Results for 'kalon'

45 found
Order:
  1. Looking at Beauty to Kalon in Western Greece: Selected Essays from the 2018 Symposium on the Heritage of Western Greece.Heather L. Reid & Tony Leyh (eds.) - 2019 - Parnassos Press-Fonte Aretusa.
    The ancient Greek word kalon can be translated as beautiful, good, noble, or fine—yet somehow it transcends any one of those concepts. In art and literature, it can apply straightforwardly to figures like Helen or Aphrodite, or enigmatically to the pais kalos: the youthful athlete that decorates so much sympotic pottery. In the philosophy of Plato, Aristotle and Plotinus, meanwhile, it takes on an ethical, even transcendent dimension. And yet, the thread between a beautiful painting and the Platonic form (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. To kalon and the Experience of Art.Hallvard Fossheim - 2020 - In Pierre Destrée, Malcolm Heath & Dana Munteanu (eds.), The Poetics in Its Aristotelian Context. pp. 34-50.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. EROS/KALON/AGATHOS: Love, the Beautiful, and the Good.Lawrence Kimmel - 2008 - Analecta Husserliana 97:3-12.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Notes on the Kalon and the Good in Plato.Rachel Barney - 2010 - Classical Philology 105:363-377.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  3
    Ethos, techne y kalon en Platón.Joaquín Lomba Fuentes - 1987 - Anuario Filosófico 20 (2):23-70.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  78
    Contemplation and Action within the Context of the Kalon.Michael Wiitala - 2009 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 83:173-182.
    In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle seems to take it for granted that the contemplative man is morally virtuous. Yet in certain passages he suggests that morally virtuous actions can impede contemplation (theōria). In this paper I examine the relationship between contemplation and morally virtuous action in Aristotle’s ethics. I argue that, when understood within the context of the motivating power of the kalon, contemplation and morally virtuous action are related to one another in such a way that one cannot (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Two Passions in Plato’s Symposium: Diotima’s To Kalon as a Reorientation of Imperialistic Erōs.Mateo Duque - 2019 - In Heather L. Reid & Tony Leyh (eds.), Looking at Beauty to Kalon in Western Greece: Selected Essays from the 2018 Symposium on the Heritage of Western Greece. Sioux City, IA, USA: Parnassos Press – Fonte Aretusa. pp. 95-110.
    In this essay, I propose a reading of two contrasting passions, two kinds of erōs, in the "Symposium." On the one hand, there is the imperialistic desire for conquering and possessing that Alcibiades represents; and on the other hand, there is the productive love of immortal wisdom that Diotima represents. It’s not just what Alcibiades says in the Symposium, but also what he symbolizes. Alcibiades gives a speech in honor of Socrates and of his unrequited love for him, but even (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  19
    Friend and Hero: Scotus's Quarrel with Aristotle over the Kalon.Gerard Delahoussaye - 2010 - Franciscan Studies 68:97-135.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The more I love someone, the more firmly or steadily I love her – the more ready I am to act for her good; accordingly, the more I love someone the more prepared I am to suffer evil for her sake. My desire for her good makes me want to act for her good. I appeal to this love when deciding what I should do; and in acting I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  27
    Chapter Six. Moral Virtue And To Kalon.Gabriel Richardson Lear - 2009 - In Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics". Princeton University Press. pp. 123-146.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  68
    When Aristotelian virtuous agents acquire the fine for themselves, what are they acquiring?Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2020 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28 (4):674-692.
    In the Nicomachean Ethics, one of Aristotle’s most frequent characterizations of the virtuous agent is that she acts for the sake of the fine (to kalon). In IX.8, this pursuit of the fine receives a more specific description; virtuous agents maximally assign the fine to themselves. In this paper, I answer the question of how we are to understand the fine as individually and maximally acquirable. I analyze Nicomachean Ethics IX.7, where Aristotle highlights virtuous activity (energeia) as central to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  83
    Shame and Honor: Aristotle’s Thumos as a Basic Desire.Victor Saenz - 2018 - Apeiron 51 (1):73-95.
    One of three basic types of desire, claims Aristotle, is thumos (‘spirit,’ ‘passion,’ ‘heart,’ ‘anger,’ ‘impulse’). The other two are epithumia (‘appetite’) and boulêsis (‘wish,’ ‘rational desire’). Yet, he never gives us an account of thumos; it has also received relatively little scholarly attention. I argue that thumos has two key features. First, it is able to cognize what I call ‘social value,’ the agent’s own perceived standing relative to others in a certain domain. In human animals, shame and honor (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  17
    Hippias Major: an interpretation.Ivor Ludlam - 1991 - Stuttgart: F. Steiner.
