Results for 'Strict laws'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  33
    Systems of measurement.Stephen Law - 2005 - Ratio 18 (2):145–164.
    Wittgenstein and Kripke disagree about the status of the proposition: the Standard Metre is one metre long. Wittgenstein believes it is necessary. Kripke argues that it is contingent. Kripke's argument depends crucially on a certain sort of thought‐experiment with which we are invited to test our intuitions about what is and isn’t necessary. In this paper I argue that, while Kripke's conclusion is strictly correct, nevertheless similar Kripke‐style thought experiments indicate that the metric system of measurement is after all relative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. The irrelevance of direction of fit.Iain Law - unknown
    The so-called ‘Humean’ view of motivation is pretty standard in the Philosophy of Mind. Its most prominent contemporary defender, Michael Smith, calls it a ‘dogma’. Humeans believe in a strict divide between beliefs and desires. Beliefs have no intrinsic motivating force: I may believe anything at all, but only with the contribution of a separate desire will I be motivated to act. This claim should be broadened out to include all cognitive states (belief, knowledge…). The Humean claim is that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Can supervenience and "non-strict laws" save anomalous monism?Jaegwon Kim - 1993 - In John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford University Press. pp. 19--26.
  4. The Unity of strict law: a comparative study dedicated to the memory of Jean Dabin.Jean Dabin & Ralph Abraham Newman (eds.) - 1978 - Brussels: Emile Bruylant.
  5. There may be strict empirical laws in biology, after all.Mehmet Elgin - 2006 - Biology and Philosophy 21 (1):119-134.
    This paper consists of four parts. Part 1 is an introduction. Part 2 evaluates arguments for the claim that there are no strict empirical laws in biology. I argue that there are two types of arguments for this claim and they are as follows: (1) Biological properties are multiply realized and they require complex processes. For this reason, it is almost impossible to formulate strict empirical laws in biology. (2) Generalizations in biology hold contingently but (...) go beyond describing contingencies, so there cannot be strict laws in biology. I argue that both types of arguments fail. Part 3 considers some examples of biological laws in recent biological research and argues that they exemplify strict laws in biology. Part 4 considers the objection that the examples in part 3 may be strict laws but they are not distinctively biological laws. I argue that given a plausible account of what distinctively biological means, such laws are distinctively biological. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  6. Strict Liability for Criminal Offences in England and Wales Following Incorporation into English Law of the European Convention on Human Rights.G. R. Sullivan - 2005 - In Andrew Simester (ed.), Appraising Strict Liability. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  15
    Strictly Institutionalized Sources of Law: Some Further Thoughts.Roger A. Shiner - 2007 - Ratio Juris 20 (2):310-324.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Singular causal statements and strict deterministic laws.Noa Latham - 1987 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 68 (1):29-43.
  9.  10
    A Theory of Strict Liability: Toward a Reformulation of Tort Law.Richard Allen Epstein - 1980 - Cato Inst.
    Errata slip inserted. Bibliography: p. 137-140.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  23
    On the Use of Strict Liability in the Criminal Law.Christine T. Sistare - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2):395 - 407.
    A highly controversial issue in criminal law theory has been the use of strict liability offenses, i.e., offenses which create liability ‘without fault.’ The collection of strict liability offenses is varied according to the element of the particular offense with respect to which liability is strict. For example, a statute prohibiting the filing of a false financial statement with the Secretary of State might impose liability despite a reasonable error as to the truth of the statement, or (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Approaches to Strict and Constructive Liability in Continental Criminal Law.John R. Spencer & Antje Pedain - 2005 - In Andrew Simester (ed.), Appraising Strict Liability. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  14
    How Hume and Kant Reconstruct Natural Law: Justifying Strict Objectivity Without Debating Moral Realism.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2016 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK.
