Results for 'death's badness'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Death’s Badness and Time-Relativity: A Reply to Purves.Taylor W. Cyr - 2016 - The Journal of Ethics 20 (4):435-444.
    According to John Martin Fischer and Anthony Brueckner’s unique version of the deprivation approach to accounting for death’s badness, it is rational for us to have asymmetric attitudes toward prenatal and posthumous nonexistence. In previous work, I have defended this approach against a criticism raised by Jens Johansson by attempting to show that Johansson’s criticism relies on an example that is incoherent. Recently, Duncan Purves has argued that my defense reveals an incoherence not only in Johansson’s example but also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  11
    Death's badness.Anthony L. Brueckner & John Martin Fischer - 1993 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (1):37-45.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3.  89
    Is Death's Badness Gendered?Samantha Brennan - 2006 - Dialogue 45 (3):559-566.
  4.  78
    Feldman’s account of death’s badness, and life-death comparatives.John M. Collins - 2005 - Southwest Philosophy Review 21 (2):83-99.
    Deprivation accounts of death's badness, such as Feldman’s (1992), that purport to avoid questionable life-death comparatives Silverstein warns against (1980) by comparing only the values of various alternative life-wholes, implicitly depend upon assigning greater comparative value to periods of these life-wholes (for the person who lives) than is assigned to periods when the person is not alive, and thus are simply special cases of the problematic life-death comparative. Life-death comparatives undermine any deprivation account if (1) there is no (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  54
    The death of Nietzsche's Zarathustra.Paul S. Loeb - 2010 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The eternal recurrence of the same. Simmel's critique ; Awareness ; Evidence ; Significance ; Coherence -- Demon or god? Deathbed revelation ; Daimonic prophecy ; Dionysian doctrine ; Diagnostic test -- The dwarf and the gateway. The gateway to Hades ; The dwarf's interpretation ; Zarathustra's cross-examination ; The inescapable cycle ; Crossing the gateway ; No time until rebirth ; The ancient memory ; Midnight swan song -- The great noon. Two conclusions ; Tragic end and analeptic satyr (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6. A puzzle about death’s badness: Can death be bad for the paradise-bound?Taylor W. Cyr - 2016 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 80 (2):145-162.
    Since at least the time of Epicurus, philosophers have debated whether death could be bad for the one who has died, since death is a permanent experiential blank. But a different puzzle about death’s badness arises when we consider the death of a person who is paradise-bound. The first purpose of this paper is to develop this puzzle. The second purpose of this paper is to suggest and evaluate several potential attempts to solve the puzzle. After rejecting two seemingly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  89
    The Time of Death's Badness.J. Johansson - 2012 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (5):464-479.
    Those who endorse the view that death is in some cases bad for the deceased—a view that, as I shall explain, has considerable bearing on many bioethical issues—need to address the following, Epicurean question: When is death bad for the one who dies? The two most popular answers are "before death" (priorism) and "after death" (subsequentism). Part of the support for these two views consists in the idea that a third answer, "at no time" (atemporalism), makes death unsatisfyingly different from (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8.  20
    Glasgow on Death's Badness and Radiant Value.Ben Bradley - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Research 48:293-300.
    In The Solace, Joshua Glasgow’s main claim is that life has “radiant value” and that death inherits some of that value; this provides us with a source of solace. He also argues that death is bad not only in virtue of depriving us of good things, but also in virtue of depriving us of opportunities for good things. I raise difficulties for these claims.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  67
    Eternalism and death's badness.Ben Bradley - 2010 - In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Harry Silverstein (eds.), Time and Identity. MIT Press.
    This chapter discusses the metaphysical view referred to by Harry Silverstein as “four-dimensionalism,” but referred to in this chapter as “eternalism.” In contrast to presentism, eternalism posits that purely past and purely future objects and events exist. If a person goes out of existence at the moment of death, the problem arises as to how death is bad for its victim. According to Silverstein, this problem arises from the truth of the “Values Connect with Feelings” thesis, according to which it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. Eternalism and death's badness syracuse university.Ben Bradley - unknown
    Suppose that at the moment of death, a person goes out of existence.1 This has been thought to pose a problem for the idea that death is bad for its victim. But what exactly is the problem? Harry Silverstein says the problem stems from the truth of the “Values Connect with Feelings” thesis (VCF), according to which it must be possible for someone to have feelings about a thing in order for that thing to be bad for that person (2000, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Health, Disability, and Well-Being.S. Andrew Schroeder - 2016 - In Guy Fletcher (ed.), Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. Routledge.
