Results for 'prenexability'

62 found
Order:
  1.  26
    Prenex normal form theorems in semi-classical arithmetic.Makoto Fujiwara & Taishi Kurahashi - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (3):1124-1153.
    Akama et al. [1] systematically studied an arithmetical hierarchy of the law of excluded middle and related principles in the context of first-order arithmetic. In that paper, they first provide a prenex normal form theorem as a justification of their semi-classical principles restricted to prenex formulas. However, there are some errors in their proof. In this paper, we provide a simple counterexample of their prenex normal form theorem [1, Theorem 2.7], then modify it in an appropriate way which still serves (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2.  6
    Prenex normalization and the hierarchical classification of formulas.Makoto Fujiwara & Taishi Kurahashi - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 63 (3):391-403.
    Akama et al. [1] introduced a hierarchical classification of first-order formulas for a hierarchical prenex normal form theorem in semi-classical arithmetic. In this paper, we give a justification for the hierarchical classification in a general context of first-order theories. To this end, we first formalize the standard transformation procedure for prenex normalization. Then we show that the classes $$\textrm{E}_k$$ and $$\textrm{U}_k$$ introduced in [1] are exactly the classes induced by $$\Sigma _k$$ and $$\Pi _k$$ respectively via the transformation procedure in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  22
    Prenex Normal Form in the Modal Predicate Logic PS*S and the Grosseteste Algebra of Sets GS*S.Robert L. Wilson - 1974 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 20 (13‐18):271-280.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  24
    Prenex Normal Form in the Modal Predicate Logic PS*S and the Grosseteste Algebra of Sets GS*S.Robert L. Wilson - 1974 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 20 (13-18):271-280.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  14
    Simulating non-prenex cuts in quantified propositional calculus.Emil Jeřábek & Phuong Nguyen - 2011 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 57 (5):524-532.
    We show that the quantified propositional proof systems Gi are polynomially equivalent to their restricted versions that require all cut formulas to be prenex Σqi . Previously this was known only for the treelike systems G*i. © 2011 WILEY-VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  13
    An Herbrand theorem for prenex formulas of LJ.Kenneth A. Bowen - 1976 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 17 (2):263-266.
  7. Omitting types of prenex formulas.C. C. Chang - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (1):61-74.
  8.  23
    An improved prenex normal form.C. C. Chang & H. Jerome Keisler - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (3):317-326.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  4
    An Improved Prenex Normal Form.C. C. Chang & H. Jerome Keisler - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (3):479-479.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  5
    Omitting Types of Prenex Formulas.C. C. Chang - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (1):182-182.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  13
    Analog of Herbrand's Theorem for Prenex Formulas of Constructive Predicate Calculus.G. E. Mints - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (3):47--51.
  12.  36
    Analog of Herbrand's Theorem for [non] Prenex Formulas of Constructive Predicate Calculus.J. van Heijenoort, G. E. Mints & A. O. Slisenko - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (3):525.
  13.  16
    C. C. Chang and H. Jerome Keisler. An improved prenex nomal form. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 27 no. 3 , pp. 317–326.Theodore Hailperin - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (3):479.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  15
    C. C. Chang. Omitting types of prenex formulas. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 32 , pp. 61–74.H. Simmons - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (1):182.
  15.  61
    Elementary completeness properties of intuitionistic logic with a note on negations of prenex formulae.G. Kreisel - 1958 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (3):317-330.
  16.  7
    Elementary Completeness Properties of Intuitionistic Logic with a Note on Negations of Prenex Formulae.G. Kreisel - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):282-283.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  33
    The decision problem for formulas in prenex conjunctive normal form with binary disjunctions.M. R. Krom - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):210-216.
  18.  6
    Review: C. C. Chang, H. Jerome Keisler, An Improved Prenex Normal Form. [REVIEW]Theodore Hailperin - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (3):479-479.
  19.  24
    G. Kreisel. Elementary completeness properties of intuitionistic logic with a note on negations of prenex formulae. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 23 no. 3 , pp. 317–330. [REVIEW]Joan Rand Moschovakis - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):282-283.
  20.  9
    Review: C. C. Chang, Omitting Types of Prenex Formulas. [REVIEW]H. Simmons - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (1):182-182.
