Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Aristotle's Metaphysics" by S. Marc Cohen

This is an automatically generated and experimental page

If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.

This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.

References in the text to the books of Aristotle’s Metaphysics are given by Greek letter. In order (with the corresponding Roman numeral given in parentheses) these are: Α (I), α (II), Β (III), Γ (IV), Δ (V), Ε (VI), Ζ (VII), Η (VIII), Θ (IX), Ι (X), Κ (XI), Λ (XII), Μ (XIII), Ν (XIV). Translations are taken from the Ross (1924) edition.

  • Ackrill, J. L., 1963, Aristotle: Categories and De Interpretatione, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1965, “Aristotle’s Distinction between Energeia and Kinesis,” in Bambrough 1965, pp. 121–141. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1972, “Aristotle’s Definitions of Psyche,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 73: 119–133. (Scholar)
  • Addis, L., 1972, “Aristotle and the Independence of Substances,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54: 699–708. (Scholar)
  • Albritton, Rogers, 1957, “Forms of Particular Substances in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Journal of Philosophy, 54: 699–707 (Scholar)
  • Allen, R. E., 1969, “Individual Properties in Aristotle’s Categories,” Phronesis, 14: 31–39. (Scholar)
  • Anagnostopoulos, Andreas, 2011, “Senses of ‘Dunamis’ and the Structure of Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics’ Theta,” Phronesis, 56: 388–425. (Scholar)
  • Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (ed.), 2009, A Companion to Aristotle, Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. (Scholar)
  • Angioni, Lucas, 2014, “Definition and Essence in Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics’ vii 4,” Ancient Philosophy, 34: 75–100. (Scholar)
  • Annas, J., 1974, “Individuals in Aristotle’s Categories: Two Queries,” Phronesis, 19: 146–152. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1976, Aristotle: Metaphysics Books Μ and Ν, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Anscombe, G. E. M., 1953, “The Principle of Individuation,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 27: 83–96; reprinted in Barnes, Schofield, and Sorabji 1979, pp. 88–95. (Scholar)
  • Aranyosi, István A., 2004, “Aristotelian Nonsubstantial Particulars,” Philosophical Writings, 26: 3–12. (Scholar)
  • Bäck, Allan, 2004, “What is being QUA being?,” Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, 82: 37–58. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2007, “Aristotle’s Abstract Ontology,” Newsletters for the Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy, 8 (2): 12–23. (Scholar)
  • Bambrough, R. (ed.), 1965, New Essays on Plato and Aristotle, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Scholar)
  • Barnes J., M. Schofield, and R. R. K. Sorabji (eds.), 1975, Articles on Aristotle, Vol 1. Science, London: Duckworth. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1979, Articles on Aristotle, Vol 3. Metaphysics, London: Duckworth. (Scholar)
  • Beere, Jonathan, 2009, Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Berti, E., 2001, “Multiplicity and Unity of Being in Aristotle,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 101: 185–207. (Scholar)
  • Block, I., 1978, “Substance in Aristotle,” in Paideia: Special Aristotle Issue, G. C. Simmons (ed.), Brockport, NY, 59–64. (Scholar)
  • Bogen, J. and J. E. McGuire (eds.), 1985, How Things Are: Studies in Predication and the History of Philosophy, Dordrecht: Reidel. (Scholar)
  • Bolton, R., 1994, “Aristotle’s Conception of Metaphysics as a Science,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 321–354. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995, “Science and the Science of Substance in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ζ,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 76: 419–469. (Scholar)
  • Bostock, D., 1994, Aristotle: Metaphysics Books Ζ and Η, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Bowin, John, 2008, “Aristotle on Identity and Persistence,” Apeiron, 41 (1): 63–90. (Scholar)
  • Brody, B. A., 1973, “Why Settle for Anything Less Than Good Old-fashioned Aristotelian Essentialism?Noûs, 7: 351–365. (Scholar)
  • Brook, Angus, 2015, “Substance and the Primary Sense of Being in Aristotle,” Review of Metaphysics, 68: 521–544. (Scholar)
  • Buchheim, T., 2001, “The Functions of the Concept of Physis in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 20: 201–234. (Scholar)
