51 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Kenneth P. Winkler [49]Kenneth Winkler [7]Kenneth Park Winkler [1]
  1.  82
    Berkeley: An Interpretation.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    David Hume wrote that Berkeley's arguments `admit of no answer but produce no conviction'. This book aims at the kind of understanding of Berkeley's philosophy that comes from seeing how we ourselves might be brought to embrace it. Berkeley held that matter does not exist, and that the sensations we take to be caused by an indifferent and independent world are instead caused directly by God. Nature becomes a text, with no existence apart from the spirits who transmit and receive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  2. The new Hume.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (4):541-579.
  3. (1 other version)Locke on personal identity.Kenneth Winkler - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (2):201-226.
  4.  63
    The Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy.Kenneth P. Winkler, Anne Conway, Allison P. Coudert & Taylor Corse - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (4):585.
    Anne Conway’s Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy, first published in 1690, is probably the most ambitious contribution to early modern metaphysics by a woman writing in the English language. This beautifully prepared edition makes Conway’s treatise available to twentieth-century readers in an accessible English translation of the 1690 Latin text—itself a translation of an original English manuscript that has long been lost.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  5.  54
    Berkeley and the doctrine of signs.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2005 - In The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 125.
  6.  50
    An Essay Concerning Human Understanding: Abridged and Edited, with an Introduction and Notes.Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.) - 1996 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    Includes generous selections from the Essay, topically arranged passages from the replies to Stillingfleet, a chronology, a bibliography, a glossary, and an index based on the entries that Locke himself devised.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7. “All Is Revolution in Us”: Personal Identity in Shaftesbury and Hume.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2000 - Hume Studies 26 (1):3-40.
    Even philosophers who believe there is a single “problem of personal identity” conceive of that problem in different ways. They differ not only in their ways of stating the problem, but in the parts of philosophy to which they assign it, and in the resources they feel entitled to call upon in their attempts to deal with it. My topic in this paper is an eighteenth-century uncertainty about the place within philosophy of the problem of personal identity. Is it a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8.  55
    Hutcheson's alleged realism.Kenneth Winkler - 1985 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 23 (2):179-194.
  9.  71
    The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley.Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.) - 2005 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    George Berkeley is one of the greatest and most influential modern philosophers. In defending the immaterialism for which he is most famous, he redirected modern thinking about the nature of objectivity and the mind's capacity to come to terms with it. Along the way, he made striking and influential proposals concerning the psychology of the senses, the workings of language, the aims of science, and the scope of mathematics. In this Companion volume a team of distinguished authors not only examines (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10. Ideas, Sentiments, and Qualities.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1992 - In Phillip D. Cummins (ed.), Minds, Ideas, and Objects: Essays on the Theory of Representation in Modern Philosophy. Ridgeview Publishing Company.
  11. Kant, the empiricists, and the enterprise of deduction.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2010 - In Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  12.  40
    The Empiricists: Critical Essays on Locke, Berkeley, and Hume.M. R. Ayers, Phillip D. Cummins, Robert Fogelin, Don Garrett, Edwin McCann, Charles J. McCracken, George Pappas, G. A. J. Rogers, Barry Stroud, Ian Tipton, Margaret D. Wilson & Kenneth Winkler - 1998 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    This collection of essays on themes in the work of John Locke , George Berkeley , and David Hume , provides a deepened understanding of major issues raised in the Empiricist tradition. In exploring their shared belief in the experiential nature of mental constructs, The Empiricists illuminates the different methodologies of these great Enlightenment philosophers and introduces students to important metaphysical and epistemological issues including the theory of ideas, personal identity, and skepticism. It will be especially useful in courses devoted (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Berkeley and Kant.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2008 - In Daniel Garber & Béatrice Longuenesse (eds.), Kant and the Early Moderns. Princeton University Press.
  14.  55
    (1 other version)Continuous Creation1.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2011 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 35 (1):287-309.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Hume and the sensible qualities.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2011 - In Lawrence Nolan (ed.), Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
  16. Berkeley on Abstract Ideas.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1983 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 65 (1):63-80.
    There are three propositions that this author demonstrates in his argument: the contention that berkeley 's attack on abstract ideas is not made wholly compatible with his atomic sensationalism, that berkeley does not provide or employ a single definition or criterion for determining the limit of abstraction and that the doctrine of abstract ideas furnishes no real support to berkeley 's argument against the existence of material substance independent of perception.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  58
    Hutcheson and Hume on the Color of Virtue.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1996 - Hume Studies 22 (1):3-22.
  18. "Creative Translation in Emerson's Idealism".Kenneth P. Winkler - 2023 - In Thomas Nolden (ed.), In the Face of Adversity: Translating Difference and Dissent. UCL Press. pp. 237-253.