  21. A Decision Procedure for Herbrand Formulas without Skolemization.Timm Lampert - manuscript
    This paper describes a decision procedure for disjunctions of conjunctions of anti-prenex normal forms of pure first-order logic (FOLDNFs) that do not contain V within the scope of quantifiers. The disjuncts of these FOLDNFs are equivalent to prenex normal forms whose quantifier-free parts are conjunctions of atomic and negated atomic formulae (= Herbrand formulae). In contrast to the usual algorithms for Herbrand formulae, neither skolemization nor unification algorithms with function symbols are applied. Instead, a procedure is described that rests on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  22
    Decidable and undecidable fragments in First order logic.Ricardo José Da Silva & Franklin Galindo - 2017 - Apuntes Filosóficos 26 (50):90-113.
    The present paper has three objectives: Presenting an actualization of a proof of the decidability of monadic predicates logic in the contemporary model theory context; Show examples of decidable and undecidable fragments inside First order logic, offering an original proof of the following theorem: Any formula of First of order logic is decidable if its prenex normal form is in the following form: ∀x1,…,∀xn∃y1,…,∃ymφ; Presenting a theorem that characterizes the validity of First order logic by the tautologicity of Propositional logic, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  51
    On interplay of quantifiers in Gödel-Dummett fuzzy logics.Blanka Kozlíková & Vítězslav Švejdar - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (5):569-580.
    Axiomatization of Gödel-Dummett predicate logics S2G, S3G, and PG, where PG is the weakest logic in which all prenex operations are sound, and the relationships of these logics to logics known from the literature are discussed. Examples of non-prenexable formulas are given for those logics where some prenex operation is not available. Inter-expressibility of quantifiers is explored for each of the considered logics.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  29
    Fragments of Heyting arithmetic.Wolfgang Burr - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1223-1240.
    We define classes Φnof formulae of first-order arithmetic with the following properties:(i) Everyφϵ Φnis classically equivalent to a Πn-formula (n≠ 1, Φ1:= Σ1).(ii)(iii)IΠnandiΦn(i.e., Heyting arithmetic with induction schema restricted to Φn-formulae) prove the same Π2-formulae.We further generalize a result by Visser and Wehmeier. namely that prenex induction within intuitionistic arithmetic is rather weak: After closing Φnboth under existential and universal quantification (we call these classes Θn) the corresponding theoriesiΘnstill prove the same Π2-formulae. In a second part we consideriΔ0plus collection-principles. We (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  25.  19
    Feferman–Vaught Decompositions for Prefix Classes of First Order Logic.Abhisekh Sankaran - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (1):147-174.
    The Feferman–Vaught theorem provides a way of evaluating a first order sentence \(\varphi \) on a disjoint union of structures by producing a decomposition of \(\varphi \) into sentences which can be evaluated on the individual structures and the results of these evaluations combined using a propositional formula. This decomposition can in general be non-elementarily larger than \(\varphi \). We introduce a “tree” generalization of the prenex normal form (PNF) for first order sentences, and show that for an input sentence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  76
    First-order Gödel logics.Richard Zach, Matthias Baaz & Norbert Preining - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 147 (1):23-47.
    First-order Gödel logics are a family of finite- or infinite-valued logics where the sets of truth values V are closed subsets of [0,1] containing both 0 and 1. Different such sets V in general determine different Gödel logics GV (sets of those formulas which evaluate to 1 in every interpretation into V). It is shown that GV is axiomatizable iff V is finite, V is uncountable with 0 isolated in V, or every neighborhood of 0 in V is uncountable. Complete (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  27.  78
    Quantified propositional calculus and a second-order theory for NC1.Stephen Cook & Tsuyoshi Morioka - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (6):711-749.
    Let H be a proof system for quantified propositional calculus (QPC). We define the Σqj-witnessing problem for H to be: given a prenex Σqj-formula A, an H-proof of A, and a truth assignment to the free variables in A, find a witness for the outermost existential quantifiers in A. We point out that the Σq1-witnessing problems for the systems G*1and G1 are complete for polynomial time and PLS (polynomial local search), respectively. We introduce and study the systems G*0 and G0, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28. Epsilon theorems in intermediate logics.Matthias Baaz & Richard Zach - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (2):682-720.