    Kenneth R. Westphal presents an original interpretation of Hume's and Kant's moral philosophies, the differences between which are prominent in current philosophical accounts. Westphal argues that focussing on these differences, however, occludes a decisive, shared achievement: a distinctive constructivist account of the basic principles of justice which justifies their strict objectivity without invoking moral realism nor moral anti- or irrealism. Westphal explores how Hume developed a kind of constructivism for basic property rights and for government, and how Kant greatly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  13.  97
    Reconsidering the Relationship among Voluntary Acts, Strict Liability, and Negligence in Criminal Law.Larry Alexander - 1990 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (2):84.
    This essay, as will become obvious, owes a huge debt to Mark Kelman, particularly to his article “Interpretative Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law.” That debt is one of both concept and content. There is rich irony in my aping Kelman's deconstructionist enterprise, for I do not share his enthusiasm for either the “insights” or the political agenda of the Critical Legal Studies movement. I do not believe that either the law in general or the criminal law in particular is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14.  31
    The Laws of Robots: Crimes, Contracts, and Torts.Ugo Pagallo - 2013 - Dordrecht: Imprint: Springer.
    This book explores how the design, construction, and use of robotics technology may affect today's legal systems and, more particularly, matters of responsibility and agency in criminal law, contractual obligations, and torts. By distinguishing between the behaviour of robots as tools of human interaction, and robots as proper agents in the legal arena, jurists will have to address a new generation of "hard cases." General disagreement may concern immunity in criminal law (e.g., the employment of robot soldiers in battle), personal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  15.  65
    Strict moral liability.Justin A. Capes - 2019 - Social Philosophy and Policy 36 (1):52-71.
    :Strict liability in tort law is thought by some to have a moral counterpart. In this essay I attempt to determine whether there is, in fact, strict liability in the moral domain. I argue that there is, and I critically evaluate several accounts of its normative foundations before suggesting one of my own.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16.  18
    Law's meaning of life: philosophy, religion, Darwin, and the legal person.Ngaire Naffine - 2009 - Portland, Or.: Hart.
    The perennial question posed by the philosophically-inclined lawyer is 'What is law?' or perhaps 'What is the nature of law?' This book poses an associated, but no less fundamental, question about law which has received much less attention in the legal literature. It is: 'Who is law for?' Whenever people go to law, they are judged for their suitability as legal persons. They are given or refused rights and duties on the basis of ideas about who matters. These ideas are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  17.  72
    Appraising Strict Liability.Andrew Simester (ed.) - 2005 - Oxford University Press.
    This book is a collection of original essays offering the first full-length consideration of the problem of strict liability in the criminal law: that is, the problem of criminal offences that allow a defendant to be convicted without proof of fault. Because of its potential to convict blameless persons, strict liability is a highly controversial phenomenon in the criminal law. Including Anglo-American and European perspectives, the contributions provide a sustained and wide-ranging examination of the fundamental issues. The breadth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  36
    Can Strict Criminal Liability for Responsible Corporate Officers be Justified by the Duty to Use Extraordinary Care?Kenneth W. Simons - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):439-454.
    The responsible corporate officer doctrine is, as a formal matter, an instance of strict criminal liability: the government need not prove the defendant’s mens rea in order to obtain a conviction, and the defendant may not escape conviction by proving lack of mens rea. Formal strict liability is sometimes consistent with retributive principles, especially when the strict liability pertains to the grading of an offense. But is strict liability consistent with retributive principles when it pertains, not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  11
    A Different Kind Of War: Internet databases and legal protection or how the strict intellectual property laws of the West threaten the developing countries’ information commons.Maria Canellopoulou-Bottis - 2004 - International Review of Information Ethics 2.