    This strange dialogue becomes intelligible when Socrates is treated as a model of the good man who appears to the Many to be bad talking with a Hippias who is a model of the bad man who appears to the Many to be good. The good and apparently good are dramatized through these models. The good is revealed to be the fitting, while the fine/beautiful (kalon) is revealed to be the apparently fitting (hence the many confusions between the two (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  68
    Aristotle on moral virtue and the fine.Gabriel Richardson Lear - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 116–136.
    The prelims comprise: To Kalon as Effective Teleological Order The Visibility of the Fine Pleasure and Praise The Value of the Fine Conclusion Acknowledgments Notes References Further reading.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  14.  1
    Limitations of Individual Love and Social Utility of Universal Love - With a Focus on the Concept of Ascending Love Revealed in Plato’s Symposium -. 김솔 & 주광순 - 2021 - Journal of the Daedong Philosophical Association 96:87-112.
    이 글은 『향연』에서 ‘아름다움 그 자체(auto to kalon)’를 향하는 플라톤적 사랑의 상승이 비현실적이라는 오해를 해소하고, 그러한 사랑의 모습이 오히려 인류애적일 뿐 아니 라 윤리적이므로 추구할 가치가 있음을 밝히고자 한다. 대개 사랑은 어떤 감정보다도 개인 적인 차원의 감정으로서, 나의 연인, 나의 가족과 같은 개별적ㆍ특수적 대상에 대한 감정 이라고 여겨진다. 또한 우리는 그 대상이 그저 그 대상이기 때문에 사랑하는 것이지, 다른 이유는 없다고 말하기도 한다. 그러나 ‘나’와 관계되는 개별적인 대상에 대한 사랑은 ‘공동 체’와 관련하는 보편성에 부딪히면 그 한계를 직면한다. 우리는 자신과 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. The Pig’s Squeak: Towards a Renewed Aesthetic Argument for Veganism.A. G. Holdier - 2016 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 29 (4):631-642.
    In 1906, Henry Stephens Salt published a short collection of essays that presented several rhetorically powerful, if formally deficient arguments for the vegetarian position. By interpreting Salt as a moral sentimentalist with ties to Aristotelian virtue ethics, I propose that his aesthetic argument deserves contemporary consideration. First, I connect ethics and aesthetics with the Greek concepts of kalon and kalokagathia that depend equally on beauty and morality before presenting Salt’s assertion: slaughterhouses are disgusting, therefore they should not be promoted. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16. Comment définir son devoir?Christelle Veillard - 2014 - Philosophie Antique 14:71-109.
    Lorsqu’il rédige son traité De officiis, Cicéron a sous les yeux le Peri kathekontos de Panétius, auquel il emprunte sa structure tripartite. Cette structure laisse pourtant perplexe, puisque le devoir (kathekon) y est envisagé sous l’angle du beau moral, puis sous l’angle de l’utile, pour en venir à une confrontation des deux. La perplexité naît de ce que le beau moral et l’utile sont interchangeables, si l’on s’en tient aux principes posés par Zénon et Chrysippe. Que signifie alors cette structure? (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. Aristotle’s Conception of Τò Καλόυ.Kelly Rogers - 1993 - Ancient Philosophy 13 (2):355.
    All the virtues, Aristotle says, are undertaken for the sake of the noble ("to kalon"). Curiously, however, he offers no direct account of this concept, despite its role as the end ("telos") of virtue. Fortunately, two patterns of usage in Aristotle's ethical discourse offer a means to clarification. Aristotle is found to link nobility jointly with his conceptions of appropriateness and praiseworthiness. An examination of these usage- patterns is found not only to elucidate Aristotle's view of nobility, moreover, but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18.  17
    Six Names of Beauty.Crispin Sartwell - 2004 - New York: Routledge.
    Beauty may be in the eye of the beholder, but it's also in the language we use and everywhere in the world around us. In this elegant, witty, and ultimately profound meditation on what is beautiful, Crispin Sartwell begins with six words from six different cultures - ancient Greek's 'to kalon', the Japanese idea of 'wabi-sabi', Hebrew's 'yapha', the Navajo concept 'hozho', Sanskrit 'sundara', and our own English-language 'beauty'. Each word becomes a door onto another way of thinking about, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  19.  64
    Reply to Irwin.Anton Ford - 2010 - Classical Philology 105 (4):396-402.
  20. Harmonia, Melos and Rhytmos. Aristotle on Musical Education.Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi - 2016 - Ancient Philosophy 36 (2):409-424.