    I consider Ralph Waldo Emerson’s creative appropriation of a philosophical doctrine that helps to make sense of an attitude towards life, its gifts and its burdens, that is often expressed in Puritan diaries. The doctrine, now known as the doctrine of continuous creation, holds that in conserving the world, God re-creates it at every moment, making the same creative effort at each ever-advancing now that God made at the very beginning. Continuous creation was explicitly endorsed by at least one Puritan (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  71
    Berkeley, Pyrrhonism, and the Theaetetus.Kenneth Winkler - 2004 - In Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian skepticism. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 48--54.
    This essay reinterprets Berkeley’s idealism as partially motivated by a need to overcome the Agrippan mode of relativity pressed by Pyrrhonists. It compares Berkeley’s solution to that of Protagoras as presented in Plato’s Theaetetus, and argues that Berkeley needed to depend on reason — intuition or demonstration — to avoid skepticism. In this interpretation, Berkeley is closer to the rationalist tradition than usually recognized.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20. Signification, intention, projection.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2009 - Philosophia 37 (3):477-501.
    Locke is what present-day aestheticians, critics, and historians call an intentionalist. He believes that when we interpret speech and writing, we aim—in large part and perhaps even for the most part—to recover the intentions, or intended meanings, of the speaker or writer. Berkeley and Hume shared Locke’s commitment to intentionalism, but it is a theme that recent philosophical interpreters of all three writers have left largely unexplored. In this paper I discuss the bearing of intentionalism on more familiar themes in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  15
    Chapter 8. Berkeley and Kant.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2008 - In Daniel Garber & Béatrice Longuenesse (eds.), Kant and the Early Moderns. Princeton University Press. pp. 142-171.
  22. Lockean Logic.”.Kenneth Winkler - 2003 - In Peter R. Anstey (ed.), The Philosophy of John Locke: New Perspectives. New York: Routledge. pp. 154--78.
  23.  21
    Locke on Essence and the Social Construction of Kinds.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2015 - In Matthew Stuart (ed.), A Companion to Locke. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Blackwell. pp. 212–235.
    Genesis suggests that God is the creator of kinds. Kinds as Locke understands them are what are nowadays called "social constructions". They are social constructions because the boundaries between them reflect our interests, perspectives, and desires, but in Locke's view those boundaries are not altogether arbitrary, because they also reflect natural or God‐given similarities among things. This chapter looks more closely at the story of creation, and explains how, in John Locke's view, kinds in particular, those kinds whose members Locke (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  6
    Abstract Ideas.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    If representation is resemblance, how we do we think of groups or classes of things? According to a tradition Berkeley opposed—a tradition represented by Locke—we do so by forming abstract or incomplete ideas. I show that Berkeley's opposition does not depend on his own personal failure to form abstract images, but on what he took to be the impersonal or objective impossibility of abstract objects. Berkeley himself accounts for general thinking not in terms of abstract or incomplete ideas, but in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  20
    A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge..Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.) - 1982 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    Kenneth Winkler's esteemed edition of Berkeley's _Principles_ is based on the second edition, the last one published in Berkeley's lifetime. Life other members of Hackett's philosophical classics series, it features editorial elements found to be of particular value to students and their teachers: analytical table of contents; chronology of the author's life; selected bibliography; note on the text; glossary; and index.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. (1 other version)Berkeley, Newton and the Stars.Kenneth Winkler - 1985 - Proceedings of the Heraclitean Society 10:57-79.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  63
    Berkeley on Volition, Power, and the Complexity of Causation.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1985 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (1):53 - 69.
  28.  67
    British Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century by Sarah Hutton.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (4):677-678.
    Most of our histories of philosophy, in our books and especially in our courses, are what William James called “appreciative chronicle[s] of human master-strokes”. They resemble tours of grand and isolated monuments. Sarah Hutton’s magnificent British Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century is a different kind of history, in which masterpieces are placed in conversation with books that are now neglected or all but forgotten. By means of this “conversation model,” Hutton provides what she justly terms “a ‘thick description’ of seventeenth-century (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  7
    Corpuscularianism.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    After describing the corpuscularian background of Berkeley's work, I consider whether Berkeley can endorse the existence of immaterial atoms or corpuscles. I suggest that he hopes to avoid a definite commitment. He wants his position to ‘float’, its level to be determined by the kind of empirical evidence that would strike materialists and immaterialists with equal force. This chapter foregrounds the role played by the notion of intelligibility, both in the defence of modern corpuscularian science and in Berkeley's critical response (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  7
    Cause and Effect.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Berkeley holds that only spirits can be causes. I trace this conclusion to his belief that minds or spirits are able to render their effects intelligible in a way that unthinking things cannot. Causes and their effects are not necessarily connected, in Berkeley's view, but there is more to causation than constant conjunction or regular association.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  42
    Descartes and the Names of God.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1993 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 67 (4):451-466.
  32. Empiricism and Multiculturalism.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2004 - Philosophic Exchange 34 (1).
    This paper relates the work of the great British empiricists – Locke, Berkeley, and Hume – to issues of multiculturalism. It is argued that these philosophers can help to provide us with some of the tools we need to craft an appropriate response to the diversity of cultures.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  66
    Early Modern Intentionalism: Replies to LoLordo’s Comments.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2009 - Philosophia 37 (3):507-509.
