviews A RUSCELLO ON RUSSELL I. GRATTAN-GUINNESS Faculty ofScience, Engineering and Mathematics Middlesex Polytechnic Enfield, Middlesex l!N3 4SF, England Michele di Francesco. Introduzione a Russell (I Filosofi, Vol. 53.) Rome and Bari: Laterza, 1990. Pp. viii, 200. 16,000 Lire. -. II Realismo analitico: logica, ontologia e significato nel primo Russell (Saggi, Vol. 28.) Milan: Guerini, 1991. Pp. 269. 30,000 Lire. Italy has long enjoyed a tradition of work (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 986