Results for 'why should i be moral'

979 found
Order:
  1.  41
    On "Why Should I Be Moral?".Thomas C. Mayberry - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (2):361 - 373.
    Some philosophers hold that there are nonmoral reasons that can be used to justify being moral and that these are “in a certain way” more fundamental than moral reasons. Presumably these reasons could also be given in some circumstances for not being moral, although this is not clear. Moral reasons, in this view, might be overriding “on the level of everyday life,” but not “at the most fundamental level.” I take this to mean that should (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Why Should I Be Moral? Revisited.Kai Nielsen - 1984 - American Philosophical Quarterly 21 (1):81 - 91.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3. Why should I be moral?Peter Singer - unknown
    “The question has, as I have already said, been a central concern of moral philosophers from the time of Plato until the Nineteenth Century. It would be tedious to list the philosophers who have discussed the issue, for the list would exclude hardly any of the major moral philosophers of the past. The names of some of them will occur in the course of this thesis.” … “In the Conclusion, I consider the present state of the question and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Why Should I Be Moral?Kai Nielsen - 1963 - Methodos 15 (59-60):275-306.
  5.  37
    Why should I be moral? : toward a defence of the categoricity and normative authority of moral considerations.Kent Hurtig - 2004 - Dissertation, St. Andrews
    Can we ever be fully practically justified in acting contrary to moral demands? My contention is that the answer is 'no'. I argue that by adopting a 'buck-passing' account of wrongness we can provide a philosophically satisfying answer to the familiar 'why should I be moral?'. In working my way toward the buck-passing account of wrongness, I outline the metaethical and 'metanormative' assumptions on which my theory stands. I also consider and reject the 'internalist' answer to 'why (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  91
    Is "why should I be moral?" An absurdity?Kai Nielsen - 1958 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 36 (1):25 – 32.
  7.  41
    Why Should I Be Moral?D. A. Lloyd Thomas - 1970 - Philosophy 45 (172):128 - 139.
    It first needs to be shown that this question raises a problem, for many people think it is answered, or at least dissolved, in the following way. There are two independent ways of answering the question “Why should I do X?”; one ultimately in terms of what I want to do, the other ultimately in terms of what I morally ought to do. Thus showing that I morally ought to do something is a final justification of a course of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  30
    Why should I be moral?P. S. Wadia - 1964 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 42 (2):216 – 226.
    The author sides with the linguistic philosophers in that to analyse 'moral reasoning' is to provide a conceptual description of a prescriptive or normative area of language. He considers the question of why we should adopt a "moral point of view" in terms of toulmin (who thinks it is a meaningless question) and baier and nelson (who think it is legitimate). The author argues that it is a crucial question which must be answered. He concludes that baier (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  26
    Why Should I Be Moral? A Reconsideration.Donald Walhout - 1959 - Review of Metaphysics 12 (4):570 - 588.
    Before we can approach an answer we need to distinguish various meanings of the question and determine what the ultimate question is. In doing this it will be necessary first to analyze some of the principal terms in the question, particularly the terms "I," "why," and "moral.".
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Why Should I Be Moral?Brad Hooker - 1986
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  22
    Why Should I Be Moral?Marvin Glass - 1973 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):191 - 195.
  12. Why Should I be Moral?Dorothy Mitchell - 1970 - Ratio (Misc.) 12 (2):138.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Dismissive Replies to "Why Should I Be Moral?".John J. Tilley - 2009 - Social Theory and Practice 35 (3):341-368.
    The question "Why should I be moral?," taken as a request for reasons to be moral, strikes many philosophers as silly, confused, or otherwise out of line. Hence we find many attempts to dismiss it as spurious. This paper addresses four such attempts and shows that they fail. It does so partly by discussing various errors about reasons for action, errors that lie at the root of the view that "Why should I be moral?" is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  13
    Theism, morality and the 'Why should I be moral?' question.John Bishop - 1985 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 17 (1/2):3.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Moral Scepticism: Why Ask "Why Should I Be Moral"?Richard Arnot Home Bett - 1986 - Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley
    Many of us have a prereflective sense--or at least, a hope--that there are reasons to be moral which apply to an agent regardless of what his or her existing motivations may be. The view that there are no such reasons may, then, be regarded as a form of moral scepticism. The philosophical position which seems most fit to refute this form of moral scepticism, and hence to support our prereflective sense, is a Kantian view of morality, according (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  46
    Theism, morality and the 'why should I be moral?' Question.John Bishop - 1984 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 (3):3 - 21.
  17. Why Should I Be Good?Bill Meacham & Austin Tx - 2007 - Philosophy Now 1 (63).
    In any sense of "being good" consequences are of utmost importance.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Why Should I Care About Morality?Arnold Zuboff - 2001 - Philosophy Now 31:24-27.