    Much academic work (in philosophy, economics, law, etc.), as well as common sense, assumes that ill health reduces well-being. It is bad for a person to become sick, injured, disabled, etc. Empirical research, however, shows that people living with health problems report surprisingly high levels of well-being - in some cases as high as the self-reported well-being of healthy people. In this chapter, I explore the relationship between health and well-being. I argue that although we have good reason to believe (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  8
    Why is death bad and what makes it least bad?Nancy S. Jecker - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (3-4):411-415.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Time-Relative Interests and Abortion.S. Liao - 2007 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 4 (2):242-256.
    The concept of a time-relative interest is introduced by Jeff McMahan to solve certain puzzles about the badness of death. Some people (e.g. McMahan and David DeGrazia) believe that this concept can also be used to show that abortion is permissible. In this paper, I first argue that if the Time-Relative Interest Account permits abortion, then it would also permit infanticide.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. Harvesting the living?: Separating brain death and organ transplantation.Courtney S. Campbell - 2004 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 14 (3):301-318.
    : The chronic shortage of transplantable organs has reached critical proportions. In the wake of this crisis, some bioethicists have argued there is sufficient public support to expand organ recovery through use of neocortical criteria of death or even pre-mortem organ retrieval. I present a typology of ways in which data gathered from the public can be misread or selectively used by bioethicists in service of an ideological or policy agenda, resulting in bad policy and bad ethics. Such risks should (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15.  34
    A Thousand Little Deaths.Lydia S. Dugdale - 2011 - Hastings Center Report 41 (4):10-10.
    Doctor, just one more thing.” I marvel every time I hear this, nearly always as I reach for the door. It is as though all patients receive copies of the same instructions, perhaps posted somewhere in the waiting room: Wait until your appointment has run over time. Watch until your doctor stands to leave. Ask a question of grave importance that cannot possibly be answered quickly. I released the doorknob. “Yes, sir?” “I was wondering if you had any advice for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  26
    Review: Why Is Death Bad and What Makes It Least Bad? [REVIEW]Nancy S. Jecker - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (3/4):411 - 415.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  15
    The Cosmological Argument1: PHEROZE S. WADIA.Pheroze S. Wadia - 1975 - Religious Studies 11 (4):411-420.
    I. Professor William L. Rowe begins an interesting paper on the Cosmological Argument by stating that his ‘purpose …is not to resurrect it’ but ‘to uncover, clarify, and examine some of the philosophical concepts and theses essential to the reasoning exhibited in the argument’. However, in the concluding pages of his paper, Rowe is at some pains to show that his discussion does at least demonstrate that the Cosmological Argument is beyond the reach of criticisms levelled against it in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  7
    Euthanasia: Affect between Art and Opinion in What Is Philosophy?D. J. S. Cross - 2020 - Deleuze and Guattari Studies 14 (2):177-197.
    According to What Is Philosophy?, all disciplines combat opinion, but art fights most effectively because art and opinion both pertain to sensibility. Yet, this common provenance also makes the line dividing art and opinion porous. The stakes of this porosity are perhaps most visible in the relation of art to life. Although art must avoid two forms of death, ‘chaos’ and ‘opinion’, Deleuze and Guattari don't treat chaos and opinion equally. The fundamental distinction between good death and bad death, between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Dissolving Death’s Time-of-Harm Problem.Travis Timmerman - 2022 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 100 (2):405-418.
    Most philosophers in the death literature believe that death can be bad for the person who dies. The most popular view of death’s badness—namely, deprivationism—holds that death is bad for the person who dies because, and to the extent that, it deprives them of the net good that they would have accrued, had their actual death not occurred. Deprivationists thus face the challenge of locating the time that death is bad for a person. This is known as the Timing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  17
    Foucault's Bad Angels of History.Lynne Huffer - 2011 - philoSOPHIA: A Journal of Continental Feminism 1 (2):239-250.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Foucault's Bad Angels of HistoryLynne HufferDo not believe everything I say.... Look for multiple, resistant, rhizomatic readings. This is not the text I intended to produce, and it is not the same as the text you are reading. Read the white spaces, hear the silences, peer into the shadows, look beyond the margins. Reach for "[t]hat voice at the edge of things." I am there as well.—Juana María RodríguezWhat (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Is death a bad thing?Mikel Burley - 2008 - Think 6 (16):59.