    I clarify Locke’s intentionalism and explain what we might gain by paying more attention to the role of linguistic intentions in the work of the British empiricists.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  56
    Grades of cartesian innateness.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1993 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 1 (2):23 – 44.
  35.  16
    Hume’s Skeptical Logic of Induction.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2016 - In Paul Russell (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of David Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    For Hume, one task of logic is “to explain the principles and operations of our reasoning faculties”; this chapter is a study of his logic of inductive reasoning, as presented in Book I of his Treatise and in the Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Like other early modern logics—especially those composed, as Hume’s was, under the influence of Locke—Hume’s logic is descriptive, explanatory, and normative. It also aspires to be revelatory. It is descriptive in documenting how our reasoning actually proceeds, explanatory (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  12
    Immaterialism.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This chapter reviews and assesses Berkeley's main arguments for immaterialism, his arguments against the existence of matter or material substance. I place particular emphasis on the themes of earlier chapters: intentionality, abstraction, necessity, and intelligibility. My aim is to show that Berkeley's thinking about these topics made a powerful contribution to his immaterialism, even if they seem, on the surface, to be distant from it. I provide an account of immediate perception as Berkeley understands it, and emphasize the phenomenalist elements (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  9
    Necessity.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    I suggest that in his early, unpublished notebooks, Berkeley experimented with a radically formal conception of necessity, according to which necessity is nothing more than the inclusion of one idea within the definition of another. Berkeley's experiment was defeated by the same objective connections that rule out the existence of simple ideas. Although Berkeley was left without an understanding of the nature of necessity, he never wavered in his conviction that necessity is something objective—that ideas and the world have an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  6
    Spirit.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    I offer an interpretation and partial defence of Berkeley's belief that he is a mind or spirit—a spiritual substance—distinct from his ideas. I argue in particular that the arguments examined in earlier chapters, particularly the account of representation or intentionality developed in Ch. 1, and the immaterialist arguments reviewed in Ch. 6, do not force Berkeley to conclude that spiritual substance is no less impossible than matter.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  74
    Scepticism and anti-realism.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1985 - Mind 94 (373):36-52.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  10
    Simple Ideas.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Many empiricists, among them Locke and Hume, make a distinction between simple and complex ideas. Berkeley refuses to do so, because he finds connections—objective connections incompatible with simplicity—even among the ‘simplest’ of ideas. Simple ideas, in his view, are illegitimately abstract.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  6
    Unperceived Objects.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This is the first of three chapters examining the consequences of Berkeley's immaterialism and the problems to which it gives rise. In the present chapter, I defend a phenomenalist interpretation of Berkeley on unperceived objects. Appealing to his denial of blind agency, I show that a phenomenalist interpretation can be reconciled with texts that seem to go against it. I provide a modest interpretation of Berkeley's doctrine of archetypes, and argue briefly that even in Siris, Berkeley's doctrine of archetypes is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  40
    Van Cleve and Reid on Conceptions and Qualities.Kenneth P. Winkler - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (1):225-231.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  7
    Words and Ideas.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This chapter explores the difference between two kinds of signs that Berkeley followed Locke in recognizing: words and ideas. I argue that Berkeley does not assume that ideas are images of things but concludes it, as part of a deliberate attempt to explain how at least some of our thoughts succeed in referring to the world. For Berkeley, representation—the intentionality or ‘aboutness’ of thought—is sometimes a matter of resemblance.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  59
    Berkeley. [REVIEW]Kenneth P. Winkler - 1992 - Idealistic Studies 22 (3):300-301.
    Emerson said that idealism sees the world in God: not as “painfully accumulated, atom after atom, act after act, in a aged creeping Past,” but as “a vast picture” painted by God “on the instant eternity.” Emerson’s portrait fits A.C. Grayling’s Berkeley, who sees the world in an infinite spirit whose power is unfailing and ubiquitous. Berkeley’s arguments, Grayling suggests, move at three levels, and at the metaphysical level, God’s activity accounts for what occurs at the level of sensory experience (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  30
    (2 other versions)Essays on Berkeley: A Tercentennial Celebration. [REVIEW]Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - Noûs 23 (2):263-265.
  46.  31
    Hume's System: An Examination of the First Book of His Treatise. [REVIEW]Kenneth P. Winkler - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (4):755-762.
  47.  25
    Berkeley: An Introduction. [REVIEW]Kenneth P. Winkler - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (2):329.
  48.  55
    Berkeley's Idealism: A Critical Examination. [REVIEW]Kenneth P. Winkler - 2014 - Philosophical Review 123 (4):541-544.
  49.  64
    Colin Turbayne, ed., "Berkeley: Critical and Interpretive Essays". [REVIEW]Kenneth Winkler - 1984 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 22 (3):372.
  50.  55
    Locke's Philosophy of Language ‐ By Walter Ott. [REVIEW]Kenneth P. Winkler - 2007 - Philosophical Books 48 (1):76-78.
1 — 50 / 51