  • Burnyeat, M. F. et al., 1979, Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy. (Scholar)
  • Burnyeat, M. F., 2001, A Map of Metaphysics Zeta, Pittsburgh, PA: Mathesis Publications. (Scholar)
  • Chappell, V., 1973, “Aristotle’s Conception of Matter,” Journal of Philosophy, 70: 679–696. (Scholar)
  • Charles, David, 1993, “Aristotle on Substance, Essence, and Biological Kinds,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 7: 227–261. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “Matter and Form: Unity, Persistence, and Identity,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 75–105. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2002, Aristotle on Meaning and Essence, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Charlton, W., 1972, “Aristotle and the Principle of Individuation,” Phronesis, 17: 239–249. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1983, “Prime Matter: a Rejoinder,” Phronesis, 28: 197–211. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “Aristotle on Identity,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 41–54. (Scholar)
  • Chen, Chung-Hwan, 1957, “Aristotle’s Concept of Primary Substance in Books Ζ and Η of the Metaphysics,” Phronesis, 2: 46–59. (Scholar)
  • Code, Alan, 1978, “No Universal is a Substance: an Interpretation of  Metaphysics Ζ 13, 1038b 8–15,” in G. C. Simmons 1978, pp. 65–74. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1984, “The Aporematic Approach to Primary Being in Metaphysics Ζ,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Suppl. Vol. 10: 1–20. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1985, “On the Origins of Some Aristotelian Theses About Predication,” in Bogen and McGuire 1985, pp. 101–131. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1986, “Aristotle: Essence and Accident,” in Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends, R. Grandy and R. Warner (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 411–439. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1987, “Metaphysics and Logic,” in Matthen 1987a, pp. 127–149. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995, “Potentiality in Aristotle’s Science and Metaphysics,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 76: 405–418. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1997, “Aristotle’s Metaphysics as a Science of Principles,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 51: 357–378. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1999, “Monty Furth’s Aristotle: 10 Years Later,” Philosophical Studies, 94: 69–80. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “Changes, Powers and Potentialities in Aristotle,” in N. Reshotko (ed.), Desire, Identity, and Existence: Essays in Honor of T. M. Penner, Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing, pp. 251–271. (Scholar)
  • Cohen, S. Marc, 1978a, “Essentialism in Aristotle,” Review of Metaphysics, 31: 387–405. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1978b, “Individual and Essence in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” in Simmons 1978, pp. 75–85. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1984, “Aristotle and Individuation,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Suppl. Vol. 10: 41–65. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2008, “Kooky Objects Revisited: Aristotle’s Ontology,” Metaphilosophy, 39: 3–19. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “Substances,” in Anagnostopoulos 2009, pp. 197–212. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2013, “Accidental Beings in Aristotle’s Ontology,” in Reason and Analysis in Ancient Greek Philosophy, Anagnostopoulos and Miller, Jr. (eds.), Dordrecht: Springer, 231–242. (Scholar)
  • Cohen, Sheldon M., 1981, “Proper Differentiae, the Unity of Definition, and Aristotle’s Essentialism,” The New Scholasticism, 55: 229–240. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1984, “Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Material Substrate,” Philosophical Review, 93: 171–194. (Scholar)
  • Cooper, John, 1988, “Metaphysics in Aristotle’s Embryology,” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, no. 214: 14–41; reprinted in Devereux and Pellegrin 1990, pp. 55–84. (Scholar)
  • Corkum, Phil, 2008, “Aristotle on Ontological Dependence,” Phronesis, 53 (1): 65–92. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “Aristotle on Nonsubstantial Individuals,” Ancient Philosophy, 29 (2): 289–310. (Scholar)
