Linked bibliography for the SEP article "The Computational Theory of Mind" by Michael Rescorla
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Aitchison, L. and Lengyel, M., 2016, “The Hamiltonian Brain: Efficient Probabilistic Inference with Excitatory-Inhibitory Neural Circuit Dynamics”, PloS Computational Biology, 12: e1005186. (Scholar)
- Arjo, D., 1996, “Sticking Up for Oedipus: Fodor on Intentional Generalizations and Broad Content”, Mind and Language, 11: 231–245. (Scholar)
- Aydede, M., 1998, “Fodor on Concepts and Frege Puzzles”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79: 289–294. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Computationalism and Functionalism: Syntactic Theory of Mind Revisited”, in Turkish Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, G. Irzik and G. Güzeldere (eds), Dordrecht: Springer. (Scholar)
- Aydede, M. and P. Robbins, 2001, “Are Frege Cases Exceptions to Intentional Generalizations?”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31: 1–22. (Scholar)
- Bechtel, W. and A. Abrahamsen, 2002, Connectionism and the Mind, Malden: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Bermúdez, J.L., 2005, Philosophy of Psychology: A Contemporary Introduction, New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Science of the Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Block, N., 1978, “Troubles With Functionalism”, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 9: 261–325. (Scholar)
- –––, 1981, “Psychologism and Behaviorism”, Philosophical Review, 90: 5–43. (Scholar)
- –––, 1983, “Mental Pictures and Cognitive Science”, Philosophical Review, 92: 499–539. (Scholar)
- –––, 1986, “Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10: 615–678. (Scholar)
- –––, 1990, “Can the Mind Change the World?”, in Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam, G. Boolos (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, The Mind as the Software of the Brain, in Invitation to Cognitive Science, vol. 3: Thinking, E. Smith and B. Osherson (eds), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Block, N. and J. Fodor, 1972, “What Psychological States Are Not”, The Philosophical Review, 81: 159–181. (Scholar)
- Boden, M., 1991, “Horses of a Different Color?”, in Ramsey et al. 1991: 3–19. (Scholar)
- Bontly, T., 1998, “Individualism and the Nature of Syntactic States”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49: 557–574. (Scholar)
- Bowie, G.L., 1982, “Lucas’s Number is Finally Up”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 11: 79–285. (Scholar)
- Brogan, W., 1990, Modern Control Theory, 3rd edition. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall. (Scholar)
- Buckner, C., 2019, “Deep Learning: A Philosophical Introduction”, Philosophy Compass, 14: e12625. (Scholar)
- Buckner, C., and J. Garson, 2019, “Connectionism and Post-Connectionist Models”, in Sprevak and Colombo 2019: 175–191. (Scholar)
- Buesing, L., J. Bill, B. Nessler, and W. Maass, W., 2011, “Neural Dynamics of Sampling: A Model for Stochastic Computation in Recurring Networks of Spiking Neurons”, PLOS Computational Biology, 7: e1002211. (Scholar)
- Burge, T., 1982, “Other Bodies”, in Thought and Object, A. Woodfield (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reprinted in Burge 2007: 82–99. (Scholar)
- –––, 1986, “Individualism and Psychology”, The Philosophical Review, 95: 3–45. Reprinted in Burge 2007: 221–253. (Scholar)
- –––, 1989, “Individuation and Causation in Psychology”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 70: 303–322. Reprinted in Burge 2007: 316–333. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “Intentional Properties and Causation”, in Philosophy of Psychology, C. MacDonald and G. MacDonald (eds), Oxford: Blackwell. Reprinted in Burge 2007: 334–343. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Disjunctivism and Perceptual Psychology”, Philosophical Topics, 33: 1–78. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, Foundations of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010a, Origins of Objectivity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010b, “Origins of Perception”, Disputatio, 4: 1–38. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010c, “Steps Towards Origins of Propositional Thought”, Disputatio, 4: 39–67. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, Cognition through Understanding, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Camp, E., 2009, “A Language of Baboon Thought?”, in The Philosophy of Animal Minds, R. Lurz (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Carruthers, P., 2003, “On Fodor’s Problem”, Mind and Language, 18: 508–523. (Scholar)
