Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Continental Rationalism" by Shannon Dea, Julie Walsh and Thomas M. Lennon
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
Primary Sources
Amo
- The Apatheia of the Human Mind, or The Absence of
Sensation and the Faculty of Sense in the Human Mind and Their Presence
in our Organic and Living Body, William Abraham (trans.), in
Antonius Gviliemus Amo, Afer of Axim, Translation of his
Works, Halle: Martin Luther University, Halle-Wittenberg,
1968.
Astell
- Astell: Political Writings, P. Springborg (ed.), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996.
- A Serious Proposal to the Ladies. Parts I and II, P.
Springborg (ed.), Ontario: Broadview Literary Texts, 2002.
- The Christian Religion, As Professed by a Daughter of the Church
of England, J. Broad (ed.), Toronto, ON: Centre for Reformation
and Renaissance Studies and Iter Publishing, 2013.
Cavendish
- Observations upon Experimental Philosophy, Eileen
O’Neill (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001. (Scholar)
Conway
- Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy, Allison
P. Coudert and Taylor Corse (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1996.
Descartes
- Oeuvres De Descartes, 11 vols., C. Adam and P. Tannery, Eds.,
Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1983.
- The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 3 vols., J.
Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch, Trans. Vol. 3 including A.
Kenny, Trans., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984–88.
- The Correspondence Between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and
René Descartes, Lisa Shapiro (ed. and trans.), Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2007.
Malebranche
- Œuvres complètes de Malebranche, 20 vols.,
A. Robinet (ed.), Paris: J. Vrin, 1958–84.
- Dialogues on Metaphysics, W. Doney, Trans., New York: Abaris
Books, 1980.
- Dialogue between a Christian Philosopher and a Chinese Philosopher
on the Existence and Nature of God, D. A. Iorio (trans.),
Washington: Catholic University Press, 1980.
- Treatise on Ethics, C. Walton (trans.), Dordrecht: Kluwer,
1993.
- Dialogues on Metaphysics and on Religion, N. Jolley and D.
Scott (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
- The Search after Truth, T. M. Lennon and P. J. Olscamp
(trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Spinoza
- Spinoza Opera, 5 volumes. C. Gebhardt (Ed.), Heidelberg:
Carl Winter, 1925–87.
- The Collected Writings of Spinoza, E. Curley (trans. and ed.),
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985. Complete Works,
S. Shirley (trans.), M. Morgan (ed.), Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002. (Scholar)
Leibniz
- Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: Sämtliche Schriften und
Briefe, German Academy of Science, Darmstadt and Berlin: Berlin
Academy, 1923–.
- Philosophical Essays, R. Ariew and D. Garber (eds. and
trans.), Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989.
- Opuscules et Fragments Inédits de
Leibniz, L. Couturat (ed.), Paris: Felix Alcan, 1903.
- Leibnizens Mathematische Schriften, C. I. Gerhardt (ed.),
Berlin: Weidman, 1875–90.
- Die Philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz,
C.I. Gerhardt (ed.), Berlin: Weidman, 1875–90. Theodicy,
A. Farrer (ed.) and E. Huggard (trans.), New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1952. (Scholar)
- Philosophical Papers and Letters, L. Loemker (ed.), 2nd
ed., Dordrecht: Reidel, 1969. Philosophical Writings, M.
Morris and G. Parkinson (eds. and trans.), London: Dent, 1973. (Scholar)
- New Essays on Human Understanding, P. Remnant and J.
Bennett (ed. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1982.
- Leibniz: Selections, P. Wiener (Ed.), New York: Charles
Scribner’s Sons, 1951.