    For a while in this article it seems impossible to articulate a compelling reason for refraining from killing an innocent stranger with the press of a button when this would earn one a small prize and would be done with absolutely guaranteed immunity from any punishment or other harm (including even an instantaneous elimination of any chance of a guilty memory, achieved through hypnosis, and an ironclad commitment from God not to condemn the killing). After many failed attempts, a compelling (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  32
    “Why Should I?” Can Foot Convince the Sceptic?Anselm W. Müller - 2018 - In Micah Lott (ed.), Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 151-185.
    For Philippa Foot, the essence of morality consists in acting on the reasons on which, qua human being, one ought to act; and this ought is one of “natural normativity”—the same ought that also occurs in statements about what a plant or an animal, qua exhibiting a certain form of life, “ought” to be like in various respects, or how its organs “ought” to function. Of this conception Foot avails herself in order to refute the moral sceptic—an undertaking that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20. Why moral philosophers are not and should not be moral experts.David Archard - 2011 - Bioethics 25 (3):119-127.
    Professional philosophers are members of bioethical committees and regulatory bodies in areas of interest to bioethicists. This suggests they possess moral expertise even if they do not exercise it directly and without constraint. Moral expertise is defined, and four arguments given in support of scepticism about their possession of such expertise are considered and rejected: the existence of extreme disagreement between moral philosophers about moral matters; the lack of a means clearly to identify moral experts; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  21. "WHY BE MORAL?" The Cheng Brothers' neo-confucian answer.Yong Huang - 2008 - Journal of Religious Ethics 36 (2):321-353.
    In this article, I present a neo-Confucian answer, by Cheng Hao and Cheng Yi, to the question, "Why should I be moral?" I argue that this answer is better than some representative answers in the Western philosophical tradition. According to the Chengs, one should be moral because it is a joy to perform moral actions. Sometimes one finds it a pain, instead of a joy, to perform moral actions only because one lacks the necessary (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  42
    Richard Price, the Debate on Free Will, and Natural Rights.Gregory I. Molivas - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (1):105-123.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Richard Price, the Debate on Free Will, and Natural RightsGregory I. MolivasWhen Richard Price projected metaphysical assumptions onto his ethical theory, he elaborated a conception of man as a normatively self-regulating being. Endowed with rationality, man is a “law unto himself.” Price’s political writings postulated accordingly that man should be his own legislator. The first proposition appeared in his ethics in the context of man’s identification with his (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  2
    Reception of ethics of discourse in modern philosophy.L. I. Tetyuev - 2019 - RUDN Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):240-252.
    The article analyzes the theoretical foundations of the modern project of rational ethics, in which the ethics of discourse is interpreted as a critical theory of society and a critic of modern morality. I. Kant was one of the first to offer the possibility of generalizing the norms of morality and perception of ethics as a transcendental critique of morality. Neo-Kantianism develops ethics as the most important part of the philosophical system and fixes its scope by the idealistic theory of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  52
    “Why Be Moral?” and Reforming Selves.A. Mark Williamson - 1991 - The Monist 74 (1):107-125.
    Even given the final truths of what is right and wrong, good and bad, ethics is not complete. For one may yet ask “Why should I be moral?” Of course, we have no prior assurance that it will be possible to provide a non-moral and justifiable answer to the rational and self-interested person. Nevertheless, I claim that reasons for being moral can be provided even for the rational, self-interested, and remorseless individual who knows he will not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  59
    Why Be Moral?LaRue Tone Hosmer - 1997 - Business Ethics Quarterly 7 (4):137-143.
    Professors Bill Shaw and John Corvino, in a response article published in the July, 1996 issue of Business Ethics Quarterly, provide a clearly courteous and obviously well-intended criticism of my original (1994) position on the question of why a manager, and in consequence an organization, should be moral. I disagree with their reasoning and, because I believe that this form of the “Why Be Moral?” question lies at the heart of any potential juncture between our field of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  26.  8
    IV*—Why Should I Be Just?D. R. Fisher - 1977 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 77 (1):43-62.
    D. R. Fisher; IV*—Why Should I Be Just?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 77, Issue 1, 1 June 1977, Pages 43–62, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristote.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  14
    “ Why Should I Be Rational?”.Oscar Wilde Max Black - 1982 - Dialectica 36 (2-3):147-168.
    SummaryThe prevalent view that a question expressed by the interrogative title must be absurd and in no need of a reasoned response is rejected. Popper's contention that commitment to rationality has only an irrational basis is criticised. A preliminary attempt is made to resolve some genuine perplexities about the justification of rationality by invoking the notion of a “quasi‐rationality” shared by human beings and other animals. Ah appendix on the metaphor of support is attached.RésuméĽauteur rejette ľopinion prédominate selon laquelle la (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Why Should One Be Moral? A Normative Exercise in the Context of Contemporary India.Rajendra Prasad - 1982 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 9 (4):321.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  35
    Why Should I Be Ethical? Some Answers from Mahabharata.Sankaran Manikutty - 2012 - Journal of Human Values 18 (1):19-32.
