Linked bibliography for the SEP article "David Lewis" by Brian Weatherson
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
Primary Literature
- 1966a, “An Argument for the Identity Theory,” Journal of Philosophy, 63: 17–25. (Scholar)
- 1966b, “Percepts and Color Mosaics in Visual Experience,” Philosophical Review, 75: 357–368. (Scholar)
- 1966 (with Jane S. Richardson), “Scriven on Human
Unpredictability,” Philosophical Studies, 17:
69–74. (Scholar)
- 1968, “Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic,” Journal of Philosophy, 65: 113–126. (Scholar)
- 1968 (with Wilfrid Hodges), “Finitude and Infinitude in the
Atomic Calculus of Individuals,” Noûs, 2:
405–410. (Scholar)
- 1969a, Convention: A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
- 1969b, “Lucas against Mechanism,” Philosophy,
44: 231–233. (Scholar)
- 1969c, “Policing the Aufbau,” Philosophical
Studies, 20: 13–17. (Scholar)
- 1969d, Review of Capitan and Merrill (eds.), Art, Mind, and
Religion, Journal of Philosophy, 66: 22–27.
- 1970a, “Anselm and Actuality,” Noûs, 4: 175–188. (Scholar)
- 1970b, “General Semantics,” Synthese, 22:
18–67. (Scholar)
- 1970c, “How to Define Theoretical Terms,” Journal of Philosophy, 67: 427–446. (Scholar)
- 1970d, “Nominalistic Set Theory,” Noûs, 4: 225–240. (Scholar)
- 1970 (with Stephanie R. Lewis), “Holes,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 48: 206–212. (Scholar)
- 1971a, “Analog and Digital,” Noûs, 5: 321–327. (Scholar)
- 1971b, “Completeness and Decidability of Three Logics of
Counterfactual Conditionals,” Theoria, 37:
74–85. (Scholar)
- 1971c, “Counterparts of Persons and Their Bodies,” Journal of Philosophy, 68: 203–211. (Scholar)
- 1971d, “Immodest Inductive Methods,” Philosophy of
Science, 38: 54–63. (Scholar)
- 1972a, “Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50: 249–258. (Scholar)
- 1972b, “Utilitarianism and Truthfulness,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50: 17–19. (Scholar)
- 1973a, Counterfactuals, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers and
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1973, Reprinted with
revisions, 1986. (Scholar)
- 1973b, “Causation,” Journal of Philosophy, 70: 556–567. (Scholar)
- 1973c, “Counterfactuals and Comparative Possibility,”
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2: 418–446. (Scholar)
- 1973d, “Lingue e lingua,” Versus, 4:
2–21. (Scholar)
- 1974a, “Tensions,” in Milton K. Munitz and Peter K.
Unger (eds.), Semantics and Philosophy, New York: New York
University Press, pp. 49–61. (Scholar)
- 1974b, “Intensional Logics Without Iterative Axioms,”
Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3: 457–466. (Scholar)
- 1974c, “Radical Interpretation,” Synthese,
23: 331–344. (Scholar)
- 1974d, “Semantic Analyses for Dyadic Deontic Logic,”
in Sören Stenlund (ed.), Logical Theory and Semantic
Analysis: Essays Dedicated to Stig Kanger on His Fiftieth
Birthday, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 1–14. (Scholar)
- 1974e, “Spielman and Lewis on Inductive Immodesty,”
Philosophy of Science, 41: 84–85. (Scholar)
- 1975a, “Adverbs of Quantification,” in Edward L.
Keenan (ed.), Formal Semantics of Natural Language,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3–15. (Scholar)
- 1975b, “Languages and Language,” in Keith Gunderson
(ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume
VII, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3–35. (Scholar)
- 1975 (with Stephanie R. Lewis), Review of Olson and Paul,
Contemporary Philosophy in Scandinavia, Theoria, 41:
39–60.
- 1976a, “Convention: Reply to Jamieson,” Canadian
Journal of Philosophy, 6: 113–120. (Scholar)
- 1976b, “Probabilities of Conditionals and Conditional Probabilities,” Philosophical Review, 85: 297–315. (Scholar)
- 1976c, “Survival and Identity,” in Amélie O.
Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons, Berkeley: University
of California Press, pp. 17–40. (Scholar)
- 1976d, “The Paradoxes of Time Travel,” American
Philosophical Quarterly, 13: 145–152. (Scholar)
- 1977a, “Possible-World Semantics for Counterfactual Logics:
A Rejoinder,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 6:
359–363. (Scholar)
- 1978a, “Reply to McMichael,” Analysis, 38:
85–86. (Scholar)
- 1978b, “Truth in Fiction,” American Philosophical
Quarterly, 15: 37–46. (Scholar)
- 1979a, “A Problem about Permission,” in E. Saarinen
et al. (eds.), Essays in Honour of Jaakko Hintikka,
Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 163–175. (Scholar)
- 1979b, “Attitudes De Dicto and De
Se,” Philosophical Review, 88: 513–543. (Scholar)
- 1979c, “Counterfactual Dependence and Time’s
Arrow,” Noûs, 13: 455–476. (Scholar)
- 1979d, “Lucas Against Mechanism II,” Canadian
Journal of Philosophy, 9: 373–376. (Scholar)
- 1979e, “Prisoners’ Dilemma is a Newcomb
Problem,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 8:
235–240. (Scholar)
- 1979f, “Scorekeeping in a Language Game,” Journal
of Philosophical Logic, 8: 339–359. (Scholar)
- 1980a, “A Subjectivist’s Guide to Objective
Chance,” in Richard C. Jeffrey (ed.), Studies in Inductive
Logic and Probability, Volume II, Berkeley: University of
California Press, pp. 263–293. (Scholar)
- 1980b, “Index, Context, and Content,” in Stig Kanger
and Sven Öhman (eds.), Philosophy and Grammar,
Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 79–100. (Scholar)
- 1980c, “Mad Pain and Martian Pain,” in Ned Block
(ed.), Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Volume I,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 216–32. (Scholar)
- 1980d, “Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58: 239–249. (Scholar)
- 1981a, “Are We Free to Break the Laws?,”
Theoria, 47: 113–121. (Scholar)
- 1981b, “Causal Decision Theory,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59: 5–30. (Scholar)
- 1981c, “Ordering Semantics and Premise Semantics for
Counterfactuals,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10:
217–234. (Scholar)
- 1981d, “What Puzzling Pierre Does Not Believe,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59: 283–289. (Scholar)
- 1981e, “Why Ain’cha Rich?,” Noûs,
15: 377–380. (Scholar)
- 1982a, “‘Whether’ Report,” in Tom Pauli
(ed.), 320311: Philosophical Essays Dedicated to Lennart
Åqvist on his Fiftieth Birthday, Uppsala: University of
Uppsala Press, pp. 194–206. (Scholar)
- 1982b, “Censored Vision,” Written under the name
“Bruce LeCatt,”, Australasian Journal of
Philosophy, 60: 158–162. (Scholar)
- 1982c, “Logic for Equivocators,” Noûs, 16: 431–441. (Scholar)
- 1983a, Philosophical Papers, Volume I, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
- 1983b, “Extrinsic Properties,” Philosophical
Studies, 44: 197–200. (Scholar)
- 1983c, “Individuation by Acquaintance and by Stipulation,” Philosophical Review, 92: 3–32. (Scholar)
- 1983d, “Levi Against U-Maximization,” Journal of Philosophy, 80: 531-534. (Scholar)
- 1983e, “New Work For a Theory of Universals,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61: 343–377. (Scholar)
- 1984a, “Devil’s Bargains and the Real World,” in
Douglas MacLean (ed.), The Security Gamble: Deterrence in the
Nuclear Age, Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allenheld, pp.
141–154. (Scholar)
- 1984b, “Putnam’s Paradox,” Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, 62: 221–236. (Scholar)
- 1986a, On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers.
- 1986b, Philosophical Papers, Volume II, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
- 1986c, “A Comment on Armstrong and Forrest,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64: 92–93. (Scholar)
- 1986d, “Against Structural Universals,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64: 25–46. (Scholar)
- 1986e, “Buy Like a MADman, Use Like a NUT” QQ
6: 5–8.
- 1986f, “Causal Explanation” in Lewis 1986b, pp.
214–240. (Scholar)
- 1986g, “Events” in Lewis 1986b, pp.
241–269. (Scholar)
- 1986h, “Probabilities of Conditionals and Conditional
Probabilities II,” Philosophical Review, 95:
581–589. (Scholar)
- 1987, “The Punishment that Leaves Something to
Chance,” Proceedings of the Russellian Society,
University of Sydney, 12: 81–97. (Scholar)
- 1988a, “Ayer’s First Empiricist Criterion of Meaning:
Why Does it Fail?,” Analysis, 48: 1–3. (Scholar)
- 1988b, “Desire as Belief,” Mind, 97:
323–332. (Scholar)
- 1988c, “Rearrangement of Particles: Reply to Lowe,”
Analysis, 48: 65–72. (Scholar)
- 1988d, “Relevant Implication,” Theoria, 54:
162–174. (Scholar)
- 1988e, “Statements Partly About Observation,” Philosophical Papers, 17: 1–31. (Scholar)
- 1988f, “The Trap’s Dilemma,” Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, 66: 220–223. (Scholar)
- 1988g, “Vague identity: Evans misunderstood,”
Analysis, 48: 128–130. (Scholar)
- 1988h, “What Experience Teaches,” Proceedings of
the Russellian Society, University of Sydney, 13:
29–57. (Scholar)
- 1989a, “Academic Appointments: Why Ignore the Advantage of
Being Right?,” in Ormond Papers, Ormond College,
University of Melbourne. Reprinted in Lewis 2000a, pp.