    In this paper, I reconstruct the reasons why Aristotle thinks that musical education is important for moral education. Musical education teaches us to enjoy appropriately and to recognize perceptually fine melodies and rhythms. Fine melodies and rhythms are similar to the kind of movements fine actions consist in and fine characters display. By teaching us to enjoy and recognise fine melodies and rhythms, musical education can train us to recognize and to take pleasure in fine actions and characters. Thus, musical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  21. Plato on Self-Predication of "the fine"–"Hippias Major" 292, e6-7.Motoaki Kato - 1995 - Bigaku 45 (4):12-22.
    In Plato's "Hippias Major" 292e6-7, we can find a self-predication sentence; "The fine is always fine." (We have similar expressions in "Protagoras" 330c4-6, 330d8-el, "Lysis" 220b6-7.) How should we interpret this sentence? We cannot give it any metaphysical meaning drawn from Plato's own theory of Form, which is explicit in his middle dialogues. "The fine" here should be the logical cause, not the one of the metaphysical essentials (cf. Paul Woodruff's "Plateo Hippias Major", p. 150). So taking a sentence like (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  9
    Thomas Aquinas on virtue and human flourishing.Stephen Theron - 2018 - Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    Thomas Aquinas offers teleological systematisation of the habits needed for human flourishing. His metaphysical jurisprudence remodels ethics upon this, rather than on a moral precept. 'Eternal law' governing the world determines 'natural law', reflected in human legislation (a variety of the 'anthropic principle'). Finally, law, unwritten, is infused spirit as self-consciousness, 'universal of universals'. Acquired virtues elicit this, become effusion, represented in religion as gifts or graces. But mind's or spirit's omnipresence, necessarily 'closer to me than I am to myself', (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Plato and the dangerous pleasures of poikilia.Jonathan Fine - 2021 - Classical Quarterly 71 (1):152-169.
    A significant strand of the ethical psychology, aesthetics and politics of Plato's Republic revolves around the concept of poikilia, ‘fascinating variety’. Plato uses the concept to caution against harmful appetitive pleasures purveyed by democracy and such artistic or cultural practices as mimetic poetry. His aim, this article shows, is to contest a prominent conceptual connection between poikilia and beauty (kallos, to kalon). Exploiting tensions in the archaic and classical Greek concept, Plato associates poikilia with dangerous pleasures to redirect admiration (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  35
    Plotinus and Augustine on Beauty and Matter.Maurizio Filippo Di Silva - 2021 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 16 (1):15-28.
    The aim of this paper is to examine whether and, if so, how far, the Augustinian notion of pulchrum is related to Plotinus’ concept of beauty, as it appears in Ennead I. 6. The Augustinian notion of beauty will be analyzed by focusing on the De natura boni, considering plurality and unity in Augustine’s identification of bonum with esse, both in their ontological and axiological dimensions. Topics selected for special consideration will be, first, beauty as outcome of modus, species and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  26
    Tragédie, thumos, et plaisir esthétique.Elizabeth Belfiore - 2003 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 67 (4):451.
    Résumé — Dans cet article, je montre que l’une des fonctions de la tragédie est de procurer un entraînement au thumos , en l’habituant à devenir amical plutôt qu’agressif envers les philoi . Je donne d’abord un bref aperçu des thèses sur le thumos exposées dans les œuvres éthiques et politiques d’Aristote. Ensuite, j’étudie la relation entre le thumos et les actes de violence entre proches, qui constituent le sujet de la tragédie, en montrant comment la pitié et la crainte (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  36
    Hume and the Aesthetics of Agency.Flint Schier - 1987 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87:121 - 135.
    Philosophical interest in beautiful moral agency can be traced back at least to Plato. It is an insistent theme of his writings that a virtuous soul is one in which the functions of its various parts are properly discharged, just as in the healthy body all the organs must perform their proper tasks. As health in the body is beautiful (kalon), so is the health of the soul. We here discern the first inkling of a thought which has engrossed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. Permanent beauty and becoming happy in Plato's Symposium.Gabriel Richardson Lear - 2006 - In J. H. Lesher, Debra Nails & Frisbee C. C. Sheffield (eds.), Plato's Symposium: Issues in Interpretation and Reception. Harvard University Press. pp. 96.
    Our first encounter with Socrates in the Symposium is bizarre. Aristodemus, surprised to run into Socrates fully bathed and with his sandals on, asks him where he is going “to have made himself so beautiful (kalos)” (174a4, Rowe trans.). Socrates replies that he is on his way to see the lovely Agathon, and so that “he has beautified himself in these ways in order to go, a beauty to a beauty (kalos para kalon)” (174a7–8). Why does Socrates, who in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  21
    The Better Part.Stephen R. L. Clark - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 35:29-49.