  • Cresswell, M. J., 1971, “Essence and Existence in Plato and Aristotle,” Theoria, 37: 91–113. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1975, “What Is Aristotle’s Theory of Universals?” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 53: 238–247. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “Non-contradiction and Substantial Predication,” Theoria, 69: 166–183. (Scholar)
  • Dahl, Norman, 1997, “Two Kinds of Essence in Aristotle: A Pale Man Is Not the Same as His Essence,” Philosophical Review, 106: 233–265. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1999, “On Substance Being the Same As Its Essence in Metaphysics Ζ6: The Pale Man Argument,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 37: 1–27. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “On Substance Being the Same as its Essence in Metaphysics vii 6: The Argument about Platonic Forms,” Ancient Philosophy, 23: 153–179. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2007, “Substance, Sameness, and Essence in ‘Metaphysics’ VII 6,” Ancient Philosophy, 27 (1): 107–126. (Scholar)
  • Dancy, R., 1975, “On Some of Aristotle’s First Thoughts about Substances,” Philosophical Review, 84: 338–373. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1978, “On some of Aristotle’s Second Thoughts about Substances: Matter,” Philosophical Review, 87: 372–413. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1983, “Aristotle on Existence,” Synthèse, 54: 409–442. (Scholar)
  • Deavel, C. J., 2003, “Unity and Primary Substance for Aristotle,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 77: 159–172. (Scholar)
  • Devereux, Daniel, 1992, “Inherence and Primary Substance in Aristotle’s Categories,” Ancient Philosophy, 12: 113–131. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “The Relation between Books Zeta and Eta of Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 25: 159–211. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2010, “Aristotle on the Form and Definition of a Human Being: Definitions and Their Parts in ‘Metaphysics Z’ 10 and 11,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 26: 167–196. (Scholar)
  • Devereux, D. and P. Pellegrin (eds.), 1990, Biologie, Logique et Metaphysique chez Aristote, Paris: Éditions du CNRS. (Scholar)
  • Driscoll, J., 1981, “Eidê in Aristotle’s Earlier and Later Theories of Substance,” in O’Meara 1981, pp. 129–159. (Scholar)
  • Duerlinger, J., 1970, “Predication and Inherence in Aristotle’s Categories,” Phronesis, 15: 179–203. (Scholar)
  • Durrant, M., 1975, “Essence and Accident,” Mind, 84: 595–600. (Scholar)
  • Ebert, T., 1998, “Aristotelian Accidents,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 16: 133–159. (Scholar)
  • Engmann, J., 1973, “Aristotle’s Distinction Between Substance and Universal,” Phronesis, 18: 139–155. (Scholar)
  • Erginel, M. M., 2004, “Non-substantial Individuals in Aristotle’s Categories, ” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 26: 185–212. (Scholar)
  • Ferejohn, Michael, 1980, “Aristotle on Focal Meaning and the Unity of Science,” Phronesis, 25: 117–128. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994a, “Matter, Definition and Generation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 10: 35–58. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994b, “The Definition of Generated Composites in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 291–318. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “Logical and Physical Inquiries in Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics’,” Modern Schoolman, 80 (4): 325–350. (Scholar)
  • Fine, Gail, 1984, “Separation,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 2: 31–87. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1985, “Separation: a Reply to Morrison,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 3: 159–165. (Scholar)
  • Fine, Kit, 1992, “Aristotle on Matter,” Mind, 101: 35–57. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “A Puzzle Concerning Matter and Form,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 13–40. (Scholar)
  • Frede, Michael, 1987, Essays in Ancient Philosophy, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1990, “The Definition of Sensible Substances in Metaphysics Ζ,” in Devereux and Pellegrin 1990, pp. 113–129. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “Aristotle’s Notion of Potentiality in Metaphysics Θ,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 173–194. (Scholar)
  • Frede, Michael and Günther Patzig, 1988, Aristoteles Metaphysik Ζ, Munich: C. H. Beck. (Scholar)