187–200. (Scholar)
- 1989b, “Dispositional Theories of Value,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 63: 113–137. (Scholar)
- 1989c, “Finite Counterforce,” in Henry Shue (ed.),
Nuclear Deterrence and Moral Restraint, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, pp. 51–114. (Scholar)
- 1989d, “Mill and Milquetoast,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 67: 152–171. (Scholar)
- 1989e, Review of John Bigelow, The Reality of Numbers,
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 67: 487–489.
- 1990, “Noneism or Allism?,” Mind, 99:
23–31. (Scholar)
- 1991, Parts of Classes, Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers.
- 1992a, “Meaning Without Use: Reply to Hawthorne,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70: 106–110. (Scholar)
- 1992b, Critical Notice of Armstrong, A Combinatorial Theory of
Possibility, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70:
211–224.
- 1993a, “Counterpart Theory, Quantified Modal Logic, and
Extra Argument Places,” Analysis, 53: 69–71. (Scholar)
- 1993b, “Evil for Freedom’s Sake?,”
Philosophical Papers, 22: 149–172. (Scholar)
- 1993c, “Many, But Almost One,” in Keith Campbell, John
Bacon, and Lloyd Reinhardt (eds.), Ontology, Causality and Mind:
Essays on the Philosophy of D. M. Armstrong, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, pp. 23–38. (Scholar)
- 1993d, “Mathematics is Megethology,” Philosophia
Mathematica, 3: 3–23. (Scholar)
- 1994a, “Humean Supervenience Debugged,” Mind,
103: 473–490. (Scholar)
- 1994b, “Reduction of Mind,” in Samuel Guttenplan
(ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers, pp. 412–431. (Scholar)
- 1995a, “Ern Malley’s Namesake,”
Quadrant, 39: 14–15. (Scholar)
- 1995b, “Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia?,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 73: 140–144. (Scholar)
- 1996a, “Desire as Belief II,” Mind, 105:
303–313. (Scholar)
- 1996b, “Elusive Knowledge,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74: 549–567. (Scholar)
- 1996c, “Maudlin and Modal Mystery,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74: 683–684. (Scholar)
- 1996d, “Illusory Innocence?” review of Peter Unger,
Living High and Letting Die, Eureka Street, 6, No.
10 December 1996: 35–36. (Scholar)
- 1996 (with Stephanie R. Lewis), Review of R. Casati and A. Varzi,
Holes, Philosophical Review, 105: 77–79.
- 1997a, “Do We Believe in Penal Substitution?,” Philosophical Papers, 26: 203–209. (Scholar)
- 1997b, “Finkish Dispositions,” Philosophical
Quarterly, 47: 143–58. (Scholar)
- 1998a, Papers in Philosophical Logic, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
- 1997c, “Naming the Colours,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75: 325–342. (Scholar)
- 1998b, “A World of Truthmakers?” review of D. M.
Armstrong, A World of States of Affairs, published under an
incorrect title in Times Literary Supplement, 4950, 13
February 1998: 30. (Scholar)
- 1998 (with Rae Langton), “Defining
‘Intrinsic’,” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 58: 333–345. (Scholar)
- 1999a, Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
- 1999b, “Why Conditionalize?,” Written in 1972 as a
course handout, but not published until 1999 in Lewis 1999a.