    Any intermediate propositional logic can be extended to a calculus with epsilon- and tau-operators and critical formulas. For classical logic, this results in Hilbert’s $\varepsilon $ -calculus. The first and second $\varepsilon $ -theorems for classical logic establish conservativity of the $\varepsilon $ -calculus over its classical base logic. It is well known that the second $\varepsilon $ -theorem fails for the intuitionistic $\varepsilon $ -calculus, as prenexation is impossible. The paper investigates the effect of adding critical $\varepsilon $ - (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  20
    The Functional Interpretation of the Existential Quantifier.Ruy B. de Queiroz & Dov Gabbay - 1995 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 3 (2-3):243-290.
    We are concerned with showing how ‘labelled’ Natural Deduction presentation systems based on an extension of the so-called Curry-Howard functional interpretation can help us understand and generalise most of the deduction calculi designed to deal with the logical notion of existential quantification. We present the labelling mechanism for ‘’ using what we call ‘ɛ-terms’, which have the form of ‘a’) in a dual form to the ‘Ax.f’ terms of in the sense that the ‘witness’ is chosen at the time of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  40
    Fragments of $HA$ based on $\Sigma_1$ -induction.Kai F. Wehmeier - 1997 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 37 (1):37-49.
    In the first part of this paper we investigate the intuitionistic version $iI\!\Sigma_1$ of $I\!\Sigma_1$ (in the language of $PRA$ ), using Kleene's recursive realizability techniques. Our treatment closely parallels the usual one for $HA$ and establishes a number of nice properties for $iI\!\Sigma_1$ , e.g. existence of primitive recursive choice functions (this is established by different means also in [D94]). We then sharpen an unpublished theorem of Visser's to the effect that quantifier alternation alone is much less powerful intuitionistically (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  31.  19
    Cut normal forms and proof complexity.Matthias Baaz & Alexander Leitsch - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 97 (1-3):127-177.
    Statman and Orevkov independently proved that cut-elimination is of nonelementary complexity. Although their worst-case sequences are mathematically different the syntax of the corresponding cut formulas is of striking similarity. This leads to the main question of this paper: to what extent is it possible to restrict the syntax of formulas and — at the same time—keep their power as cut formulas in a proof? We give a detailed analysis of this problem for negation normal form , prenex normal form and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32.  11
    Classical truth in higher types.Ulrich Berger - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (3):240-246.
    We study, from a classical point of view, how the truth of a statement about higher type functionals depends on the underlying model. The models considered are the classical set-theoretic finite type hierarchy and the constructively more meaningful models of continuous functionals, hereditarily effective operations, as well as the closed term model of Gödel's system T. The main results are characterisations of prenex classes for which truth in the full set-theoretic model transfers to truth in the other models. As a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  9
    On Minimal Models.Francicleber Ferreira & Ana Teresa Martins - 2007 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 15 (5-6):503-526.
    We investigate some logics which use the concept of minimal models in their definition. Minimal objects are widely used in Logic and Computer Science. They are applied in the context of Inductive Definitions, Logic Programming and Artificial Intelligence. An example of logic which uses this concept is the MIN logic due to van Benthem [20]. He shows that MIN is equivalent to the Least Fixed Point logic in expressive power. In [6], we extended MIN to the MIN Logic and proved (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  24
    Turning decision procedures into disprovers.André Rognes - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (1):87-104.
    A class of many-sorted polyadic set algebras is introduced. These generalise structure and model in a way that is relevant in regards to the Entscheidungsproblem and to automated reasoning.A downward Löwenheim-Skolem property is shown in that each satisfiable finite conjunction of purely relational first-order prenex sentences has a finite generalised model. This property does, together with a construction related to doubling the size of a finite structure, provide several strict generalisations of the strategy of finite model search for disproving.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  29
    Complexity of syntactical tree fragments of Independence-Friendly logic.Fausto Barbero - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (1):102859.
    A dichotomy result of Sevenster (2014) [29] completely classified the quantifier prefixes of regular Independence-Friendly (IF) logic according to the patterns of quantifier dependence they contain. On one hand, prefixes that contain “Henkin” or “signalling” patterns were shown to characterize fragments of IF logic that capture NP-complete problems; all the remaining prefixes were shown instead to be essentially first-order. In the present paper we develop the machinery which is needed in order to extend the results of Sevenster to non-prenex, regular (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  10
    Independence-friendly logic without Henkin quantification.Fausto Barbero, Lauri Hella & Raine Rönnholm - 2021 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 60 (5):547-597.