- Chalmers, D., 1990, “Syntactic Transformations on Distributed Representations”, Connection Science, 2: 53–62. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, “Why Fodor and Pylyshyn Were Wrong: The Simplest Refutation”, Philosophical Psychology, 63: 305–319. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “On Implementing a Computation”, Minds and Machines, 4: 391–402. (Scholar)
- –––, 1996a, “Does a Rock Implement Every Finite State Automaton?”, Synthese, 108: 309–333. (Scholar)
- –––, 1996b, “Minds, Machines, and Mathematics”, Psyche, 2: 11–20. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “The Components of Content”, in Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings, D. Chalmers (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “A Computational Foundation for the Study of Cognition”, The Journal of Cognitive Science, 12: 323–357. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “The Varieties of Computation: A Reply”, The Journal of Cognitive Science, 13: 213–248. (Scholar)
- Chemero, A., 2009, Radical Embodied Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Cheney, D. and R. Seyfarth, 2007, Baboon Metaphysics: The Evolution of a Social Mind, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Scholar)
- Chomsky, N., 1965, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Church, A., 1936, “An Unsolvable Problem of Elementary Number Theory”, American Journal of Mathematics, 58: 345–363. (Scholar)
- Churchland, P.M., 1981, “Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes”, Journal of Philosophy, 78: 67–90. (Scholar)
- –––, 1989, A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, Neurophilosophy At Work, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Churchland, P.S., 1986, Neurophilosophy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Churchland, P.S., C. Koch, and T. Sejnowski, 1990, “What Is Computational Neuroscience?”, in Computational Neuroscience, E. Schwartz (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Churchland, P.S. and T. Sejnowski, 1992, The Computational Brain, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Clark, A., 2014, Mindware: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Cognitive Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Clayton, N., N. Emery, and A. Dickinson, 2006, “The Rationality of Animal Memory: Complex Caching Strategies of Western Scrub Jays”, in Rational Animals?, M. Nudds and S. Hurley (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Copeland, J., 1996, “What is Computation?”, Synthese, 108: 335–359. (Scholar)
- Cover, T. and J. Thomas, 2006, Elements of Information Theory, Hoboken: Wiley. (Scholar)
- Crane, T., 1991, “All the Difference in the World”, Philosophical Quarterly, 41: 1–25. (Scholar)
- Crick, F. and C. Asanuma, 1986, “Certain Aspects of the Anatomy and Physiology of the Cerebral Cortex”, in McClelland et al. 1987: 333–371. (Scholar)
- Cummins, R., 1989, Meaning and Mental Representation, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Davidson, D., 1980, Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Dayan, P., 2009, “A Neurocomputational Jeremiad”, Nature Neuroscience, 12: 1207. (Scholar)
- Dennett, D., 1971, “Intentional Systems”, Journal of Philosophy, 68: 87–106. (Scholar)
- –––, 1987, The Intentional Stance, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1991, “Mother Nature versus the Walking Encyclopedia”, in Ramsey, et al. 1991: 21–30. (Scholar)
- Dietrich, E., 1989, “Semantics and the Computational Paradigm in Cognitive Psychology”, Synthese, 79: 119–141. (Scholar)
- Donahoe, J., 2010, “Man as Machine: A Review of Memory and Computational Brain, by C.R. Gallistel and A.P. King”, Behavior and Philosophy, 38: 83–101. (Scholar)
- Dreyfus, H., 1972, What Computers Can’t Do, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1992, What Computers Still Can’t Do, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Dretske, F., 1981, Knowledge and the Flow of Information, Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, “Mental Events as Structuring Causes of Behavior”, in Mental Causation, J. Heil and A. Mele (eds), Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Edelman, S., 2008, Computing the Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “How to Write a ‘How a Build a Brain’ Book”, Trends in Cognitive Science, 18: 118–119. (Scholar)
- Egan, F., 1991, “Must Psychology be Individualistic?”, Philosophical Review, 100: 179–203. (Scholar)
- –––, 1992, “Individualism, Computation, and Perceptual Content”, Mind, 101: 443–459. (Scholar)