Secondary Sources
- Abraham, William, 1964, “The Life and Times of Anton Wilhelm
Amo”, Transactions of the Historical Society of Ghana,
7: 60–81. [A biography of Amo.] (Scholar)
- Adams, Robert Merrihew, 1994, Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist, Oxford: Oxford University Press. [A careful and penetrating study that benefits from the author’s extensive of knowledge of Leibniz’s oeuvre.] (Scholar)
- Allison, Henry, 1987, Benedict de Spinoza: An Introduction,
New Haven: Yale University Press. [A classic work by an eminent
Spinoza scholar. Suitable for beginners, but also useful for those
well-versed in Spinoza.] (Scholar)
- Atherton, Margaret, 1993, “Cartesian Reason and Gendered
Reason”, A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason
and Objectivity, Eds. Louise Antony and Charlotte Witt, Boulder:
Westview Press. [Against arguments that Descartes’s conception of
rationality served to exclude women, Atherton here adduces evidence
that some early modern women philosophers regarded Cartesian reason as
egalitarian, and were encouraged by it in their work.] (Scholar)
- –––, 1996, “Lady Mary Shepherd’s Case
Against George Berkeley”, British Journal for the History of
Philosophy, 4(2): 347–366. [An analysis of Shepherd’s
objections to Hume, and the manner in which she distinguishes her view
from Berkeley’s.] (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Reading Lady Mary Shepherd”, The Harvard Review of Philosophy, 13(2):73–85. [An introduction to both Shepherd’s biography and her philosophical disputes with Dugald Stewart and John Fearn.] (Scholar)
- Bennett, Jonathan, 1984, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics,
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. [A clear, penetrating study of
Spinoza whose arguments and analogies have entered the scholarly idiom.
Essential reading for Spinozists.] (Scholar)
- Bermúdez, José Luis, 1997, “Scepticism and Science in Descartes”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57(4): 743–772. [An argument for separating the importance of scepticism for motivating Descartes’s project and our interpretation of him as a canonical rationalist.] (Scholar)
- Bolton, Martha Brandt, 201, “Causality and Causal Induction:
The Necessitarian Theory of Lady Mary Shepherd”, in Causation
and Modern Philosophy, Keith Allen and Tom Stoneham (eds.),
242–261. New York/Routledge. [A detailed look at Shepherd’s views
of cause, causal principles, and mathematical induction. The latter
topic includes some discussion of Shepherd’s dispute with Dugald
Stewart.] (Scholar)
- Bordo, Susan, 1987, The Flight to Objectivity: Essays on Cartesianism and Culture, Albany: State University of New York Press. [A classic feminist psychoanalytic study of Descartes’s Meditations. Inter alia, Bordo argues that Descartes reconceives rationality as paradigmatically masculine.] (Scholar)
- Boyle, Deborah, 2009, Descartes on Innate Ideas, London: Continuum. [A comprehensive study of Descartes’s nativism. Boyle argues that, for Descartes, we have implicit knowledge of our innate ideas, and that reflection is required to make the knowledge explicit. The volume includes a thorough survey and critique of the secondary literature on innate ideas in Descartes.] (Scholar)
- Bryson, Cynthia B, 1998, “Mary Astell: Defender of the ‘Disembodied Mind’”, Hypatia, 13(4): 40–62. [An argument in favor of Astell being the first English, woman feminist. Bryson argues that Astell’s version of Cartesian dualism allows her to reject the subordination of women, and her rejection of the possibility of “thinking matter” allows her to reject the kinds of social contracts between men and women that Locke endorsed in his political system.] (Scholar)
- Carriero, John, 1995, “On the Relationship Between Mode and
Substance in Spinoza’s Metaphysics”, Journal of the
History of Philosophy, 33(2): 245–73. [Carriero traces the
medieval Aristotelian influence of Spinoza’s substance/mode
distinction, and in so doing challenges Curley’s argument that
Spinozist modal dependence is causal dependence.] (Scholar)
- Cottingham, John, 1984, Rationalism, London: Paladin Books. [A concise, accessible survey of issues in both early modern and contemporary Rationalism.] (Scholar)
- Curley, Edwin, 1988, Behind the Geometric Method,
Princeton: Princeton University Press. [A brief, persuasive argument
for a naturalistic understanding of Spinoza’s Ethics by a
leader in the field.] (Scholar)
- Della Rocca, Michael, 1996, Representation and the Mind-Body Problem in Spinoza, Oxford: Oxford University Press. [The authoritative work on Spinoza’s theory of ideas.] (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Descartes, the Cartesian Circle, and Epistemology without God”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(1): 1–33. [An interpretation of Descartes’s system that would allow him to escape the circle objection.] (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, Spinoza, London and New York: Routledge. [An accessible introduction to Spinoza’s main doctrines, with a useful sketch of the historical context.] (Scholar)