    We analyze the expressive resources of \ logic that do not stem from Henkin quantification. When one restricts attention to regular \ sentences, this amounts to the study of the fragment of \ logic which is individuated by the game-theoretical property of action recall. We prove that the fragment of prenex AR sentences can express all existential second-order properties. We then show that the same can be achieved in the non-prenex fragment of AR, by using “signalling by disjunction” instead of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  29
    Structure and definability in general bounded arithmetic theories.Chris Pollett - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 100 (1-3):189-245.
    The bounded arithmetic theories R2i, S2i, and T2i are closely connected with complexity theory. This paper is motivated by the questions: what are the Σi+1b-definable multifunctions of R2i? and when is one theory conservative over another? To answer these questions we consider theories , and where induction is restricted to prenex formulas. We also define which has induction up to the 0 or 1-ary L2-terms in the set τ. We show and and for . We show that the -multifunctions of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  38.  17
    Equivalence and quantifier rules for logic with imperfect information.Xavier Caicedo, Francien Dechesne & Theo Janssen - 2008 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 17 (1):91-129.
    In this paper, we present a prenex form theorem for a version of Independence Friendly logic, a logic with imperfect information. Lifting classical results to such logics turns out not to be straightforward, because independence conditions make the formulas sensitive to signalling phenomena. In particular, nested quantification over the same variable is shown to cause problems. For instance, renaming of bound variables may change the interpretations of a formula, there are only restricted quantifier extraction theorems, and slashed connectives cannot be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  39.  33
    Expressivity of Imperfect Information Logics without Identity.Antti Kuusisto - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (2):237-265.
    In this article we investigate the family of independence-friendly (IF) logics in the equality-free setting, concentrating on questions related to expressive power. Various natural equality-free fragments of logics in this family translate into existential second-order logic with prenex quantification of function symbols only and with the first-order parts of formulae equality-free. We study this fragment of existential second-order logic. Our principal technical result is that over finite models with a vocabulary consisting of unary relation symbols only, this fragment of second-order (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  26
    On Theorems of Gödel and Kreisel: Completeness and Markov's Principle.D. C. McCarty - 1994 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (1):99-107.
    In 1957, Gödel proved that completeness for intuitionistic predicate logic HPL implies forms of Markov's Principle, MP. The result first appeared, with Kreisel's refinements and elaborations, in Kreisel. Featuring large in the Gödel-Kreisel proofs are applications of the axiom of dependent choice, DC. Also in play is a form of Herbrand's Theorem, one allowing a reduction of HPL derivations for negated prenex formulae to derivations of negations of conjunctions of suitable instances. First, we here show how to deduce Gödel's results (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. Minimal realizability of intuitionistic arithmetic and elementary analysis.Zlatan Damnjanovic - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (4):1208-1241.
    A new method of "minimal" realizability is proposed and applied to show that the definable functions of Heyting arithmetic (HA)--functions f such that HA $\vdash \forall x\exists!yA(x, y)\Rightarrow$ for all m, A(m, f(m)) is true, where A(x, y) may be an arbitrary formula of L(HA) with only x, y free--are precisely the provably recursive functions of the classical Peano arithmetic (PA), i.e., the $ -recursive functions. It is proved that, for prenex sentences provable in HA, Skolem functions may always be (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  45
    Strictly Primitive Recursive Realizability, II. Completeness with Respect to Iterated Reflection and a Primitive Recursive $\omega$ -Rule.Zlatan Damnjanovic - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (3):363-388.
    The notion of strictly primitive recursive realizability is further investigated, and the realizable prenex sentences, which coincide with primitive recursive truths of classical arithmetic, are characterized as precisely those provable in transfinite progressions over a fragment of intuitionistic arithmetic. The progressions are based on uniform reflection principles of bounded complexity iterated along initial segments of a primitive recursively formulated system of notations for constructive ordinals. A semiformal system closed under a primitive recursively restricted -rule is described and proved equivalent to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  38
    On the First-Order Prefix Hierarchy.Eric Rosen - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (2):147-164.