- –––, 1999, “In Defense of Narrow Mindedness”, Mind and Language, 14: 177–194. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “Naturalistic Inquiry: Where Does Mental Representation Fit In?”, in Chomsky and His Critics, L. Antony and N. Hornstein (eds), Malden: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “A Modest Role for Content”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41: 253–259. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “How to Think About Mental Content”, Philosophical Studies, 170: 115–135. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “The Nature and Function of Content in Computational Models”, in Sprevak and Colombo 2019: 247–258. (Scholar)
- Eliasmith, C., 2003, “Moving Beyond Metaphors: Understanding the Mind for What It Is”, Journal of Philosophy, 100: 493–520. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, How to Build a Brain, Oxford: Oxford: University Press. (Scholar)
- Eliasmith, C. and C.H. Anderson, 2003, Neural Engineering: Computation, Representation and Dynamics in Neurobiological Systems, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Elman, J., 1990, “Finding Structure in Time”, Cognitive Science, 14: 179–211. (Scholar)
- Feferman, S., 1996, “Penrose’s Gödelian Argument”, Psyche, 2: 21–32. (Scholar)
- Feldman, J. and D. Ballard, 1982, “Connectionist Models and their Properties”, Cognitive Science, 6: 205–254. (Scholar)
- Field, H., 2001, Truth and the Absence of Fact, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Figdor, C., 2009, “Semantic Externalism and the Mechanics of Thought”, Minds and Machines, 19: 1–24. (Scholar)
- Fodor, J., 1975, The Language of Thought, New York: Thomas Y. Crowell. (Scholar)
- –––, 1980, “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology”, Behavioral and Brain Science, 3: 63–73. Reprinted in Fodor 1981: 225–253. (Scholar)
- –––, 1981, Representations, Cambridge: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1983, The Modularity of Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1987, Psychosemantics, Cambridge: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1990, A Theory of Content and Other Essays, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1991, “A Modal Argument for Narrow Content”, Journal of Philosophy, 88: 5–26. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, The Elm and the Expert, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1998, Concepts, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2000, The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Reply to Steven Pinker ‘So How Does the Mind Work?’”, Mind and Language, 20: 25–32. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, LOT2, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Fodor, J. and Z. Pylyshyn, 1988, “Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis”, Cognition, 28: 3–71. (Scholar)
- Frege, G., 1879/1967, Begriffsschrift, eine der Arithmetischen Nachgebildete Formelsprache des Reinen Denkens. Reprinted as Concept Script, a Formal Language of Pure Thought Modeled upon that of Arithmetic, in From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, J. van Heijenoort (ed.), S. Bauer-Mengelberg (trans.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Gallistel, C.R., 1990, The Organization of Learning, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Gallistel, C.R. and King, A., 2009, Memory and the Computational Brain, Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Gandy, R., 1980, “Church’s Thesis and Principles for Mechanism”, in The Kleene Symposium, J. Barwise, H. Keisler, and K. Kunen (eds). Amsterdam: North Holland. (Scholar)
- Gödel, K., 1936/65. “On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems”, Reprinted with a new Postscript in The Undecidable, M. Davis (ed.), New York: Raven Press Books. (Scholar)
- Grice, P., 1989, Studies in the Ways of Words, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Hadley, R., 2000, “Cognition and the Computational Power of Connectionist Networks”, Connection Science, 12: 95–110. (Scholar)
- Harnish, R., 2002, Minds, Brains, Computers, Malden: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Haykin, S., 2008, Neural Networks: A Comprehensive Foundation, New York: Prentice Hall. (Scholar)
- Haugeland, J., 1985, Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Horgan, T. and J. Tienson, 1996, Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Horowitz, A., 2007, “Computation, External Factors, and Cognitive Explanations”, Philosophical Psychology, 20: 65–80. (Scholar)
- Johnson, K., 2004, “On the Systematicity of Language and Thought”, Journal of Philosophy, 101: 111–139. (Scholar)