    This paper describes intellectual property legislation in the European Union, the US and the Draft Treaty on the legal protection of unoriginal databases, usually available in the Internet. I argue that this type of legislation, if enforced upon developing countries and countries in transition through international ‘agreements’, could in effect deprive them of their own information commons, their own public domain. With examples from China, India, Africa and Iceland, I argue that this deprivation in the case of developing countries is, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  96
    The philosophy of criminal law: selected essays.Douglas N. Husak - 2010 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Does criminal liability require an act? -- Motive and criminal liability -- The costs to criminal theory of supposing that intentions are irrelevant to permissibility -- Transferred intent -- The nature and justifiability of nonconsummate offenses -- Strict liability, justice, and proportionality -- The sequential principle of relative culpability -- Willful ignorance, knowledge, and the equal culpability thesis : a study of the significance of the principle of legality -- Rapes without rapists : consent and reasonable mistake -- Mistake (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  21. Richard Epstein and the Theory of Strict Liability in Tort Law.Thomas Fay - 1992 - Reason Papers 17:29-38.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  19
    Strict Joint and Several Liability and Justice.D. R. Cooley - 2003 - Journal of Business Ethics 47 (3):199-208.
    The American tort system regularly conducts a sort of lottery in which plaintiffs try to name as many defendants in a tort action as they can in order to collect a large judgment from at least one of them. This procedure is encouraged under strict joint and several liability, which permits plaintiffs to recover greater damages from defendants - usually businesses - with less moral culpability for the tort than poorer defendants, who bear greater culpability. In a case involving (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  61
    The Strictness of Strict Liability.Michael S. Moore - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):513-529.
    This article conceptualizes what strict liability is in the criminal law. Four properties are found to be individually necessary, only jointly sufficient, for there to be the kind of moral blameworthiness that must underlie any just punishment: prima facie wrongdoing, absence of justification, prima facie culpability, and absence of excuse. Whenever criminal liability is imposed without the presence of one or more of these properties, the liabuility is said to be strict.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  98
    Strict responsibility, moral and criminal.R. A. Duff - 2009 - Journal of Value Inquiry 43 (3):295-313.
  25.  35
    Strict Naturalism and Christianity: Attempt at Drafting an Updated Theology of Nature.Rudolf B. Brun - 2007 - Zygon 42 (3):701-714.
    . In the first part of this essay I sketch a view on cosmogenesis from the perspective of modern science, emphasizing, first, that the laws of nature are outcomes of the history of nature, not imposed on nature from outside of nature; and, second, that the universe, including human beings, is the result of a single, natural process. It consistently brings forth novelty through a probabilistic sequence of syntheses. Consequently, the new emerges from the unification of elements that were (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  15
    On Law and Reason.Aleksander Peczenik - 1989 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    a This is an outline of a coherence theory of law. Its basic ideas are: reasonable support and weighing of reasons. All the rest is commentary.a (TM) These words at the beginning of the preface of this book perfectly indicate what On Law and Reason is about. It is a theory about the nature of the law which emphasises the role of reason in the law and which refuses to limit the role of reason to the application of deductive logic. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  27.  31
    Does strict judicial scrutiny involve thetu quoque fallacy?George Schedler - 1990 - Law and Philosophy 9 (3):269 - 283.
    To protect what it deems fundamental rights, the Supreme Court strictly scrutinizes legislation that impinges on these rights. The Court views such legislation as a means to some end the legislation seeks to accomplish. The Court requires that the statute be neither overinclusive nor underinclusive; the legislation may not affect more people than necessary to achieve its end, nor is the statute permitted to leave some people out in achieving its end.I argue that when legislation imposes burdens, its underinclusiveness is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  14
    Strict Liability’s Criminogenic Effect.Paul H. Robinson - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):411-426.
    It is easy to understand the apparent appeal of strict liability to policymakers and legal reformers seeking to reduce crime: if the criminal law can do away with its traditional culpability requirement, it can increase the likelihood of conviction and punishment of those who engage in prohibited conduct or bring about prohibited harm or evil. And such an increase in punishment rate can enhance the crime-control effectiveness of a system built upon general deterrence or incapacitation of the dangerous. Similar (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Law as a Test of Conceptual Strength.Matthieu Queloz - forthcoming - In Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco, Daniel Peixoto Murata & Julieta A. Rabanos (eds.), Bernard Williams on Law and Jurisprudence: From Agency and Responsibility to Methodology.