    After examining arguments for and against the view that death is a bad thing, Mikel Burley tentatively endorses the Epicurean claim that death cannot rationally be judged bad. For moral reasons, however, this conclusion is acceptable only with regard to one's own death.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. How bad is death?Ben Bradley - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (1):111-127.
    A popular view about why death is bad for the one who dies is that death deprives its subject of the good things in life. This is the “deprivation account” of the evil of death. There is another view about death that seems incompatible with the deprivation account: the view that a person’s death is less bad if she has lived a good life. In The Ethics of Killing, Jeff McMahan argues that a deprivation account should discount the evil of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  23. “I like bad music.” That's my usual response to people who ask me about my musi.Rock Critics Need Bad Music - 2004 - In Christopher Washburne & Maiken Derno (eds.), Bad Music: The Music We Love to Hate. Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  32
    Making Death Not Quite as Bad for the One Who Dies.Kirsten Egerstrom - 2021 - In Michael Cholbi & Travis Timmerman (eds.), Exploring the Philosophy of Death and Dying: Classic and Contemporary Perspectives. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 93-100.
    One popular rival to Epicureanism is deprivationism, which maintains that a person’s death at a given time is bad for her to the extent that, and because, it prevents her from having a longer life that would have been, on the whole, good. Deprivationism has the surprising implication that we can lessen how bad a person’s death is for them by changing the life they would have had if they lived longer (for example, by convincing a person’s favorite author to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Why is death bad?Anthony L. Brueckner & John Martin Fischer - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 50 (2):213-221.
    It seems that, whereas a person's death needn't be a bad thing for him, it can be. In some circumstances, death isn't a "bad thing" or an "evil" for a person. For instance, if a person has a terminal and very painful disease, he might rationally regard his own death as a good thing for him, or at least, he may regard it as something whose prospective occurrence shouldn't be regretted. But the attitude of a "normal" and healthy human being (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  26.  31
    Species-Being and the Badness of Extinction and Death.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2018 - Zeitschrift Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie 1 (1):143-162.
    This paper offers an account of the property Feuerbach and Marx called “species-being,” the human being’s distinctive tendency to identify herself as a member of her species, and to think of the species as a “we.” It links the notion to Kant’s theory of rights, arguing that every claim of right commits the maker of that claim to something like world government, and therefore to the conception of humanity as a collective agent. It also links species-being to the concept of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  77
    Categorical Desires and the Badness of Animal Death.Matt Bower & Bob Fischer - 2018 - Journal of Value Inquiry 52 (1):97-111.
    One way to defend humane animal agriculture is to insist that the deaths of animals aren’t bad for them. Christopher Belshaw has argued for this position in the most detail, maintaining that death is only bad when it frustrates categorical desires, which he thinks animals lack. We are prepared to grant his account of the badness of death, but we are skeptical of the claim that animals don’t have categorical desires. We contend that Belshaw’s argument against the badness (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. “K enny G's playing is lame ass, jive, pseudo bluesy, out-of-tune.Does Kenny G. Play Bad Jazz - 2004 - In Christopher Washburne & Maiken Derno (eds.), Bad Music: The Music We Love to Hate. Routledge.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The evil of death revisited.Harry S. Silverstein - 2000 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 24 (1):116–134.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  30.  12
    Good ethics and bad choices: the relevance of behavioral economics for medical ethics.Jennifer S. Blumenthal-Barby - 2021 - Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.
    An original examination of the relevance of behavioral economics for the practice of medical ethics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. The evil of death and the Lucretian symmetry: a reply to Feldman.John Martin Fischer & Anthony Brueckner - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 163 (3):783-789.
    In previous work we have defended the deprivation account of death’s badness against worries stemming from the Lucretian point that prenatal and posthumous nonexistence are deprivations of the same sort. In a recent article in this journal, Fred Feldman has offered an insightful critique of our Parfitian strategy for defending the deprivation account of death’s badness. Here we adjust, clarify, and defend our strategy for reply to Lucretian worries on behalf of the deprivation account.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  32.  4
    Russian cosmism.Boris Groĭs (ed.) - 2018 - Cambridge, MA: EFlux-MIT Press.
    Crucial texts, many available in English for the first time, written before and during the Bolshevik Revolution by the radical biopolitical utopianists of Russian Cosmism. Cosmism emerged in Russia before the October Revolution and developed through the 1920s and 1930s; like Marxism and the European avant-garde, two other movements that shared this intellectual moment, Russian Cosmism rejected the contemplative for the transformative, aiming to create not merely new art or philosophy but a new world. Cosmism went the furthest in its (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33. Death and Decline.Aaron Thieme - 2022 - Philosophical Quarterly 73 (1):248-257.