- Johnson-Laird, P., 1988, The Computer and the Mind, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, “The History of Mental Models”, in Psychology of Reasoning: Theoretical and Historical Perspectives, K. Manktelow and M.C. Chung (eds), New York: Psychology Press. (Scholar)
- Kazez, J., 1995, “Computationalism and the Causal Role of Content”, Philosophical Studies, 75: 231–260. (Scholar)
- Kelso, J., 1995, Dynamic Patterns, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Klein, C., 2012, “Two Paradigms for Individuating Implementations”, Journal of Cognitive Science, 13: 167–179. (Scholar)
- Kriegesgorte, K., 2015, “Deep Neural Networks: A New Framework for Modeling Biological Vision and Brain Information Processing”, Annual Review of Vision Science, 1: 417–446. (Scholar)
- Kriegesgorte, K. and P. Douglas, 2018, “Cognitive Computational Neuroscience”, Nature Neuroscience, 21: 1148–1160. (Scholar)
- Krishevsky, A., I. Sutskever, and G. Hinton, 2012, “ImageNet Classification with Deep Convolutional Neural Networks”, Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems, 25: 1097–1105. (Scholar)
- Krotov, D., and J. Hopfield, 2019, “Unsupervised Learning by Competing Hidden Units”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 116: 7723–7731. (Scholar)
- Ladyman, J., 2009, “What Does it Mean to Say that a Physical System Implements a Computation?”, Theoretical Computer Science, 410: 376–383. (Scholar)
- LeCun, Y., Y. Bengio, and G. Hinton, 2015, “Deep Learning”, Nature, 521: 436–444. (Scholar)
- Lewis, D., 1969, “Lucas against Mechanism”, Philosophy, 44: 231–3. (Scholar)
- –––, 1972, “Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50: 249–58. (Scholar)
- –––, 1979, “Lucas Against Mechanism II”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 9: 373–376. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, “Reduction of Mind”, in A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, S. Guttenplan (ed.), Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Lizier, J., B. Flecker, and P. Williams, 2013, “Towards a Synergy-based Account of Measuring Information Modification”, Proceedings of the 2013 IEEE Symposium on Artificial Life (ALIFE), Singapore: 43–51. (Scholar)
- Ludwig, K. and S. Schneider, 2008, “Fodor’s Critique of the Classical Computational Theory of Mind”, Mind and Language, 23: 123–143. (Scholar)
- Lucas, J.R., 1961, “Minds, Machines, and Gödel”, Philosophy, 36: 112–137. (Scholar)
- Ma, W. J., 2019, “Bayesian Decision Models: A Primer”, Neuron, 104: 164–175. (Scholar)
- Maass, W., 1997, “Networks of Spiking Neurons: The Next Generation of Neural Network Models”, Neural Networks, 10: 1659–1671. (Scholar)
- MacLennan, B., 2012, “Analog Computation”, Computational Complexity, R. Meyers (ed.), New York: Springer. (Scholar)
- Marblestone, A., G. Wayne, and K. Kording, 2016, “Toward an Integration of Deep Learning and Neuroscience”, Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience, 10: 1–41. (Scholar)
- Marcus, G., 2001, The Algebraic Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Marr, D., 1982, Vision, San Francisco: W.H. Freeman. (Scholar)
- McClelland, J., D. Rumelhart, and G. Hinton, 1986, “The Appeal of Parallel Distributed Processing”, in Rumelhart et al. 1986: 3–44. (Scholar)
- McClelland, J., D. Rumelhart, and the PDP Research Group, 1987, Parallel Distributed Processing, vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- McCulloch, W. and W. Pitts, 1943, “A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity”, Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 7: 115–133. (Scholar)
- McDermott, D., 2001, Mind and Mechanism, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Mendola, J., 2008, Anti-Externalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Milkowski, M., 2013, Explaining the Computational Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Miller, P., 2018, An Introductory Course in Computational Neuroscience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Mole, C., 2014, “Dead Reckoning in the Desert Ant: A Defense of Connectionist Models”, Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5: 277–290. (Scholar)
- Murphy, K., 2012, Machine Learning: A Probabilistic Perspective, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Naselaris, T., Bassett, D., Fletcher, A., Körding, K., Kriegeskorte, N., Nienborg, H., Poldrack, R., Shohamy, D., and Kay, K., 2018, “Cognitive Computational Neuroscience: A New Conference for an Emerging Discipline”, Trends in Cognitive Science, 22: 365–367. (Scholar)
- Nagel, E. and J.R. Newman, 1958, Gödel’s Proof, New York: New York University Press.