  • Furth, Montgomery, 1978, “Transtemporal Stability in Aristotelean Substances,” Journal of Philosophy, 75: 624–646. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1985, Aristotle’s Metaphysics 7–10, Indianapolis: Hackett. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1987, “Aristotle on the Unity of Form,” in Matthen 1987a, pp. 77–102. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1988, Substance, Form and Psyche: an Aristotelian Metaphysics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1990, “Specific and Individual Forms in Aristotle,” in Devereux and Pellegrin 1990, pp. 106–110. (Scholar)
  • Gerson, Lloyd P. (ed.) and Joseph Owens, 2007, Aristotle’s Gradations of being in Metaphysics E-Z, South Bend: St Augustine’s Press. (Scholar)
  • Gill, Mary Louise, 1989, Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1993, “Matter against Substance,” Synthèse, 96: 379–397. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “Individuals and Individuation in Aristotle,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 55–72. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995, “Symposium on Aristotle on Substance and Predication,” Ancient Philosophy, 15: 511–520. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2001, “Aristotle’s Attack on Universals,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 20: 235–260. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005a, “Myles Burnyeat’s Map of Metaphysics Zeta,” Philosophical Quarterly, 55: 114–121. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005b, “Aristotle’s Metaphysics Reconsidered,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 43: 223–251. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2006, “Commentary on Modrak,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 22: 136–142. (Scholar)
  • Gotthelf, Allan, 1999, “A Biological Provenance,” Philosophical Studies, 94: 35–56. (Scholar)
  • Graham, D. W., 1987a, “The Paradox of Prime Matter,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 25: 475–490. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1987b, Aristotle’s Two Systems, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Granger, H., 1980, “A Defense of the Traditional Position concerning Aristotle’s non-substantial Particulars,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10: 593–606. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1984, “Aristotle on Genus and Differentia,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 22: 1–24. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1989, “Aristotle’s Natural Kinds,” Philosophy, 64: 245–247. (Scholar)
  • Green, Jerry, 2014, “The Underlying Argument of Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics Ζ.3’,” Phronesis, 59: 321–342. (Scholar)
  • Grene, M., 1974, “Is Genus to Species as Matter to Form? Aristotle and Taxonomy,” Synthèse, 28: 51–69. (Scholar)
  • Grice, H. P., 1988, “Aristotle on the Multiplicity of Being,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 69: 175–200. (Scholar)
  • Halper, E., 1987, “A Solution to the Problem of Sensible Substance,” Journal of Philosophy, 84: 666–672. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1989, One and Many in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, the Central Books, Columbus: Ohio State University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1975, “Aristotle on Primary ousia,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 57: 1–20. (Scholar)
  • Hartman, Edwin, 1976, “Aristotle on the Identity of Substance and Essence,” Philosophical Review, 85: 545–561. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1977, Substance, Body, and Soul: Aristotelian Investigations, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
  • Haslanger, Sally, 1994, “Parts, Compounds, and Substantial Unity,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 129–170. (Scholar)
  • Heinaman, R., 1981a, “Non-substantial Individuals in the Categories,” Phronesis, 26: 295–307. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1981b, “Knowledge of Substance in Aristotle,” Journal of Hellenic Studies, 101: 63–77. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1997, “Frede and Patzig on Definition in Metaphysics Ζ.10 and 11,” Phronesis, 42: 283–298. (Scholar)
  • Hennig, Boris, 2008, “Matter in Z3,” Foundations of Science, 13 (3–4): 199–215. (Scholar)
  • Henry, Devin, 2011, “Aristotle’s Pluralistic Realism,” The Monist, 94 (2): 197–220. (Scholar)
  • Hetherington, S.C., 1984, “A Note on Inherence,” Ancient Philosophy, 4: 218–223. (Scholar)
  • Ide, Harry A., 1992, “Dunamis in Metaphysics IX,” Apeiron, 25: 1–26. (Scholar)