    In this paper, I investigate backward-looking accounts of death's badness. I begin by reviewing deprivationism—the standard, forward-looking account of death's badness. On deprivationism, death is bad for its victims when it deprives them of a good future. This account famously faces two problems—Lucretius’s symmetry problem and the preemption problem. This motivates turning to backward-looking accounts of death's badness on which death is bad for its victim (in a respect) when it involves a decline from (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Pera apo tē megalē siōpē: thanatos, to anapantēto erōtēmatiko.Geōrgios K. Zographakēs (ed.) - 1977 - Athēnai: Metapsychikē Hetaireia Athēnōn.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Death, Immortality, and Meaning in Life.John Martin Fischer - 2019 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    "There are seven chapters, addressing philosophical issues pertaining to death, the badness of death, time and death, ideas on immortality, near death experiences, and extending life through medical technology. The book is shorter, and less elaborate, than Kagan's Death. And it goes into more depth about a selection of central issues related to death and immortality than May's book. It gives an original take on various basic puzzles pertaining to death, and integrates a discussion of these philosophical issues with (...)
  36. Scholastic Economics and Arab Scholars: The "Great Gap" Thesis Reconsidered.S. M. Ghazanfar - 1991 - Diogenes 39 (154):117-140.
    Joseph Alois Schumpeter (1883-1950) stands among the intellectual giants of the twentieth century, especially in the field of economics; in his long and varied impact on the profession, he is second only to Maynard Keynes. He was a pragmatist in his economic philosophy, an “objective scientific investigator with no particular axe to grind” (Newman, et al., 746). His encyclopedic History of Economic Analysis, edited after his death by his wife and published in 1954, is a monument to his gigantic and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Survivalism, Corruptionism, and Mereology.David S. Oderberg - 2012 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (4):1-26.
    Corruptionism is the view that following physical death, the human being ceases to exist but their soul persists in the afterlife. Survivalism holds that both the human being and their soul persist in the afterlife, as distinct entities, with the soul constituting the human. Each position has its defenders, most of whom appeal both to metaphysical considerations and to the authority of St Thomas Aquinas. Corruptionists claim that survivalism violates a basic principle of any plausible mereology, while survivalists tend to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  38.  3
    The Long Dark Night of The Hat.S. W. Sondheimer - 2021-10-12 - In Jeffery L. Nicholas (ed.), The Expanse and Philosophy. Wiley. pp. 187–194.
    Plato had a great deal to say about the nature and function of the soul, much of it inspired by Socrates’ death by hemlock. According to Plato, the body and soul are two separate entities. The soul, Aristotle hypothesized, is a sort of non‐corporeal nervous system that directs sensory perception, movement, and thought, a great blob of form that animates a matter, entirely useless without a vessel to fill. In direct opposition to Plato and Socrates, Aristotle believed the physical and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Desire satisfaction, death, and time.Duncan Purves - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (6):799-819.
    Desire satisfaction theories of well-being and deprivationism about the badness of death face similar problems: desire satisfaction theories have trouble locating the time when the satisfaction of a future or past-directed desire benefits a person; deprivationism has trouble locating a time when death is bad for a person. I argue that desire satisfaction theorists and deprivation theorists can address their respective timing problems by accepting fusionism, the view that some events benefit or harm individuals only at fusions of moments (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40.  4
    Introduction.S. Waller & William E. Deal - 2010-09-24 - In Fritz Allhoff & S. Waller (eds.), Serial Killers ‐ Philosophy for Everyone. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 1–14.
    This chapter contains sections titled: How Common Are Serial Killings? What is a Serial Killer? I Think Therefore I Kill: The Philosophical Musings of Serial Killers Can You Blame Them? Ethics, Evil, and Serial Killing Dangerous Infatuations: The Public Fascination with Serial Killers A Eulogy for Emotion: The Lack of Empathy and the Urge to Kill Creepy Cognition: Talking and Thinking about Serial Killers Psycho‐ology: Killer Mindsets and Meditations on Murder A Solemn Afterword: A Message from the Victim's Network A (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    Petrarch's War: Florentine Wages and the Black Death.William Caferro - 2013 - Speculum 88 (1):144-165.