    In ‘What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?’, Bernard Williams reaffirms J. L. Austin’s suggestion that philosophy might learn from tort law ‘the difference between practical reality and philosophical frivolity’. Yet while Austin regarded tort law as just another repository of time-tested concepts, on a par with common sense as represented by a dictionary, Williams argues that ‘the use of certain ideas in the law does more to show that those ideas have strength than is done by the mere (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  30
    Wright’s Strict Finitistic Logic in the Classical Metatheory: The Propositional Case.Takahiro Yamada - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (4).
    Crispin Wright in his 1982 paper argues for strict finitism, a constructive standpoint that is more restrictive than intuitionism. In its appendix, he proposes models of strict finitistic arithmetic. They are tree-like structures, formed in his strict finitistic metatheory, of equations between numerals on which concrete arithmetical sentences are evaluated. As a first step towards classical formalisation of strict finitism, we propose their counterparts in the classical metatheory with one additional assumption, and then extract the propositional (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  46
    Strict Confidentiality: An Alternative to Pre’s “Limited Confidentiality” Doctrine. [REVIEW]John Lowman & Ted Palys - 2007 - Journal of Academic Ethics 5 (2-4):163-177.
    In “Advisory Opinion on Confidentiality, Its Limits and Duties to Others” the Canadian Interagency Advisory Panel on Research Ethics (PRE) articulates a rationale for a priori limitations to research confidentiality, based largely on putative legal duties to violate confidentiality in certain circumstances. We argue that PRE promotes a “Law of the Land” doctrine of research ethics that is but one approach to resolving potential conflicts between law and research ethics. PRE emphasises risks that have never materialized, and ignores jurisprudence on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  20
    Dixonian Strict Legalism, Wilson v Darling Island Stevedoring and Contracting in the Real World.John Gava - 2010 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 30 (3):519-543.
    Abstract—How do judges decide cases? Are judges controlled by rules, principles and professional standards of reasoning or do they decide as politicians, using the law as an instrument to achieve predetermined goals. In Australia one influential view on this issue was expressed by Sir Owen Dixon when he called for a ‘strict and complete legalism’ for judges. Dixon’s strict legalism no longer commands the respect that it once did and his view is now commonly seen as naïve or (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  5
    The Type Theory of Law: An Essay in Psychoanalytic Jurisprudence.Marko Novak - 2016 - Cham: Imprint: Springer.
    This volume presents a Type Theory of Law (TTL), claiming that this is a unique theory of law that stems from the philosophical understanding of Jung's psychological types applied to the phenomenon of law. Furthermore, the TTL claims to be a universal, general and descriptive account of law. To prove that, the book first presents the fundamentals of Jungian psychological types, as they had been invented by Jung and consequently developed further by his followers. The next part of the book (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  6
    The Strict and Broad Views of Intention Again.Patrick Lee - 2022 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 22 (3):479-494.
    I reply to Steven Jensen’s article, “Phoenix Rising from the Ashes: Recent Attempts to Revive New Natural Law Action Theory,” which appeared in this journal in 2020. His arguments helpfully clarify where the disagreements between the strict and broad views of intention lie but, I argue, fail to refute the arguments and explanations he criticizes. I argue he misinterprets the strict view’s reference to necessity in its criterion for what is intended. I also argue against what he labels (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  44
    On Logic of Strictly-Deontic Modalities. A Semantic and Tableau Approach.Tomasz Jarmużek & Mateusz Klonowski - 2020 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 29 (3):335–380.
    Standard deontic logic (SDL) is defined on the basis of possible world semantics and is a logic of alethic-deontic modalities rather than deontic modalities alone. The interpretation of the concepts of obligation and permission comes down exclusively to the logical value that a sentence adopts for the accessible deontic alternatives. Here, we set forth a different approach, this being a logic which additionally takes into consideration whether sentences stand in relation to the normative system or to the system of values (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  36. On the Distinction Between Law Schemata and Causal Laws.Jens Harbecke - 2013 - Acta Analytica 28 (4):423-434.