  • Irwin, T. H., 1981, “Homonymy in Aristotle,” Review of Metaphysics, 34: 523–544. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1988, Aristotle’s First Principles, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Jones, B., 1972, “Individuals in Aristotle’s Categories,” Phronesis, 17: 107–123. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1975, “An Introduction to the first five chapters of Aristotle’s Categories,” Phronesis, 20: 146–172. (Scholar)
  • Kirwan, C. A., 1970, “How Strong are the Objections to Essence?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 71: 43–59. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1971, Aristotle: Metaphysics Books Gamma, Delta, and Epsilon, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Kohl, Markus, 2008, “Substancehood and Subjecthood in Aristotle’s ‘Categories’,” Phronesis, 53 (2): 152–179. (Scholar)
  • Koslicki, Kathrin, 2006, “Aristotle’s Mereology and the Status of Form,” Journal of Philosophy, 103 (12): 715–736. (Scholar)
  • Kosman, L. A., 1984, “Substance, Being, and Energeia,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 2: 121–149 (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “The Activity of Being in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 195–213. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1999, “Aristotelian Metaphysics and Biology: Furth’s Substance, Form and Psyche,” Philosophical Studies, 94: 57–68. (Scholar)
  • Kung, Joan, 1977, “Aristotelian Essence and Explanation,” Philosophical Studies, 31: 361–383. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1978, “Can Substance be Predicated of Matter?Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 60: 140–159. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1986, “Aristotle on ‘Being is Said in Many Ways’,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 3: 3–18. (Scholar)
  • Lacey, A. R., 1965, “Ousia and Form in Aristotle,” Phronesis, 10: 54–69. (Scholar)
  • Lear, Jonathan, 1988, Aristotle: the Desire to Understand, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • LeBlond, J. M., 1979, “Aristotle on Definition,” in Barnes, Schofield, and Sorabji 1979, pp. 63–79. (Scholar)
  • Lesher, James H., 1971, “Aristotle on Form, Substance, and Universals: a Dilemma,” Phronesis, 16: 169–178. (Scholar)
  • Lewis, Frank A., 1982, “Accidental Sameness in Aristotle,” Philosophical Studies, 39: 1–36. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1983, “Form and Predication in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” in Bogen and McGuire 1985, pp. 59–83. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1984, “What is Aristotle’s Theory of Essence?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Suppl. Vol. 10: 89–132. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1991, Substance and Predication in Aristotle, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “Aristotle on the Relation between a Thing and its Matter,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 247–77. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995a, “Aristotle on the Unity of Substance,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 76: 222–265. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995b, “Symposium on Substance, Predication, and Unity in Aristotle,” Ancient Philosophy, 15: 521–549. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “Friend or Foe? Some Encounters with Plato in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Zeta,” Modern Schoolman, 80: 365–390. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, “A Nose by Any Other Name: Sameness, Substitution, and Essence in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ζ5,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 28: 161–199. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “Form and Matter,” in Anagnostopoulos 2009, pp. 162–185. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2011, “Predication, Things, and Kinds in Aristotle’s ‘Metaphysics’,” Phronesis, 56: 350–387. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2013, How Aristotle Gets By in Metaphysics Zeta, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Lloyd, A. C., 1970, “Aristotle’s Principle of Individuation,” Mind, 79: 519–529. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1981, Form and Universal in Aristotle, Liverpool: F. Cairns. (Scholar)