    The nature of the Florentine economy during the era of plague and the so-called crisi del trecento has been the subject of a great deal of study and debate. The nuanced and sophisticated discourse has proceeded, however, without proper consideration of warfare, which coincided with the other crises, but has been relegated in the Anglophone scholarship to the lonely subfield of military history. Recent studies have helped improve the status quo and blur rigid disciplinary lines. But there remains a stubborn (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  10
    The Sickness Unto Death.Søen Kierkegaard & Walter Lowrie - 1946 - Princeton University Press.
    Best known as a philosopher, one of the founders of existentialism, Kierkegaard also wrote books whose themes were primarily religious, psychological or literary. He was opposed to much in organised Christianity, stressing the necessity for individual choice against prescribed dogma and ritual. In this book, he concentrates his penetrating psychological observations on the theme of despair.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  43.  35
    Western attitudes toward death: from the Middle Ages to the present.Philippe Ariès - 1974 - Baltimore,: Johns Hopkins University Press.
    Ariès traces Western man's attitudes toward mortality from the early medieval conception of death as the familiar collective destiny of the human race to the modern tendency, so pronounced in industrial societies, to hide death as if it were an embarrassing family secret.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  44.  47
    Breaking bad and philosophy.David Richard Koepsell & Robert Arp (eds.) - 2012 - Chicago: Open Court.
    Breaking Bad, hailed by Stephen King, Chuck Klosterman, and many others as the best of all TV dramas, tells the story of a man whose life changes because of the medical death sentence of an advanced cancer diagnosis. The show depicts his metamorphosis from inoffensive chemistry teacher to feared drug lord and remorseless killer. Driven at first by the desire to save his family from destitution, he risks losing his family altogether because of his new life of crime. In defiance (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  13
    Rethinking German idealism.S. J. McGrath & Joseph Carew (eds.) - 2016 - London: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    The ‘death’ of German Idealism has been decried innumerable times since its revolutionary inception, whether it be by the 19th-century critique of Western metaphysics, phenomenology, contemporary French philosophy, or analytic philosophy. Yet in the face of two hundred years of sustained, extremely rigorous attempts to leave behind its legacy, German Idealism has resisted its philosophical death sentence. For this exact reason it is timely ask: What remains of German Idealism? In what ways does its fundamental concepts and texts still speak (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  3
    Három filozófiai kérdés az emberről: gondolatok a halálról, az elismerésről és a humanizmusról.Tamás Barcsi - 2016 - Máriabesnyő: Attraktor.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  3
    Dṛgdṛśyaviveka: discernment between atman and non atman, attributed to Śaṅkara. Śaṅkarācārya - 2008 - New York, N.Y.: Aurea Vidyā. Edited by Raphael.
    The Author and the Editor invite us to Discern (viveka) between Real and non-real, between atman (Self) and non-atman (non-Self), between Infinite and finite, between Life and death. In Svami Nikhilananda's words: -This work, which contains only forty-six sloka (verses) is an excellent vade mecum (handbook) for students of advanced courses in Advaita philosophy-. Both Readers and Scholars will welcome the truly Monumental Bibliography. SHANKARA, the Author, has been one of the greatest philosophers of India, and has profoundly influenced not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  39
    The hour of our death.Philippe Ariès - 1981 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This remarkable book--the fruit of almost two decades of study--traces in compelling fashion the changes in Western attitudes toward death and dying from the earliest Christian times to the present day. A truly landmark study, The Hour of Our Death reveals a pattern of gradually developing evolutionary stages in our perceptions of life in relation to death, each stage representing a virtual redefinition of human nature. Starting at the very foundations of Western culture, the eminent historian Phillipe Aries shows how, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  49.  31
    Galileo as a ‘bad theologian’: a formative myth about Galileo’s trial.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (4):753-791.
    For 150 years after Galileo’s condemnation in 1633, there were many references to the trial, but no sustained, heated or polarized discussions. Then came the thesis that Galileo was condemned not for being a good astronomer but for being a bad theologian ; it began in 1784–1785 with an apology of the Inquisition by Mallet du Pan in the Mercure de France and the printing in Tiraboschi’s Storia della letteratura italiana of an apocryphal letter attributed to Galileo but forged by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  4
    Transcendent mind: rethinking the science of consciousness.Imants Barušs - 2017 - Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Edited by Julia Mossbridge.
    Where does consciousness come from? For most scientists and laypeople, it is axiomatic that something in the substance of the brain - neurons, synapses and grey matter in just the right combination - create perception, self-awareness, and intentionality. Yet despite decades of neurological research, that ""something"" - the mechanism by which this process is said to occur - has remained frustratingly elusive. This is no accident, as the authors of this book argue, given that the evidence increasingly points to a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000