    The article seeks to answer the question: Why should I be ethical? For an answer, it examines Mahabharata, the ancient Indian epic. It seeks to explore the complex ethical issues posed by Mahabharata, how they are relevant to us as individuals and to us as managers and teachers of management in business schools and enables us to understand how possibly we could use the insights to better our lives and of those around us. Mahabharata’s central message, concludes the article, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  19
    Why Be Moral? Comments on Yong Huang's Book on the Cheng Brothers.JeeLoo Liu - 2019 - Philosophy East and West 69 (1):268-280.
    In Why Be Moral: Learning from the Neo-Confucian Cheng Brothers, Yong Huang presents a comparative study on the moral philosophy of the Cheng brothers as how comparative philosophy should be done: to engage in contemporary philosophical problems and to propose solutions that could be gleaned from the ideas of ancient Chinese philosophers. His analysis provides a paradigm for comparative philosophy. I think this is the right way to do comparative philosophy—to focus on problem solving rather than textual (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  30
    “ Why Should I Be Rational?”.Max Black & Oscar Wilde - 1982 - Dialectica 36 (2‐3):147-168.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  23
    On "Should I Be Moral?": A Reply to Snare.Michael S. Pritchard - 1976 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6 (1):121 - 126.
  33.  10
    Why Should Man Be Moral?Wan Jun-ren - 2003 - Modern Philosophy 1:010.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  2
    Why Should I Be Just?D. R. Fisher - 1977 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 77:43 - iv.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Why should our mind-reading abilities be involved in the explanation of phenomenal consciousness?Diana I. Pérez - 2008 - Análisis Filosófico 28 (1):35-84.
    In this paper I consider recent discussions within the representationalist theories of phenomenal consciousness, in particular, the discussions between first order representationalism (FOR) and higher order representationalism (HOR). I aim to show that either there is only a terminological dispute between them or, if the discussion is not simply terminological, then HOR is based on a misunderstanding of the phenomena that a theory of phenomenal consciousness should explain. First, I argue that we can defend first order representationalism from Carruthers' (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  15
    Should Patients Be Required to Undergo Standard Chemotherapy Before Being Eligible for Novel Phase I Immunotherapy Clinical Trials?Benjamin S. Wilfond, Christian Morales & Holly A. Taylor - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (4):66-67.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  45
    Why Should We Become Posthuman? The Beneficence Argument Questioned.Andrés Pablo Vaccari - 2019 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (2):192-219.
    Why should we become posthuman? There is only one morally compelling answer to this question: because posthumanity will be a more beneficial state, better than present humanity. This is the Posthuman Beneficence Argument, the centerpiece of the liberal transhumanist defense of “directed evolution.” In this article, I examine PBA and find it deficient on a number of lethal counts. My argument focuses on the writings of transhumanist philosopher Nick Bostrom, who has developed the most articulate defense of PBA and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  63
    Why be moral?A. I. Melden - 1948 - Journal of Philosophy 45 (17):449-456.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39.  30
    Why the histrionic personality disorder should not be in the DSM: A new taxonomic and moral analysis.Carol Steinberg Gould - 2011 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 4 (1):26-40.
    In this article, I argue for a reconsideration of the taxonomy of the Histrionic Personality Disorder. First, HPD does not carry the negative ethical implications of the other Cluster Bs, which are Anti-Social, Borderline, and Narcissistic. Using Aristotelian notions of character as a heuristic device, I argue that ontologically HPD is not a personality disorder, but instead a cultural disorder, a result of attitudes toward traditionally feminine styles of interaction. This explains the confusion in the research between HPD and hysteria (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Why Moral Error Theorists Should Become Revisionary Moral Expressivists.Toby Svoboda - 2015 - Journal of Moral Philosophy:1-25.
    Moral error theorists hold that morality is deeply mistaken, thus raising the question of whether and how moral judgments and utterances should continue to be employed. Proposals include simply abolishing morality, adopting some revisionary fictionalist stance toward morality, and conserving moral judgments and utterances unchanged. I defend a fourth proposal, namely revisionary moral expressivism, which recommends replacing cognitivist moral judgments and utterances with non-cognitivist ones. Given that non-cognitivist attitudes are not truth apt, revisionary expressivism (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  41. Oh, All the Wrongs I Could Have Performed! Or: Why Care about Morality, Robustly Realistically Understood.David Enoch & Itamar Weinshtock Saadon - 2023 - In Paul Bloomfield & David Copp (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism. Oxford University Press. pp. 434-462.