  • Loux, Michael J., 1979, “Form, Species, and Predication in Metaphysics Ζ, Η, and Θ,” Mind, 88: 1–23. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1991, Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ζ and Η, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995a, “Symposium on Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Ancient Philosophy, 15: 495–510. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995b, “Composition and Unity: An Examination of Metaphysics Η.6,” In May Sim (ed.), The Crossroads of Norm and Nature. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “Aristotle: Metaphysics,” in The Blackwell Guide to Ancient Philosophy, C. Shields (ed.), Malden MA: Blackwell Publishing, pp. 163–183. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, “Aristotle on Matter, Form, and Ontological Strategy,” Ancient Philosophy, 25: 81–123. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “Aristotle on Universals,” in Anagnostopoulos 2009, pp. 186–196. (Scholar)
  • MacKinnon, D. M., 1965, “Aristotle’s Conception of Substance,” in Bambrough 1965, pp. 97–119. (Scholar)
  • Makin, Stephen, 2004, “What Does Aristotle Mean by Priority in Substance?Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 24: 209–238. (Scholar)
  • Malcolm, John, 1993, “On the Endangered Species of the Metaphysics,” Ancient Philosophy, 13: 79–93. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1996, “On the Duality of Eidos in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 78: 1–10. (Scholar)
  • Mansion, S., 1979, “The Ontological Composition of Sensible Substances in Aristotle (Metaphysics VII, 7–9),” in Barnes, Schofield, and Sorabji 1979, pp. 80–87. (Scholar)
  • Matthen, Mohan (ed.), 1987a, Aristotle Today: Essays on Aristotle’s Ideal of Science, Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1987b, “Individual Substances as Hylomorphic Complexes,” in Matthen 1987a, pp. 151–176. (Scholar)
  • Matthews, Gareth B., 1982, “Accidental Unities,” in Language and Logos: Studies in Ancient Greek Philosophy, M. Schofield and M. C. Nussbaum (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 223–240. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1986, “Gender and Essence in Aristotle,” in Women and Philosophy, J. L. Thompson (ed.), supplement to Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64: 16–25. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1989, “The Enigma of Categories la20ff and Why it Matters,” Apeiron, 22: 91–104. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1990, “Aristotelian Essentialism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Suppl. 50: 251–262. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1991, “Container Metaphysics According to Aristotle’s Greek Commentators,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supp. vol. 17: 7–23. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “Aristotelian Categories,” in Anagnostopoulos 2009, pp. 144–161. (Scholar)
  • Matthews, Gareth B. and S. Marc Cohen, 1968, “The One and the Many,” Review of Metaphysics, 21: 630–655. (Scholar)
  • McPartland, Keith, 2013, “On an Attempt to Resolve an Inconsistency in Aristotle’s Account of Inherence,” Ancient Philosophy, 33: 375–390. (Scholar)
  • Menn, Stephen, 1994, “The Origins of Aristotle’s Concept of energeia,” Ancient Philosophy, 14: 73–114. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2001, “Metaphysics Z 10–16 and the Argument-Structure of Metaphysics Z,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 21: 83–134. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2011, “On Myles Burnyeat’s ‘Map of Metaphysics Zeta’,” Ancient Philosophy, 31 (1): 161–202. (Scholar)
  • Miller, F. D., 1978, “Aristotle’s Use of Matter,” In Simmons 1978, pp. 105–119. (Scholar)
  • Modrak, Deborah K., 1979, “Forms, Types, and Tokens in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 17: 371–381. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1983, “Forms and Compounds,” in Bogen and McGuire 1985, pp. 85–99. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1989, “Aristotle on the difference between Mathematics and Physics and First Philosophy,” Apeiron, 22: 121–139. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2006, “Form and Function,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 22: 111–135. (Scholar)
  • Moravcsik, J. M. E., 1967, “Aristotle on Predication,” Philosophical Review, 76: 80–96. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “Essences, Powers, and Generic Propositions,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 229–244. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1985b, “Separation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 3: 125–157. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1985c, “Separation: a Reply to Fine,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 3: 167–173. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1993, “The Place of Unity in Aristotle’s Metaphysical Project,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 9: 131–156. (Scholar)