- Newell, A., 1990, Unified Theories of Cognition, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Newell, A. and H. Simon, 1956, “The Logic Theory Machine: A Complex Information Processing System”, IRE Transactions on Information Theory, IT-2, 3: 61–79. (Scholar)
- –––, 1976, “Computer Science as Empirical Inquiry: Symbols and Search”, Communications of the ACM, 19: 113–126. (Scholar)
- O’Keefe, J. and L. Nadel, 1978, The Hippocampus as a Cognitive Map, Oxford: Clarendon University Press. (Scholar)
- Ockham, W., 1957, Summa Logicae, in his Philosophical Writings, A Selection, P. Boehner (ed. and trans.), London: Nelson. (Scholar)
- Orhan, A. E. and Ma, W. J., 2017, “Efficient Probabilistic Inference in Generic Neural Networks Trained with Non-probabilistic Feedback ”, Nature Communications, 8: 1–14. (Scholar)
- Peacocke, C., 1992, A Study of Concepts, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, “Externalist Explanation”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 67: 203–230. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, “Content, Computation, and Externalism”, Mind and Language, 9: 303–335. (Scholar)
- –––, 1999, “Computation as Involving Content: A Response to Egan”, Mind and Language, 14: 195–202. (Scholar)
- Penrose, R., 1989, The Emperor’s New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Perry, J., 1998, “Broadening the Mind”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58: 223–231. (Scholar)
- Piantadosi, S., J. Tenenbaum, and N. Goodman, 2012, “Bootstrapping in a Language of Thought”, Cognition, 123: 199–217. (Scholar)
- Piccinini, G., 2004, “Functionalism, Computationalism, and Mental States”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 35: 811–833. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Computing Mechanisms”, Philosophy of Science, 74: 501–526. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008a, “Computation Without Representation”, Philosophical Studies, 137: 205–241. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008b, “Some Neural Networks Compute, Others Don’t”, Neural Networks, 21: 311–321. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “The Resilience of Computationalism”, Philosophy of Science, 77: 852–861. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Computationalism”, in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, E. Margolis, R. Samuels, and S. Stich (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Piccinini, G. and A. Scarantino, 2010, “Computation vs. Information processing: Why their Difference Matters to Cognitive Science”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41: 237–246. (Scholar)
- Piccinini, G. and S. Bahar, 2013, “Neural Computation and the Computational Theory of Cognition”, Cognitive Science, 37: 453–488. (Scholar)
- Piccinini, G. and O. Shagrir, 2014, “Foundations of Computational Neuroscience”, Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 25: 25–30. (Scholar)
- Pinker, S., 2005, “So How Does the Mind Work?”, Mind and Language, 20: 1–24. (Scholar)
- Pinker, S. and A. Prince, 1988, “On Language and Connectionism”, Cognition, 28: 73–193. (Scholar)
- Pouget, A., Beck, J., Ma., W. J., and Latham, P., 2013, “Probabilistic Brains: Knowns and Unknowns”, Nature Neuroscience, 16: 1170–1178. (Scholar)
- Putnam, H., 1967, “Psychophysical Predicates”, in Art, Mind, and Religion, W. Capitan and D. Merrill (eds), Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Reprinted in Putnam 1975 as “The Nature of Mental States”: 429–440. (Scholar)
- –––, 1975, Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1983, Realism and Reason: Philosophical Papers, vol. 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1988, Representation and Reality, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, “The Best of All Possible Brains?”, The New York Times, November 20, 1994: 7. (Scholar)
- Pylyshyn, Z., 1984, Computation and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Quine, W.V.O., 1960, Word and Object, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Ramsey, W., S. Stich, and D. Rumelhart (eds), 1991, Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. (Scholar)