- 1999c, “Zimmerman and the Spinning Sphere,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 77: 209–212. (Scholar)
- 2000a, Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
- 2000b, “Causation as Influence” abridged version,
Journal of Philosophy, 97: 182–197. (Scholar)
- 2001a, “Forget About the ‘Correspondence Theory of
Truth’,” Analysis, 61: 275–280. (Scholar)
- 2001b, “Redefining ‘Intrinsic’,”
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63:
381–398. (Scholar)
- 2001c, “Sleeping Beauty: Reply to Elga,”
Analysis, 61: 171–176. (Scholar)
- 2001d, “Truthmaking and Difference-Making,” Noûs, 35: 602-615. (Scholar)
- 2001 (with Rae Langton), “Marshall and Parsons on
‘Intrinsic’” Rae Langton, co-author, Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research, 63: 353–355. (Scholar)
- 2002a, “Tensing the Copula,” Mind, 111:
1–14. (Scholar)
- 2002b, “Tharp’s Third Theorem,”
Analysis, 62: 95–97. (Scholar)
- 2003a, “Rights to Rights,” Theoria, 69:
160–165. (Scholar)
- 2003b, “Things qua Truthmakers,” in Hallvard
Lillehammer and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra (eds.), Real
Metaphysics: Essays in Honour of D. H. Mellor, London: Routledge,
pp. 25–38. (Scholar)
- 2003 (with Gideon Rosen), “Postscript to ‘Things qua
Truthmakers’: Negative Existentials,”, in Hallvard
Lillehammer and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra (eds.), Real
Metaphysics: Essays in Honour of D. H. Mellor, London: Routledge,
pp. 39–42. (Scholar)
- 2004a, “Causation as Influence” unabridged version, in
John Collins, Ned Hall, and L.A. Paul (eds.), Causation and
Counterfactuals, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 75–106. (Scholar)
- 2004b, “How Many Lives has Schrödinger’s
Cat?,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82:
3–22. (Scholar)
- 2004c, “Tensed Quantifiers,” in Dean Zimmerman (ed.),
Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 1, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 3–14. (Scholar)
- 2004d, “Void and Object,” in John Collins, Ned Hall,
and L.A. Paul (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 277–290. (Scholar)
- 2004e, “Letters to Priest and Beall,” in Graham
Priest, J. C. Beall and Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of
Non-Contradiction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp.
176–177. (Scholar)
- 2005, “Quasi-Realism is Fictionalism” in Mark Calderon
(ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press,
pp. 314–321. (Scholar)
- 2007, “Divine Evil” in Louise Anthony (ed.),
Philosophers Without Gods, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
pp. 231–242. (Scholar)
- 2009, “Ramseyan Humility” in David Braddon-Mitchell
and Robert Nola (eds.), Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical
Naturalism, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 203–222. (Scholar)
- 2015a, “Counterparts of States of Affairs” in Barry
Loewer and Jonathan Schaffer (eds.), A Companion to David
Lewis, New York: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 15-17. (Scholar)
- 2015b, “Reply to Dana Scott, “Is There Life on Other
Possible Worlds”” in Barry Loewer and Jonathan Schaffer
(eds.), A Companion to David Lewis, New York: Wiley
Blackwell, pp. 18-21. (Scholar)
- 2020a, Philosophical Letters of David K. Lewis, volume 1:
Causation, Modality, Ontology, edited by Helen Beebee and A. R.
J. Fisher, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- 2020b, Philosophical Letters of David K. Lewis, volume 2:
Mind, Language, Epistemology, edited by Helen Beebee and A. R. J.
Fisher, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cited Secondary Literature
- Adams, Robert, 1974, “Theories of Actuality” Noûs, 8: 211–231. (Scholar)
- Armstrong, D. M., 1978, Universals and Scientific Realism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Bennett, Jonathan, 1984, “Counterfactuals and Temporal Direction” Philosophical Review, 93: 57–91. (Scholar)
- Bennett, Jonathan, 2003, A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Braddon-Mitchell, David and Robert Nola, 1997,
“Ramsification and Glymour’s Counterexample”
Analysis, 57: 167–169. (Scholar)
- Cohen, Stewart, 1986, “Knowledge and Context”, The Journal of Philosophy, 83: 574–583. (Scholar)
- Davies, Martin, 1981, Meaning, Quantification, Necessity: Themes in Philosophical Logic, London: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Elga, Adam, 2000, “Self-Locating Belief and the Sleeping Beauty Problem,” Analysis 60: 143–147. (Scholar)
- DeRose, Keith, 1995, “Solving the Skeptical Problem”, The Philosophical Review, 104(1), 1–52. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, “Defeating Dr. Evil with
Self-Locating Belief,” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 69: 383–396. (Scholar)
- Egan, Andy, 2007, “Epistemic modals, relativism and assertion,” Philosophical Studies, 133: 1–22. (Scholar)
- Fine, Kit, 1975, “Critical Notice of
Counterfactuals,” Mind, 84:
451–458. (Scholar)
- Forrest, Peter, 1982, “Occam’s Razor and Possible
Worlds” Monist, 65: 456–464. (Scholar)