    The paper argues against the widely accepted assumption that the causal laws of (completed) physics, in contrast to those of the special sciences, are essentially strict. This claim played an important role already in debates about the anomalousness of the mental, and it currently experiences a renaissance in various discussions about mental causation, projectability of special science laws, and the nature of physical laws. By illustrating the distinction with some paradigmatic physical laws, the paper demonstrates (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  32
    Strict Liability and the Paradoxes of Proportionality.Leo Katz & Alvaro Sandroni - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):365-373.
    This essay explores the case against strict liability offenses as part of the more general debate about proportional punishment. This debate takes on a very different look in light of a formal result derived by the authors elsewhere, that is briefly summarized and whose implications are pursued here. Traditional objections that consequentialists have mounted against the deontologists’/retributivists’ defense of proportionality fall by the wayside, but a new threat to the proportionality requirement replaces it: the ease with which any such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  44
    Violating Strict Deontological Constraints: Excuse or Pardon?Rudolf Schuessler - 2015 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (4):587-601.
    Deontologists often assume that ethical constraints hold ‘come what may’ but that violations of the constraints can be excused or pardoned. Vinit Haksar has argued for pardon as deontologically appropriate mitigation for the violation of deontological constraints. However, the reasons he adduces against excuse are inconclusive. In this paper, I show how complex the question of excuse versus pardon for deontological transgressions is. Liability for the development of character traits and the assumption of agent-centered responsibility have to be taken into (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  20
    A strictly geometric interpretation of gravitation in general relativity.J. P. Kobus - 1973 - Foundations of Physics 3 (1):45-51.
    A geometric interpretation of gravitation is given using general relativity. The law of gravitation is taken in the formR 44=0, whereR 44is the component of the contracted Riemann-Christoffel (Ricci) tensor representing the curvature of time. The remaining curvature components of the contracted Riemann-Christoffel tensor may or may not vanish. All that is required in addition toR 44=0 is that the Gaussian curvatureR be nowhere infinite. The conditionR 44=0 yields a nonlinear wave equation. One of the static degenerate solutions represents the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  20
    Kenneth Westphal, How Hume and Kant Reconstruct Natural Law: Justifying Strict Objectivity without Debating Moral Realism Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016 Pp. 208 ISBN 9780198747055 $65.00. [REVIEW]Frederick Rauscher - 2018 - Kantian Review 23 (3):491-496.
  41. Occasionalism and strict mechanism: Malebranche, Berkeley, fontenelle.Lisa Downing - 2005 - In Christia Mercer (ed.), Early Modern Philosophy: Mind, Matter, and Metaphysics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 206-230.
    The rich connections between metaphysics and natural philosophy in the early modern period have been widely acknowledged and productively mined, thanks in no small part to the work of Margaret Wilson, whose book, Descartes, served as an inspirational example for a generation of scholars. The task of this paper is to investigate one particular such connection, namely, the relation between occasionalist metaphysics and strict mechanism. My focus will be on the work of Nicholas Malebranche, the most influential Cartesian philosopher (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42.  58
    Common-law judicial reasoning and analogy.Adam Rigoni - 2014 - Legal Theory 20 (2):133-156.
    Proponents of strict rule-based theories of judicial reasoning in common-law systems have offered a number of criticisms of analogical alternatives. I explain these criticisms and show that at best they apply equally well to rule-based theories. Further, I show how the analogical theories explain a feature of judicial common-law reasoningthat rule-based theories ignore. Finally, I show that reason-based, analogical theories of common-law judicial reasoning, such as those offered by John Horty and Grant Lamond, offer especially strong rejoinders to the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  43.  12
    Natural Law and Public Reason.Robert P. George & Christopher Wolfe - 2000 - Georgetown University Press.