  • Moser, P., 1983, “Two Notions of Substance in Metaphysics Ζ,” Apeiron, 17: 103–112. (Scholar)
  • O’Meara, D. J. (ed.), 1981, Studies in Aristotle, Washington: Catholic University Press. (Scholar)
  • Owen, G. E. L., 1965a, “Inherence,” Phronesis, 10: 97–105. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1965b, “Aristotle on the Snares of Ontology,” in Bambrough 1965, pp. 69–95. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1965c, “The Platonism of Aristotle,” Proceedings of the British Academy 50 125–150; reprinted in Barnes, Schofield, and Sorabji 1975, pp. 14–34. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1978, “Particular and General,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 79: 1–21. (Scholar)
  • Owens, Joseph, 1978, The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics, 3d ed., rev., Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies. (Scholar)
  • Page, C., 1985, “Predicating Forms of Matter in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Review of Metaphysics, 39: 57–82. (Scholar)
  • Panayides, Christos, 1999, “Aristotle on the Priority of Actuality in Substance,” Ancient Philosophy, 19: 327–344. (Scholar)
  • Pelletier, F. J., 1979, “Sameness and Referential Opacity in Aristotle,” Noûs, 13: 283–311. (Scholar)
  • Pena, Lorenzo, 1999, “The Coexistence of Contradictory Properties in the Same Subject According to Aristotle,” Apeiron, 32: 203–229. (Scholar)
  • Peramatzis, Michael, 2011, Priority in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Perin, Casey, 2007, “Substantial Universals in Aristotle’s Categories,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 33: 125–143. (Scholar)
  • Reeve, C. D. C., 2000, Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Indianapolis: Hackett. (Scholar)
  • Regis, E., 1976, “Aristotle’s ‘Principle of Individuation’,” Phronesis, 21: 157–166. (Scholar)
  • Robinson, H. M., 1974, “Prime Matter in Aristotle,” Phronesis, 19: 168–188. (Scholar)
  • Rorty, Richard, 1973, “Genus as Matter: a Reading of Metaphysics Ζ-H,” in Lee, Mourelatos, and Rorty (eds.) Exegesis and Argument, Phronesis, Suppl. 1, Assen: Van Gorcum. 393–420. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1974, “Matter as Goo: Comments on Grene’s Paper,” Synthèse, 28: 71–77. (Scholar)
  • Ross, W. D., 1924, Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Scaltsas, T., 1985, “Substratum, Subject, and Substance,” Ancient Philosophy, 5: 215–40. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994a, Substances and Universals in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994b, “Substantial Holism,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 107–128 (Scholar)
  • Scaltsas, T., D. Charles, and M. L. Gill (eds.), 1994, Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Schofield, M., 1972, “Metaphysics Ζ3: Some Suggestions,” Phronesis, 17: 97–101. (Scholar)
  • Sellars, Wilfrid, 1957, “Substance and Form in Aristotle,” Journal of Philosophy, 54: 688–699. (Scholar)
  • Shields, C., 1990, “The Generation of Form in Aristotle,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 7: 367–390. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2008, “Substance and Life in Aristotle,” Apeiron, 41 (3): 129–151. (Scholar)
  • Simmons, G. C. (ed.), 1978, Paideia: Special Aristotle Issue, Brockport, NY. (Scholar)
  • Smith, J. A., 1921, “Tode ti in Aristotle,” Classical Review, 35: 19. (Scholar)
  • Spellman, Lynne, 1989, “Specimens of Natural Kinds and the Apparent Inconsistency of Metaphysics Ζ,” Ancient Philosophy, 9: 49–65. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995, Substance and Separation in Aristotle, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • Stahl, D., 1981, “Stripped Away: Some Contemporary Obscurities Surrounding Metaphysics Ζ3 (1029a10–26),” Phronesis, 26: 177–180. (Scholar)
  • Stein, Nathanael, 2012, “Causal Necessity in Aristotle,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 20 (5): 855–879. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2011, “Aristotle’s Causal Pluralism,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 93 (2): 121–147. (Scholar)
  • Stough, C. L., 1972, “Language and Ontology in Aristotle’s Categories,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 10: 261–272. (Scholar)
  • Studtmann, Paul, 2008, “On the several Senses of ‘Form’ in Aristotle,” Apeiron, 41 (3): 1–26. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2011, “Aristotle’s Early and Late Ontologies,” Philosophy Compass, 6 (7): 469–476. (Scholar)
  • Sykes, R. D., 1975, “Form in Aristotle: Universal or Particular?Philosophy, 50: 311–331. (Scholar)