    Suppose someone is brought up as an orthodox Jew, and so only eats kosher, is very conservative sexually, etc. Suppose they then find out that this Judaism stuff is just all a big mistake. If they then regret all the shrimp they could have eaten, all the sex!, this makes perfect sense. Not so, however, if someone finds out that moral realism is false, and they now regret all the fun they could have had hurting people’s feeling, etc. Even (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  28
    Why Moral Error Theorists Should Become Revisionary Moral Expressivists.Toby Svoboda - 2015 - New Content is Available for Journal of Moral Philosophy (1):48-72.
    _ Source: _Page Count 25 Moral error theorists hold that morality is deeply mistaken, thus raising the question of whether and how moral judgments and utterances should continue to be employed. Proposals include simply abolishing morality, adopting some revisionary fictionalist stance toward morality, and conserving moral judgments and utterances unchanged. I defend a fourth proposal, namely revisionary moral expressivism, which recommends replacing cognitivist moral judgments and utterances with non-cognitivist ones. Given that non-cognitivist attitudes are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  43.  58
    Undercutting Justice – Why legal representation should not be allocated by the market.Shai Agmon - 2021 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 20 (1):99-123.
    The adversarial legal system is traditionally praised for its normative appeal: it protects individual rights; ensures an equal, impartial, and consistent application of the law; and, most importantly, its competitive structure facilitates the discovery of truth – both in terms of the facts, and in terms of the correct interpretation of the law. At the same time, legal representation is allocated as a commodity, bought and sold in the market: the more one pays, the better legal representation one gets. In (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Why Care about Being an Agent.Caroline T. Arruda - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (3):488-504.
    The question ‘Why care about being an agent?’ asks for reasons to be something that appears to be non-optional. But perhaps it is closer to the question ‘Why be moral?’; or so I shall argue. Here the constitutivist answer—that we cannot help but have this aim—seems to be the best answer available. I suggest that, regardless of whether constitutivism is true, it is an incomplete answer. I argue that we should instead answer the question by looking at our (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45. Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach.Alvin I. Goldman - 1999 - Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (2):201-217.
    Why should a citizen vote? There are two ways to interpret this question: in a prudential sense, and in a moral sense. Under the first interpretation, the question asks why—or under what circumstances—it is in a citizen's self-interest to vote. Under the second interpretation, it asks what moral reasons citizens have for voting. I shall mainly try to answer the moral version of the question, but my answer may also, in some circumstances, bear on the prudential (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  46.  43
    Why Should Educators Care about Argumentation?Harvey Siegel - 1995 - Informal Logic 17 (2).
    Educators who are reflective about their educational endeavours ask themselves questions like: What is the aim of education? What moral, methodological, or other constraints govern our educational activities and efforts? One natural place to look for answers is in the philosophy of education, which (among other things) tries to provide systematic answers to these questions. One general answer offered by the philosophy of education is that the aim of education consists in fostering the development of students' rationality. On this (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47. Reasons to Be Moral Revisted: Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 33.Sam Black & Evan Tiffany (eds.) - 2010 - University of Calgary Press.
    H.A. Prichard argued that the “why should I be moral?” question is the central subject matter of moral theory. Prichard famously claimed to have proved that all efforts to answer that question are doomed. Many contributors to this volume of contemporary papers attempt to reconstruct Prichard’s argument. They claim either explicitly or implicitly that Prichard was mistaken, and philosophy can contribute to meaningful engagement with the ‘why be moral?’ question. A theme to emerge from these papers (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  17
    Can a Moral Man Raise the Question, "Should I Be Moral?".Frank Snare - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (3):499 - 507.
    Let it be allowed, though virtue or moral rectitude does indeed consist in affection to and pursuit of what is right and good, as such; yet, that when we sit down in a cool hour, we can neither justify to ourselves this or any other pursuit, till we are convinced that it will be for our happiness, or at least not contrary to it.—Butler, Sermon XIThere are a number of different grounds on which philosophers have argued that the question (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49. Why No Classical Theist, Let Alone Orthodox Christian, Should Ever Be a Compatibilist.Jerry L. Walls - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (1):75-104.
    I argue that no classical theist, and even more no orthodox Christian, should affirm compatibilism in our world. However plausible compatibilism may be on atheistic assumptions, bringing God into the equation should radically alter our judgment on this ongoing controversy. In particular, if freedom and determinism are compatible, then God could have created a world in which all persons freely did only the good at all times. Given this implication of compatibilism, three issues that are already challenging become (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  17
    Bernard Gert on on "Why Should I Act Morally?".Michael S. Pritchard - 2013 - Teaching Ethics 14 (1):15-19.
1 — 50 / 979