- Detlefsen, Karen, 2006, “Atomism, Monism, and Causation in the Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish”, Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, 3: 199–240. [A discussion of the tension between Cavendish’s monism and her anti-atomism.] (Scholar)
- Donagan, Alan, 1988, Spinoza, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [A spare, compulsively readable interpretation of Spinoza’s mature work as a whole, with an emphasis on his naturalism.] (Scholar)
- Fantl, Jeremy, 2016, “Mary Shepherd on Causal Necessity”, Metaphysica, 17(1): 87–108. [An argument that Shepherd’s anti-Humeanism is actually stronger than has been heretofore appreciated.] (Scholar)
- Fraenkel, Carlos, Dario Perinetti, and Justin Smith, Eds, 2010,
The Rationalists: Between Tradition and Innovation, Dordrecht:
Springer. [Essays on varied topics by key thinkers in the field, all of
them devoted to understanding and problematizing the category of
rationalism by considering aspects of key rationalist figures in their
historical contexts.] (Scholar)
- Frankfurt, Harry, 1965, “Descartes’ Validation of
Reason”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 2:
149–56. [A seminal work dealing with the alleged circularity of
Descartes’s Meditations.] (Scholar)
- Garber, Daniel and Michael Ayers, Eds., 1998, The Cambridge
History of Seventeenth Century Philosophy, 2 vols.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [This collection provides a
comprehensive look at the relevant philosophical period, with
invaluable material about the historical and social context.] (Scholar)
- Garrett, Don, Ed., 1996, The Cambridge Companion to
Spinoza, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
[Essays on all aspects of Spinoza’s thought by top Spinoza
scholars.] (Scholar)
- Goldstone, Jack, 1998, “The Problem of the ‘Early
Modern’ World”, Journal of the Economic and Social
History of the Orient, 41(3): 249–284. [An influential
problematization of the “early modern” periodization that
in particular identifies the eurocentrism and the myth of progress on
which the periodization trades. Goldstone also explores
inconsistencies between the manner in which the boundaries of the
early modern era are drawn and usual conventions in historical
periodization.] (Scholar)
- Guéroult, Martial, 1968, Spinoza I: Dieu, Paris: Georg Olms. [Guéroult is credited with having dealt Wolfson’s subjectivist account of Spinoza’s attributes its death blow.] (Scholar)
- Hagengruber, Ruth, 2015, “Cutting Through the Veil of Ignorance: Rewriting the History of Philosophy”, The Monist, 98: 34–42. [An argument in favor of taking the philosophical writings of women through the history of philosophy as contributions of general relevance to this history.] (Scholar)
- Harth, Erica, 1991, “Cartesian Women”, Yale French Studies 80: 146–164. [A useful study of the thought of French Cartesian Women, especially those who were prominent in the philosophical salons of the seventeenth century.] (Scholar)
- Huenemann, Charles, 2008, Understanding Rationalism, Durham, UK: Acumen. [A clear and helpful introduction to Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, written for college juniors.] (Scholar)
- Ishiguro, Hidé, 1972, Leibniz’s Philosophy of Logic and
Language, Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press. [A clear,
untechnical discussion of Leibniz’s arguments considered in light of
contemporary angloamerican logic.] (Scholar)
- Jolley, Nicholas (editor), 1995, The Cambridge Companion to
Leibniz, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Essays on all
aspects of Leibniz’s thought by top Leibniz scholars.] (Scholar)
- Kenny, Anthony, 1998, “Descartes on the Will”, in John Cottingham (ed.), Descartes, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pages 132–60. First appeared in R.J. Butler (ed.), 1973, Cartesian Studies, New York: Barnes and Noble. [Articulation of the “freedom of perversity” interpretation of Descartes’s discussions with Mesland on freedom.] (Scholar)
- Kenny, Anthony (editor), 1986, Rationalism, Empiricism and
Idealism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. [A useful collection,
mostly of lectures delivered at the British Academy by leading
scholars of early modern philosophy.] (Scholar)
- Krause, Andrej, 2009, “Amo’s
Ontology”, Philosophia Africana, 12(2):
141–157. [A discussion of Amo’s general ontology and how
it informs his commitment to the insensitivity of the human
soul.] (Scholar)
- Lascano, Marcy, 2013, “Anne Conway: Bodies in the Spiritual World”, Philosophy Compass, 8(4): 327–336. [A defense of Conway’s articulation of her monism, with an emphasis on the important role for “body” in a system where the only substance is spirit.] (Scholar)
- Lennon, Thomas M., 1993, The Battle of the Gods and Giants: The Legacies of Descartes and Gassendi, 1655–1715, Princeton: Princeton University Press. [An account of the contest between the Cartesians and their principal opponents as an extension of the battle that Plato depicts in the Sophist between the materialists and the friends of the forms.] (Scholar)
- Lewis, Geneviève (Rodis), 1950,
L’individualité selon Descartes, Paris:
J.Vrin. [Discusses all the texts on both sides of the question of the
uniqueness of extended substance.]
