Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Aristotle’s Natural Philosophy" by Istvan Bodnar

This is an automatically generated and experimental page

If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.

This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.

Primary Sources

  • Aristotle, De generatione et corruptione, translated with notes by C. J. F. Williams, Oxford: Clarendon Press (Clarendon Aristotle Series), 1982.
  • Aristotle, On coming-to-be and passing-away (De generatione and corruptione), revised Greek text with introduction and commentary by Harold H. Joachim, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1926.
  • Aristote, De la génération et de la corruption, critical edition, French translation and notes by Marwan Rashed, Paris: Les Belles Lettres (Collection Budé), 2005.
  • Aristote, Du ciel, (De Caelo = On the Heavens), Greek text and French translation by Paul Moraux, Paris: Les Belles lettres (Collection Budé), 1965.
  • Aristotle, Physics, Books I–II, translated with introduction and notes by William Charlton, Oxford: Clarendon Press (Clarendon Aristotle Series), 1970 (2nd. ed. 1992).
  • Aristotle, Physics, Books III–IV, translated with notes by Edward Hussey, Oxford: Clarendon Press (Clarendon Aristotle Series), 1983.
  • Aristotle, Physics, Book VIII, translated with commentary by Daniel W. Graham, Oxford: Clarendon Press (Clarendon Aristotle Series), 1999.
  • Aristotle, Physics, revised Greek text with introduction and commentary by William David Ross, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1936.
  • Theophrastus, On First Principles (known as his Metaphysics), Greek Text and Medieval Arabic Translation, edited and translated with introduction, commentaries and glossaries by Dimitri Gutas, Leiden: Brill, 2010.