- ––– and D. M. Armstrong, 1984, “An
Argument Against David Lewis’ Theory of Possible Worlds,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62: 164–8. (Scholar)
- Frankfurt, Harry, 1971, “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,” Journal of Philosophy, 68: 5–20. (Scholar)
- Goodman, Nelson, 1955, Fact, Fiction and Forecast, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Hall, Ned, 1994, “Correcting the Guide to Objective Chance”, Mind 103: 505–518. (Scholar)
- Hawthorne, John, 1990, “A Note on Languages and Language,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68: 116–118. (Scholar)
- Hájek, Alan, 2008, “David Lewis,” in The
New Dictionary of Scientific Biography, ed. Noretta Koertke, New
York: Scribners. (Scholar)
- Jackson, Frank, 1998, From Metaphysics to Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Janssen-Lauret, Frederique and Fraser MacBride, 2020,
“Lewis’s Global Descriptivism and Reference
Magnetism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 98:
192–198. (Scholar)
- Keller, Simon, 2015, “David Lewis’s Social and
Political Philosophy”, in Barry Loewer and Jonathan Schaffer
(eds.), A Companion to David Lewis, New York: Wiley
Blackwell, pp. 549-561. (Scholar)
- Kim, Jaegwon, 1973, “Causes and Counterfactuals,” Journal of Philosophy, 70: 570–572. (Scholar)
- Kripke, Saul, 1982, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Lewis, Stephanie, 2015, “Intellectual Biography of David
Lewis (1941-2001): Early Influences”, in Barry Loewer and
Jonathan Schaffer (eds.), A Companion to David Lewis, New
York: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 1-14. (Scholar)
- Melia, Joseph, 1992, “A Note on Lewis’s
Ontology”, Analysis, 52: 191–192. (Scholar)
- Melia, Joseph and Juha Saatsi, 2006, “ Ramseyfication and Theoretical Content”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57: 561–585. (Scholar)
- Nolan, Daniel, 2005, David Lewis, Chesham: Acumen Publishing. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Selfless Desires”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73: 665–679. (Scholar)
- Paul, L. A., 2000, “Aspect Causation,” Journal of Philosophy, 97: 235–256. (Scholar)
- Plantinga, Alvin, 1974, The Nature of Necessity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Putnam, Hillary, 1981, Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Quine, Willard van Orman, 1960, Word and Object, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Schaffer, Jonathan, “Trumping Preemption,” Journal of Philosophy, 97: 165–181. (Scholar)
- Schelling, Thomas, 1960, The Strategy of Conflict, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Schwarz, Wolfgang, 2009, David Lewis: Metaphysik und Analyse, Paderborn: Mentis-Verlag. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Against Magnetism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92: 17–36. (Scholar)
- Skyrms, Brian, 1987, “Dynamic Coherence and Probability Kinematics,” Philosophy of Science, 54: 1–20. (Scholar)
- Sider, Theodore, 2001, “Criteria of Personal Identity and the Limits of Conceptual Analysis,” Philosophical Perspectives, 15: 279–315. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “The Ersatz Pluriverse,” Journal of Philosophy, 99: 279–315. (Scholar)
- Smart, J. J. C., 1959 “Sensations and Brain Processes,” Philosophical Review, 68: 141–156. (Scholar)
- Sorensen, Roy, 2009, “Epistemic Paradoxes,” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition), Edward
N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/epistemic-paradoxes/>. (Scholar)
- Stalnaker, Robert, 1968, “A Theory of Conditionals, ” in Nicholas Rescher (ed.), Studies in Logical Theory (American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series: Volume 2), Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 98–112. (Scholar)
- –––, 1976, “Possible Worlds” Noûs, 10: 65–75. (Scholar)
- –––, 1984, Inquiry, Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, Our Knowledge of the Internal World, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Teller, Paul, 1976, “Conditionalization, observation, and
change of preference” in: W. L. Harper and C. A. Hooker (eds.),
Foundations of Probability Theory, Statistical Inference, and
Statistical Theories of Science, vol. 1. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp.
205–253. (Scholar)
- Thau, Michael, 1994, “Undermining and Admissibility”, Mind, 103: 491–504. (Scholar)
- Weatherson, Brian, 2003, “What Good are Counterexamples?” Philosophical Studies, 115: 1–31. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “The Role of Naturalness in
Lewis’s Theory of Meaning” Journal for the History of
Analytical Philosophy, 1(10)
[available online]. (Scholar)
- Williams, J. Robert G., 2007, “Eligibility and Inscrutability,” Philosophical Review, 116: 361–399. (Scholar)
- Wilson, Alastair, forthcoming, “Plenitude and Recombination,” in Helen Beebee and Anthony Fisher (eds.), David Lewis: A Historical Perspective, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1953, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)