- Lin, Martin, 2011, “Rationalism and Necessitarianism”, Noûs, 46(3): 418–448. [A discussion of Spinoza’s and Leibniz’s disagreement over whether metaphysical rationalism leads to necessitarianism.] (Scholar)
- Lloyd, Genevieve, 1993, The Man of Reason: “Male” and “Female” in Western Philosophy, 2nd Ed., London: Routledge [This influential feminist study traces the construction of reason as masculine in the history of Western philosophy. Lloyd sees Descartes’s method as a crucial move in the historical philosophical centering of masculine thought.] (Scholar)
- Loeb, Louis, 1981, From Descartes to Hume: Continental Metaphysics and the Development of Modern Philosophy, Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press. [Loeb famously challenges the rationalist-empiricist divide, arguing that important aspects of Locke’s and Berkeley’s thought are rationalist in character.] (Scholar)
- Mates, Benson, 1986, The Philosophy of Leibniz: Metaphysics & Language, Oxford: Oxford University Press. [An internalist reading of Leibniz focusing in particular on logical issues and on Leibniz’s nominalism.] (Scholar)
- McCracken, Charles J., 1983, Malebranche and British Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press. [A classic account of Malebranche’s influence on British philosophy, which also contains a wonderful 100 page account of Malebranche’s system.] (Scholar)
- Melamed, Yitzhak, 2013, “Spinoza’s Metaphysics of Thought: Parallelisms and the Multifaceted Structure of Ideas”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3): 636–683. [A reinterpretation of Spinozist parallelism that seeks to resolve why human beings can only know two of substance’s infinite attributes.] (Scholar)
- Merchant, Carolyn, 1979, “The Vitalism of Anne Conway: Its
Impact on Leibniz’s Concept of the Monad”, Journal of
the History of Philosophy, 17(3): 255–269. [A discussion of
Conway’s system, and her influence on Leibniz.] (Scholar)
- Moreau, Joseph, 1947, “Malebranche et le spinozisme”, in
Joseph Moreau (ed.), Malebranche: Correspondance avec
J.-J. Dortous de Mairan, Paris: Vrin, pages 1–99. [Moreau
provides an excellent introduction to and analysis of this
correspondence in his introduction to this edition of the
correspondence.] (Scholar)
- Nadler, Steven., Ed., 1993, Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony, University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. [A collection of essays concerning the three main rationalist theories of causation. The essays in this collection consider not only the major figures discussed in the above article, but also a number of intermediate and minor figures.] (Scholar)
- Nelson, Alan, Ed., 2005, A Companion to Rationalism, Oxford, Blackwell. [An ably edited collection of essays devoted to the historical antecedents of rationalism, to the movement’s “golden age” and to rationalist elements in contemporary thought.] (Scholar)
- Norton, David Fate, 1981, “The Myth of British Empiricism”, History of European Ideas, 1(4): 331–344. [An argument problematizing the very category of “British Empiricism.”] (Scholar)
- Okruhlik, Kathleen and James R. Brown, Eds., 1985, The Natural
Philosophy of Leibniz, Dordrecht: D. Reidel. [A challenging
collection devoted to the role of physics and natural philosophy in the
development of Leibniz’s thought.] (Scholar)
- Perry, Ruth, 1986, The Celebrated Mary Astell: An Early English Feminist, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. [An influential intellectual biography of Astell.] (Scholar)
- Peterman, Alison, 2015, “Spinoza on Extension”, Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(14): 1–23. [An argument against the interpretation that Spinoza takes extension in space to be a fundamental property of physical things.] (Scholar)
- Rozemond, Marleen, 1998, Descartes’s Dualism, Cambridge:
Harvard University Press. [A thorough account of the topic indicated,