    "Public reason" is one of the central concepts in modern liberal political theory. As articulated by John Rawls, it presents a way to overcome the difficulties created by intractable differences among citizens' religious and moral beliefs by strictly confining the place of such convictions in the public sphere. Identifying this conception as a key point of conflict, this book presents a debate among contemporary natural law and liberal political theorists on the definition and validity of the idea of public reason. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  44. Grounding, metaphysical laws, and structure.Martin Grajner - 2021 - Analytic Philosophy 62 (4):376-395.
    According to the deductive-nomological account of ground, a fact A grounds another fact B in case the laws of metaphysics determine the existence of B on the basis of the existence of A. Accounts of grounding of this particular variety have already been developed in the literature. My aim in this paper is to sketch a new version of this account. My preferred account offers two main improvements over existing accounts. First, the present account is able to deal with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  18
    Laws, Exceptions and Dispositions.Max Kistler - 2020 - JOLMA 1 (1):53-74.
    Can laws of nature be universal regularities and nevertheless have exceptions? Several answers to this question, in particular the thesis that there are no laws outside of fundamental physics, are examined and rejected. It is suggested that one can account for exceptions by conceiving of laws as strictly universal determination relations between (instances of) properties. When a natural property is instantiated, laws of nature give rise to other, typically dispositional properties. In exceptional situations, such properties manifest (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Do Ceteris Paribus Laws Exist? A Regularity-Based Best System Analysis.Matthias Unterhuber - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (S10):1833-1847.
    This paper argues that ceteris paribus (cp) laws exist based on a Lewisian best system analysis of lawhood (BSA). Furthermore, it shows that a BSA faces a second trivialization problem besides the one identified by Lewis. The first point concerns an argument against cp laws by Earman and Roberts. The second point aims to help making some assumptions of the BSA explicit. To address the second trivialization problem, a restriction in terms of natural logical constants is proposed that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  47.  28
    The Laws of the Unspoken: Silence and Secrecy.Patrick Tacussel - 1988 - Diogenes 36 (144):16-31.
    Of silence, paradoxically, one can only speak. By virtue of the alliance that unites reason and language, the capacity to name and to address indeed obeys a certain desire to restrain excessive communication. Laughter, tears and silence are part of the expressive world: however, they attest to the impossible pitfall of words in the socializing function that we accord them. Of extreme sociality, of meaning that exceeds the bearable, the suitability and the commerce of ideas, the only thing that rises (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. The nature of laws.Michael Tooley - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):667-98.
    This paper is concerned with the question of the truth conditions of nomological statements. My fundamental thesis is that it is possible to set out an acceptable, noncircular account of the truth conditions of laws and nomological statements if and only if relations among universals - that is, among properties and relations, construed realistically - are taken as the truth-makers for such statements. My discussion will be restricted to strictly universal, nonstatistical laws. The reason for this limitation is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   392 citations  
  49.  77
    Universal Law and Poverty Relief.Oliver Sensen - 2022 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 26 (2):177-190.
    In this article, I examine what Kant’s Formula of Universal Law requires of an individual agent in situations of great need, e.g.: if you can easily help a drowning child, or if you know of a famine situation in another country. I first explain why I do not simply apply the standard interpretation of how one can derive concrete duties from Kant’s Universal Law formulation of the Categorical Imperative. I then glean an alternative procedure from Kant’s texts and give the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  58
    A. P. Simester : Appraising Strict Liability: Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2005, Cdn$150.00, US$95.00, £60.00, ISBN 0-19-927851-2.Roger A. Shiner & Jeremy Hoemsen - 2007 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 1 (1):119-122.
    The article is a review of A.P. Simester, ed., Appraising Strict Liability. We strongly recommend the book for the sophistication of the contributors’ analyses, and the contribution the book makes to clarifying the normative issues at stake in strict liability legal regimes. The review focuses on the more philosophical essays in the book. The specific issues from the book identified in the review are: the rights-based character of the prohibition on conviction without moral fault; the importance of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000