    According to Aristotle, the goal of anyone who is not simply stupid or slavish is to live a worthwhile life. There are, no doubt, people who have no goal at all beyond the moment's pleasure or release from pain. There may be people incapable of reaching any reasoned decision about what to do, and acting on it. But anyone who asks how she should live implicitly agrees that her goal is to live well, to live a life that she can (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  24
    The Better Part.Stephen R. L. Clark - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 35:29-49.
    According to Aristotle, the goal of anyone who is not simply stupid or slavish is to live a worthwhile life. There are, no doubt, people who have no goal at all beyond the moment's pleasure or release from pain. There may be people incapable of reaching any reasoned decision about what to do, and acting on it. But anyone who asks how she should live implicitly agrees that her goal is to live well, to live a life that she can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  7
    ""Striving for Contemplation:" True" Politicians vs" Good" Politicians in Aristotle´ s Philosophy.Elena Irrera - 2010 - Elenchos 31 (1):77-110.
    In this paper I will argue that, in Aristotle’s thought, the political commitment of authentically wise men is ultimately motivated by an intellectual rather than by a merely practical interest. Through analysis of Eudemian Ethics A 4. 1216 a 23-7 and Q 3. 1248 b 8-37 I shall contend that the socalled “true politician” is to be identified with a kalos kai agathos man, i.e. with an individual who – rather than being driven by mere desire for the promotion of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  5
    Striving for Contemplation. True Politicians Vs Good Politicians in Aristotle's Philosophy.Elena Irrera - 2010 - Elenchos 31 (1):77-110.
    In this paper I will argue that, in Aristotle’s thought, the political commitment of authentically wise men is ultimately motivated by an intellectual rather than by a merely practical interest. Through analysis of Eudemian Ethics A 4. 1216 a 23-7 and Q 3. 1248 b 8-37 I shall contend that the socalled “true politician” is to be identified with a kalos kai agathos man, i.e. with an individual who – rather than being driven by mere desire for the promotion of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. An Advocacy of the Homo Theologicus: Theologal Thinking and Being Toward Meaning.Inti Yanes - forthcoming - International Journal of Religion and Spirituality in Society.
    Human being is essentially a homo theologicus. Its thinking is a theologal way of being. The origin of theological thinking is the onto-existential condition of man as being in the world toward the Transcendence through death in the quest for Meaning. Transcendence is the perfect union of the ontological (Being) and the epistemological (Meaning) in an analogical relationship with the identity between “kalon” and “agathon” as present in Plato. There is an essential correspondence between Being and Meaning that has (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  54
    Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics on virtue competition.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2023 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (1):1-21.
    For many, striving to attain first place in an athletic competition is explicable. Less explicable is striving to attain first place in a virtue (aretē) competition. Yet this latter dynamic appears in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. There is 4.3’s magnanimity, the crown of the virtues, which seemingly manifests itself in outdoing one’s peers in virtue. Such one-upmanship also seems operant with 9.8’s praiseworthy self-lover, who seeks to get as much of the fine (to kalon) as possible for herself. Contrary to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  73
    The Learner’s Motivation and the Structure of Habituation in Aristotle.Margaret Hampson - 2022 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 104 (3):415-447.
    Moral virtue is, for Aristotle, a state to which an agent’s motivation is central. For anyone interested in Aristotle’s account of moral development this invites reflection on two questions: how is it that virtuous motivational dispositions are established? And what contribution do the moral learner’s existing motivational states make to the success of her habituation? I argue that views which demand that the learner act with virtuous motives if she is to acquire virtuous dispositions misconstrue the nature and structure of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35.  11
    Aristotle on Thought and Feeling by Paula Gottlieb (review).Corinne Gartner - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (4):703-705.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Aristotle on Thought and Feeling by Paula GottliebCorinne GartnerPaula Gottlieb. Aristotle on Thought and Feeling. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. Pp. 173. Hardback, $99.99.Paula Gottlieb's recent book is an illuminating, synoptic study of Aristotle's theory of human motivation, according to which his innovative notion of prohairesis (choice)—specifically, the virtuous agent's prohairesis—is the cornerstone. She argues against both Kantian-flavored readings, which prioritize reason's role in motivating ethical action, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Plato’s Metaphysical Development before Middle Period Dialogues.Mohammad Bagher Ghomi - manuscript
    Regarding the relation of Plato’s early and middle period dialogues, scholars have been divided to two opposing groups: unitarists and developmentalists. While developmentalists try to prove that there are some noticeable and even fundamental differences between Plato’s early and middle period dialogues, the unitarists assert that there is no essential difference in there. The main goal of this article is to suggest that some of Plato’s ontological as well as epistemological principles change, both radically and fundamentally, between the early and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  16
    La carnalidad del amor: percepción e historia.Martín Dillon - 1997 - Areté. Revista de Filosofía 9 (2):219-234.