including valuable scholastic background.] (Scholar)
- Russell, Bertrand, 1992, A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy
of Leibniz, London: Routledge. [First published in 1900, this work
includes Russell’s classic arguments that the basis of Leibniz’s
thought lies in his Aristotelian logic, and that, for Leibniz,
relational properties are merely ideal.] (Scholar)
- Schmaltz, Tad, 2002, Radical Cartesianism: The French reception of Descartes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [A treatment of those few—specifically, Desgabets and Régis—who accepted Descartes’s doctrine of created truth.] (Scholar)
- Shapiro, Lisa, 2007, “Volume Editor’s Introduction”,
in Lisa Shapiro (ed. & trans.), The Correspondence Between
Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. [The definitive analysis of this
correspondence.] (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, “Princess Elisabeth and Descartes:
The Union of Soul and Body and the Practice of
Philosophy”, British Journal for the History of
Philosophy, 7(3): 503–520. [An argument in favor of viewing
Elisabeth as a philosopher in her own right, and not merely a
correspondent of Descartes.] (Scholar)
- Sharp, Hasana, 2012, “Eve’s Perfection: Spinoza on Sexual
(In)Equality”, Journal of the History of Philosophy
50(4): 559–580. [A study of inconsistencies in Spinoza’s
account of women’s capacities.] (Scholar)
- Smith, Justin, 2015, Nature, Human Nature, & Human Difference: Race in Early Modern Philosophy, Princeton: Princeton University Press. [A useful study of the construction of race in early modernity and its interactions with the philosophical thought of the day.] (Scholar)
- Sowaal, Alice, 2004, “Cartesian Bodies”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 34(2): 217–40. [This useful article sorts Descartes’s inconsistent language about substance in terms of levels.] (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Mary Astell’s Serious Proposal: Mind, Method, and Custom”, Philosophy Compass, 2(2): 227–243. [A discussion of Astell’s theory of mind.] (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Mary Astell”, The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta
(ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/astell/>. (Scholar)
- Sutherland, Christine Mason, 2005, The Eloquence of Mary
Astell, Calgary: University of Calgary Press. [A recent study of
Astell’s importance as a rhetorician.] (Scholar)
- Tollefsen, Deborah, 1999, “Princess Elisabeth and the Problem of Mind-Body Interaction”, Hypatia, 14(3): 59–77. [A discussion of Elisabeth’s objections to Descartes’s dualism.] (Scholar)
- Wilson, Aaron, 2016, Peirce’s Empiricism: Its Roots and Its Originality, Lanham: Lexington Books. [This study of American Pragmatist Charles Sanders Peirce contains a useful chapter on the history of the rationalism-empiricism distinction.] (Scholar)
- Wilson, Margaret Dauler, 1982, Descartes, New York:
Routledge. [See Chapter Three for a clear and useful discussion of
Descartes’s doctrine of created truths.] (Scholar)
- Wiredu, Kwasi, 2004, “Amo’s Critique of Descartes’
Philosophy of Mind”, in Kwasi Wiredu (ed.), A Companion to
African Philosophy, Malden, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing,
Ltd., pages 200–206. [Introduction to Amo’s biography, and
main lines of his critique against Descartes’s theory of
mind.] (Scholar)
- Wolfson, Harry, 1934, The Philosophy of Spinoza, 2 vols., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Wolfson’s is still the classic argument for the subjectivist account of attributes in Spinoza.] (Scholar)
- Woolhouse, R.S., 1993, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz: The Concept of Substance in Seventeenth Century Metaphysics, London and New York: Routledge. [A deep account of many of the themes covered here, with something of value for readers at all levels.] (Scholar)