Secondary Sources

  • Ackrill, J. L., 1991, “Change and Aristotle’s theological argument,” in H. Blumenthal and H. Robinson (eds.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Supplementary Volume), Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 57–66; reprinted in J.L. Ackrill, Essays on Plato and Aristotle, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, 131–41. (Scholar)
  • Annas, Julia, 1982, “Aristotle on inefficient causes,” Philosophical Quarterly, 32: 311–26. (Scholar)
  • Bodnár, István M., 1997, “Movers and elemental motions in Aristotle,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Volume 15), Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 81–117. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2016, “Cases of Celestial Teleology in Metaphysics Λ,” in Christoph Horn, Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda – New Essays (Volume 15), Boston/Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 247–268. (Scholar)
  • Bordt, Michael, SJ, 2011, “Why Aristotle’s God is not the Unmoved Mover,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Volume 40): Essays in Memory of Michael Frede, edited by James Allen, Eyjólfur Kjalar Emilsson, Wofgang-Rainer Mann and Benjamin Morison, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 92–109. (Scholar)
  • Burnyeat, Myles F., 2008, “Kinesis vs Energeia: A much-read passage in (but not of) Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Volume 34), Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 219–291 (Scholar)
  • Charles, David, 2015, “Aristotle”s processes,“ in Mariska Leunissen (ed.), Aristotle”s Physics: A critical guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 186–205. (Scholar)
  • Cherniss, Harold F., 1944, Aristotle’s criticism of Plato and the Academy, Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. (Scholar)
  • Code, Alan, 1987, “Soul as efficient cause in Aristotle’s embryology,” Philosophical Topics, 15: 51–59. (Scholar)
  • Coope, Ursula, 2004, “Aristotle’s account of agency in Physics III.3,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 20: 201–221. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “Change and its relation to actuality and potentiality,” in Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle, Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 277–291. (Scholar)
  • de Haas, Frans and Mansfeld, Jaap (eds.), 2004, Aristotle: On Generation and Corruption, Book I: Symposium Aristotelicum, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Falcon, Andrea, 2005, Aristotle and the science of nature: Unity without uniformity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2015, “The argument of Physics VIII,” in Mariska Leunissen (ed.), Aristotle‘s Physics: A critical guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 265–283. (Scholar)
  • Frede, Michael and Charles, David (eds.), 2000, Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda: Symposium Aristotelicum, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Freeland, Cynthia A., 1987, “Aristotle on bodies, matter, and potentiality,” in Allan Gotthelf and James Lennox (eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 392–407. (Scholar)
  • Furley, David, 1978, “Self-movers,” in G.E.R. Lloyd and G.E.L. Owen (eds.), Aristotle on mind and the senses, (Proceedings of the Seventh Symposium Aristotelicum), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 165–79; Reprinted in David Furley (ed.), Cosmic problems: Essays on Greek and Roman philosophy of nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989, pp. 121–31. (Scholar)
  • Gill, Mary Louise, 1980, “Aristotle’s theory of causal action in Physics III. 3,” Phronesis, 25: 129–47. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “The theory of the elements in De caelo 3 and 4,” in Alan C. Bowen and Christian Wildberg (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle’s De caelo, Leiden-Boston: Brill, pp. 119–161. (Scholar)
  • Hankinson, R.J., 2009, “Natural, unnatural, and preternatural motions: Contrariety and argument for the elements in De caelo 1.2–4,” in Alan C. Bowen and Christian Wildberg (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle’s De caelo, Leiden-Boston: Brill, pp. 83–118. (Scholar)
  • Judson, Lindsay, 1994, “Heavenly motion and the unmoved mover,” in Mary Louise Gill and James G. Lennox (eds.), Self-motion: From Aristotle to Newton, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 155–171. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2015, “Aristotle’s astrophysics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Volume 49), Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 151–192. (Scholar)
  • Judson, Lindsay (ed.), 1991, Aristotle’s Physics: A collection of essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Kelsey, Sean, 2006, “Aristotle Physics I 8,” Phronesis, 51: 330–361. (Scholar)
  • –––. 2008, “The place of I 7 in the argument of Physics I,” Phronesis, 53: 180–208. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2010, “Hylomorphism in Aristotle’s Physics,” Ancient Philosophy, 30: 107–124. (Scholar)
  • Kosman, L. Aryeh, 1969, “Aristotle’s definition of motion,” Phronesis, 14: 40–62. (Scholar)
  • Makin, Stephen, 1990/1991, “An ancient principle about causation,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 91: 135–52. (Scholar)
  • Marmodoro, Anna, 2007, “The union of cause and effect in Aristotle: Physics 3. 3,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Volume 32), Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 205–232. (Scholar)
  • Matthen, Mohan and Hankinson, R.J., 1993, “Aristotle’s universe: Its form and matter,” Synthèse, 96: 417–435. (Scholar)
  • Moravcsik, Julius M., 1991, “What makes reality intelligible? Reflections on Aristotle’s theory of aitia,” in Lindsay Judson (ed.), Aristotle’s Physics: A collection of essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 31–48. (Scholar)
  • Mourelatos, Alexander P., 1967, “Aristotle’s powers and modern empiricism,” Ratio, 9: 97–104. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1984, “Aristotle’s rationalist account of qualitative interaction,” Phronesis, 29: 1–16. (Scholar)
  • Peramatzis, Michail M., 2011, Priority in Aristotle’s metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Solmsen, Friedrich, 1960, Aristotle’s system of the physical world, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
  • Sorabji, Richard, 1988, Matter, space, and motion: Theories in Antiquity and their sequel, London: Duckworth or Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1983, Time, creation, and the continuum: Theories in Antiquity and the early Middle Age, London: Duckworth or Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
  • Stavrineas, Stasinos, 2015, “Nature as a principle of change,” in Mariska Leunissen, ed., Aristotle’s Physics: A critical guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 46–65. (Scholar)
  • Turnbull, Robert G., 1958, “Aristotle’s debt to the ‘natural philosophy’ of the Phaedo,” Philosophical Quarterly, 8: 131–43. (Scholar)
  • Wardy, R., 1990, The chain of change: A study of Aristotle’s Physics VII, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • Waterlow, Sarah, 1982, Nature, change, and agency in Aristotle’s Physics, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
  • Wildberg, Christian, 1988, John Philoponus’ criticism of Aristotle’s theory of aether (Peripatoi 16), Berlin: De Gruyter 1988. (Scholar)

Generated Sun Jan 23 02:40:36 2022