- Rescorla, M., 2009a, “Chrysippus’s Dog as a Case Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition”, in The Philosophy of Animal Minds, R. Lurz (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009b, “Cognitive Maps and the Language of Thought”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60: 377–407. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “How to Integrate Representation into Computational Modeling, and Why We Should”, Journal of Cognitive Science, 13: 1–38. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Against Structuralist Theories of Computational Implementation”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64: 681–707. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014a, “The Causal Relevance of Content to Computation”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88: 173–208. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014b, “A Theory of Computational Implementation”, Synthese, 191: 1277–1307. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Bayesian Perceptual Psychology”, in The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception, M. Matthen (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017a, “From Ockham to Turing—and Back Again”, in Turing 100: Philosophical Explorations of the Legacy of Alan Turing, (Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History), A. Bokulich and J. Floyd (eds), Springer. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017b, “Levels of Computational Explanation”, in Philosophy and Computing: Essays in Epistemology, Philosophy of Mind, Logic, and Ethics, T. Powers (ed.), Cham: Springer. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “A Realist Perspective on Bayesian Cognitive Science”, in Inference and Consciousness, A. Nes and T. Chan (eds.), New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Rogers, T. and J. McClelland, 2014, “Parallel Distributed Processing at 25: Further Explorations of the Microstructure of Cognition”, Cognitive Science, 38: 1024–1077. (Scholar)
- Rumelhart, D., 1989, “The Architecture of Mind: A Connectionist Approach”, in Foundations of Cognitive Science, M. Posner (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Rumelhart, D., G. Hinton, and R. Williams, 1986, “Learning Representations by Back-propagating Errors”, Nature, 323: 533–536. (Scholar)
- Rumelhart, D. and J. McClelland, 1986, “PDP Models and General Issues in Cognitive Science”, in Rumelhart et al. 1986: 110–146. (Scholar)
- Rumelhart, D., J. McClelland, and the PDP Research Group, 1986, Parallel Distributed Processing, vol. 1. Cambridge: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Rupert, R., 2008, “Frege’s Puzzle and Frege Cases: Defending a Quasi-Syntactic Solution”, Cognitive Systems Research, 9: 76–91. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, Cognitive Systems and the Extended Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Russell, S. and P. Norvig, 2010, Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach, 3rd ed., New York: Prentice Hall. (Scholar)
- Sawyer, S., 2000, “There Is No Viable Notion of Narrow Content”, in Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, B. McLaughlin and J. Cohen (eds), Malden: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Schneider, S., 2005, “Direct Reference, Psychological Explanation, and Frege Cases”, Mind and Language, 20: 423–447. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, The Language of Thought: A New Philosophical Direction, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Searle, J., 1980, “Minds, Brains, and Programs”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3: 417–457. (Scholar)
- –––, 1990, “Is the Brain a Digital Computer?”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 64: 21–37. (Scholar)
- Segal, G., 2000, A Slim Book About Narrow Content, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Shagrir, O., 2001, “Content, Computation, and Externalism”, Mind, 110: 369–400. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “Why We View the Brain as a Computer”, Synthese, 153: 393–416. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Review of Explaining the Computational Theory of Mind, by Marcin Milkowski”, Notre Dame Review of Philosophy, January 2014. (Scholar)
- –––, forthcoming, “In Defense of the Semantic View of Computation”, Synthese, first online 11 October 2018; doi:10.1007/s11229-018-01921-z (Scholar)
- Shannon, C., 1948, “A Mathematical Theory of Communication”, Bell System Technical Journal 27: 379–423, 623–656. (Scholar)
- Shapiro, S., 2003, “Truth, Mechanism, and Penrose’s New Argument”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32: 19–42. (Scholar)