    We investigate the expressive power of fragments of first-order logic that are defined in terms of prefixes. The main result establishes a strict hierarchy among these fragments over the signature consisting of a single binary relation. It implies that for each prefix p, there is a sentence in prenex normal form with prefix p, over a single binary relation, such that for all sentences θ in prenex normal form, if θ is equivalent to , then p can be embedded in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  57
    On Boolean algebras and integrally closed commutative regular rings.Misao Nagayama - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (4):1305-1318.
    In this paper we consider properties, related to model-completeness, of the theory of integrally closed commutative regular rings. We obtain the main theorem claiming that in a Boolean algebra B, the truth of a prenex Σn-formula whose parameters ai partition B, can be determined by finitely many conditions built from the first entry of Tarski invariant T(ai)'s, n-characteristic D(n, ai)'s and the quantities S(ai, l) and S'(ai, l) for $l < n$. Then we derive two important theorems. One claims that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  10
    $\Sigma^1_1$ -Completeness of a Fragment of the Theory of Trees with Subtree Relation.P. Cintioli & S. Tulipani - 1994 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (3):426-432.
    We consider the structure of all labeled trees, called also infinite terms, in the first order language with function symbols in a recursive signature of cardinality at least two and at least a symbol of arity two, with equality and a binary relation symbol which is interpreted to be the subtree relation. The existential theory over of this structure is decidable (see Tulipani [9]), but more complex fragments of the theory are undecidable. We prove that the theory of the structure (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  34
    Examining fragments of the quantified propositional calculus.Steven Perron - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (3):1051-1080.
    When restricted to proving $\Sigma _{i}^{q}$ formulas, the quantified propositional proof system $G_{i}^{\ast}$ is closely related to the $\Sigma _{i}^{b}$ theorems of Buss's theory $S_{2}^{i}$ . Namely, $G_{i}^{\ast}$ has polynomial-size proofs of the translations of theorems of $S_{2}^{i}$ , and $S_{2}^{i}$ proves that $G_{i}^{\ast}$ is sound. However, little is known about $G_{i}^{\ast}$ when proving more complex formulas. In this paper, we prove a witnessing theorem for $G_{i}^{\ast}$ similar in style to the KPT witnessing theorem for $T_{2}^{i}$ . This witnessing theorem (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  33
    On the no-counterexample interpretation.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1491-1511.
    In [15], [16] G. Kreisel introduced the no-counterexample interpretation (n.c.i.) of Peano arithmetic. In particular he proved, using a complicated ε-substitution method (due to W. Ackermann), that for every theorem A (A prenex) of first-order Peano arithmetic PA one can find ordinal recursive functionals Φ A of order type 0 which realize the Herbrand normal form A H of A. Subsequently more perspicuous proofs of this fact via functional interpretation (combined with normalization) and cut-elimination were found. These proofs however do (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  37
    A hierarchy of maps between compacta.Paul Bankston - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1628-1644.
    Let CH be the class of compacta (i.e., compact Hausdorff spaces), with BS the subclass of Boolean spaces. For each ordinal α and pair $\langle K,L\rangle$ of subclasses of CH, we define Lev ≥α K,L), the class of maps of level at least α from spaces in K to spaces in L, in such a way that, for finite α, Lev ≥α (BS,BS) consists of the Stone duals of Boolean lattice embeddings that preserve all prenex first-order formulas of quantifier rank (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  40
    The simplest axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2004 - Studia Logica 77 (3):385 - 411.
    We provide a quantifier-free axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry in a language containing only absolute geometrically meaningful ternary operations (in the sense that they have the same interpretation in Euclidean geometry as well). Each axiom contains at most 4 variables. It is known that there is no axiom system for plane hyperbolic consisting of only prenex 3-variable axioms. Changing one of the axioms, one obtains an axiom system for plane Euclidean geometry, expressed in the same language, all of whose (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  7
    On the complexity of finding falsifying assignments for Herbrand disjunctions.Pavel Pudlák - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):769-783.
    Suppose that Φ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${{\it \Phi}}$$\end{document} is a consistent sentence. Then there is no Herbrand proof of ¬Φ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\neg {\it \Phi}}$$\end{document}, which means that any Herbrand disjunction made from the prenex form of ¬Φ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\neg {\it \Phi}}$$\end{document} is falsifiable. We show that the problem of finding such a falsifying assignment is hard in the following sense. For every (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 62