  • Teloh, H., 1979, “Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ζ.13,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 5: 77–79. (Scholar)
  • Thorp, J. W., 1974, “Aristotle’s Use of Categories,” Phronesis, 19: 238–256. (Scholar)
  • Tweedale, M., 1987, “Aristotle’s Universals,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 65: 412–426. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1988, “Aristotle’s Realism,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 18: 501–526. (Scholar)
  • Verbeke, G., 1981, “Aristotle’s Metaphysics viewed by the Ancient Greek Commentators, ” in O’Meara 1981, pp. 107–127. (Scholar)
  • Wedin, Michael V., 1991, “PARTisanship in Metaphysics Z,” Ancient Philosophy, 11: 361–385. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1993, “Nonsubstantial Individuals,” Phronesis, 38: 137–165. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1999, “The Scope of Non-Contradiction: A Note on Aristotle’s ‘Elenctic’ Proof in Metaphysics Gamma 4,” Apeiron, 32: 231–242. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2000, Aristotle’s Theory of Substance: The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “The Science and Axioms of Being,” in Anagnostopoulos 2009, pp. 125–143. (Scholar)
  • Wheeler, Mark, 1999, “The Possibility of Recurrent Individuals in Aristotle’s Organon,” Gregorianum, 80: 539–551. (Scholar)
  • Wheeler, S., 1977. “The Theory of Matter from Metaphysics Ζ, Η, Θ,” International Studies in Philosophy, 13–22. (Scholar)
  • White, Nicholas P., 1972, “The Origins of Aristotle’s Essentialism,” Review of Metaphysics, 26: 57–85. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1986, “Identity, Modal Individuation, and Matter in Aristotle,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 11: 475–494. (Scholar)
  • Whiting, J. E., 1986, “Form and Individuation in Aristotle,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 3: 359–377. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1991, “Metasubstance: Critical Notice of Frede-Patzig and Furth,” Philosophical Review, 100: 607–639. (Scholar)
  • Williams, D. C., 1958, “Form and Matter,” Philosophical Review, 67: 291–312, 499–521. (Scholar)
  • Witt, Charlotte, 1987, “Hylomorphism in Aristotle,” Journal of Philosophy, 84: 673–679. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1989a, “Hylomorphism in Aristotle,” Apeiron, 22: 141–158. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1989b, “Aristotelian Essentialism Revisited,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 27: 285–298. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1989c, Substance and Essence in Aristotle: an Interpretation of Metaphysics VII-IX, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “The Priority of Actuality in Aristotle,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 215–228. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, Ways of Being: Potentiality and Actuality in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
  • Woods, Michael, 1967, “Problems in Metaphysics Ζ, Chapter 13,”; in J. Moravcsik (ed.), Aristotle: A Collection of Critical Essays, New York: Anchor, pp. 215–238. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1974, “Substance and Essence in Aristotle,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 75: 167–180. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1991a, “Particular Forms Revisited,” Phronesis, 26: 75–87. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1991b, “Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Suppl. Vol.: Aristotle and the Later Tradition, 41–56. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1993, “Form, Species, and Predication in Aristotle,” Synthèse, 96: 399–415. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1994, “The Essence of a Human Being and the Individual Soul in Metaphysics Ζ and Η ,” in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill 1994, pp. 279–290. (Scholar)
  • Yu, Jiyuan, 1997, “Two Conceptions of Hylomorphism in Metaphysics ΖΗΘ,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 15: 119–45. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2001a, “The Identity of Form and Essence in Aristotle,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39: 299–312. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2001b, “What is the Focal Meaning of Being in Aristotle?Apeiron, 34: 205–231. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, The Structure of Being in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Dordrecht: Kluwer. (Scholar)

Generated Sun Mar 26 05:23:35 2017