- Shea, N., 2013, “Naturalizing Representational Content”, Philosophy Compass, 8: 496–509. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, Representation in Cognitive Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Sieg, W., 2009, “On Computability”, in Philosophy of Mathematics, A. Irvine (ed.), Burlington: Elsevier. (Scholar)
- Siegelmann, H. and E. Sontag, 1991, “Turing Computability with Neural Nets”, Applied Mathematics Letters, 4: 77–80. (Scholar)
- Siegelmann, H. and E. Sontag, 1995, “On the Computational Power of Neural Nets”, Journal of Computer and Science Systems, 50: 132–150. (Scholar)
- Silverberg, A., 2006, “Chomsky and Egan on Computational Theories of Vision”, Minds and Machines, 16: 495–524. (Scholar)
- Sloman, A., 1978, The Computer Revolution in Philosophy, Hassocks: The Harvester Press. (Scholar)
- Smolensky, P., 1988, “On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11: 1–74. (Scholar)
- –––, 1991, “Connectionism, Constituency, and the Language of Thought”, in Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, B. Loewer and G. Rey (eds), Cambridge: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Sperber, D., 2002, “In Defense of Massive Modularity”, in Language, Brain, and Cognitive Development: Essays in Honor of Jacques Mehler, E. Dupoux (ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Sprevak, M., 2010, “Computation, Individuation, and the Received View on Representation”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41: 260–270. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “Triviality Arguments About Computational Implementation”, in Sprevak and Colombo 2019: 175–191. (Scholar)
- –––, forthcoming, “Two Kinds of Information Processing in Cognition”, Review of Philosophy and Psychology. (Scholar)
- Sprevak, M. and Colombo, M., 2019, The Routledge Handbook of the Computational Mind, New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Stalnaker, R., 1999, Context and Content, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Stich, S., 1983, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Thelen, E. and L. Smith, 1994, A Dynamical Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Thrun, S., W. Burgard, and D. Fox, 2006, Probabilistic Robotics, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Thrun, S., M. Montemerlo, and H. Dahlkamp, et al., 2006, “Stanley: The Robot That Won the DARPA Grand Challenge”, Journal of Field Robotics, 23: 661–692. (Scholar)
- Tolman, E., 1948, “Cognitive Maps in Rats and Men”, Psychological Review, 55: 189–208. (Scholar)
- Trappenberg, T., 2010, Fundamentals of Computational Neuroscience, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Turing, A., 1936, “On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem”, Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42: 230–265. (Scholar)
- –––, 1950, “Computing Machinery and Intelligence”, Mind, 49: 433–460. (Scholar)
- van Gelder, T., 1990, “Compositionality: A Connectionist Variation on a Classical Theme”,Cognitive Science, 14: 355–384. (Scholar)
- van Gelder, T. and R. Port, 1995, “It’s About Time: An Overview of the Dynamical Approach to Cognition”, in Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition, R. Port and T. van Gelder (eds), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Varela, F., Thompson, E. and Rosch, E., 1991, The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- von Neumann, J., 1945, “First Draft of a Report on the EDVAC”, Moore School of Electrical Engineering, University of Pennsylvania. Philadelphia, PA. (Scholar)
- Wakefield, J., 2002, “Broad versus Narrow Content in the Explanation of Action: Fodor on Frege Cases”, Philosophical Psychology, 15: 119–133. (Scholar)
- Weiskopf, D., 2004, “The Place of Time in Cognition”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55: 87–105. (Scholar)
- Whitehead, A.N. and B. Russell, 1925, Principia Mathematica, vol. 1, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Wilson, R., 2005, “What Computers (Still, Still) Can’t Do”, in New Essays in Philosophy of Language and Mind, R. Stainton, M. Ezcurdia, and C.D. Viger (eds). Canadian Journal of Philosophy, supplementary issue 30: 407–425. (Scholar)
- Yablo, S., 1997, “Wide Causation”, Philosophical Perspectives, 11: 251–281. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “Causal Relevance”, Philosophical Issues, 13: 316–327. (Scholar)
- Zednik, C., 2019, “Computational Cognitive Neuroscience”, in Sprevak and Colombo 2019: 357–369. (Scholar)
- Zylberberg, A., S. Dehaene, P. Roelfsema, and M. Sigman, 2011, “The Human Turing Machine”, Trends in Cognitive Science, 15: 293–300. (Scholar)