    Este ensayo busca desarrollar una teoría del amor erótico basada en la tesis de Merleau-Ponty acerca de la reversibilidad de la carne. En el intento de distinguir el amor auténtico del amor romántico, y de elaborar el rol del conocimiento carnal que responde a la ansiedad erótica, este trabajo está específicamente dirigido hacia los aspectos cognitivos del amor sexual. Los antiguos temas griegos de la mímesis y de la nobleza (to kalón) son redefinidos mediante los conceptos de la reversibilidad y (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  41
    Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X: Translation and Commentary.Joachim Aufderheide - 2020 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Aristotle.
    Presents a new translation with commentary exploring the final book of Aristotle's Ethics in a philosophically rigorous yet interpretatively open way.
  39.  2
    Libéralité et gratitude.David Konstan - 2018 - Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 1:89-104.
    Dans ce texte, je fais une distinction, chez Aristote, entre deux conceptions de l’acte consistant à accorder un bienfait à une autre personne. La première relève de la libéralité ou eleutheriotês, une des vertus examinées par Aristote dans l’ Éthique à Nicomaque ; la personne libérale aide une autre personne en vue de ce qui est « beau » ou « noble » ( to kalon ). L’autre conception correspond à la faveur ou kharis, qu’Aristote analyse quand il examine (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  29
    The Beautiful in Aristotle’s Ethics.David H. Little - 2022 - Polis 39 (1):149-163.
    This article argues for an aesthetic reading of to kalon, primarily as it appears in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle uses to kalon to indicate that, to the morally serious, virtue is attractive and productive of a kind of pleasure. Read aesthetically, to kalon mitigates the tension between one’s own good and the common good. Aristotle shows how his students’ understanding of to kalon can be refined and thus preserved as an important and salutary feature of moral (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Review of Christopher Bobonich (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics[REVIEW]Noell Birondo - 2018 - The Classical Review 68 (2):305-308.
    ‘Greek Ethics’, an undergraduate class taught by the British moral philosopher N. J. H. Dent, introduced this reviewer to the ethical philosophy of ancient Greece. The class had a modest purview—a sequence of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle—but it proved no less effective, in retrospect, than more synoptic classes for having taken this apparently limited and (for its students and academic level) appropriate focus. This excellent Companion will now serve any such class extremely well, allowing students a broader exposure than that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. The Guise of the Beautiful: Symposium 204d ff.Jonathan Fine - 2019 - Phronesis 65 (2):129-152.
    A crux of Plato’s Symposium is how beauty relates to the good. Diotima distinguishes beauty from the good, I show, to explain how erotic pursuits are characteristically ambivalent and opaque. Human beings pursue beauty without knowing why or thinking it good; yet they are rational, if aiming at happiness. Central to this reconstruction is a passage widely taken to show that beauty either coincides with the good or demands disinterested admiration. It shows rather that what one loves as beautiful does (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Review of Pearson, Aristotle on Desire. [REVIEW]Thornton Lockwood - 2013 - Bryn Mawr Classical Review 9:24.
    The image of a copy of Praxiteles’ Aphrodite—nude but demurely shielding her pubic region—which adorns the dust cover of Pearson’s superb monograph, Aristotle on Desire</i>), suggests to the casual book buyer that the volume encased therein will explain Aristotle’s thoughts about sexual desire—perhaps as a central part or the paradigm case of his general theory of desire. But the goddess likes being tricky: Aristotle has very little to say about sexual desire (at best it is a subcategory of <i>epithumia</i>, set (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Review of Gottlieb, The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. [REVIEW]Thornton C. Lockwood Jr - 2011 - International Philosophical Quarterly 51 (3):418-420.
    In his Metaphysics of Morals, Kant famously wrote “The distinction between virtue and vice can never be sought in the degree to which one follows certain maxims…In other words, the well-known principle (Aristotle’s) that locates virtue in the mean between two vices is false.” Kant is not the first (or the last) thinker to take to task Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean, but he is representative of a line of criticism of Aristotle’s doctrine which argues that ethics is the realm (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Ἔρως and γυμναστική in the platonic corpus: The quest for the Form of Κάλλος.Konstantinos Gkaleas - 2019 - In Heather L. Reid & Tony Leyh (eds.), Looking at Beauty to Kalon in Western Greece: Selected Essays from the 2018 Symposium on the Heritage of Western Greece. Parnassos Press-Fonte Aretusa.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark