Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Disability: Health, Well-Being, and Personal Relationships" by David Wasserman, Adrienne Asch, Jeffrey Blustein and Daniel Putnam

This is an automatically generated and experimental page

If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.

This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.

  • ADAPT (American Disabled for Attendant Programs Today), “A Disability Perspective on Home Health Care”, available online, Albertson, NY: National Center on Employment of the Handicapped, Human Resources Center, accessed August 22, 2014. (Scholar)
  • Albrecht, G.L. and G. Devlieger, 1999, “The disability paradox: high quality of life against the odds”, Social Science and Medicine, pp. 977–988. (Scholar)
  • Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA), 1990, United States. [ADA available online] (Scholar)
  • Amundson, R., 1992, “Disability, Handicap, and the Environment”, Journal of Social Philosophy, 23(1) 105–19. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2000, “Against Normal Function”, Studies in History, Philosophy, Biology and Biomedical Science, 31(1): 33–53. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, “Disability, Ideology, and Quality of Life: A Bias in Biomedical Ethics”, in Wasserman, Wachbroit, and Bickenbach 2005b: 101–124. (Scholar)
  • Anderson, Elizabeth, 2010, The Imperative of Integration, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
  • Asch, A., 1993, “Abused or neglected clients—or abusive or neglectful service systems?” Ethical Conflicts in the Management of Home Care, R.A. Kane & A.L. Caplan (eds.), New York: Springer Publishing Company, 113–21. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “Disability, Equality and Prenatal Testing: Contradictory or Compatible?”, Florida State University Law Review, 30(2): 315–342. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, “Recognizing Death while Affirming Life: Can End of Life Reform Uphold a Disabled Person’s Interest in Continued Life?” The Hastings Center Report, 35(7): s31-s36. (Scholar)
  • Asch, A. and M. Fine, 1988, “Introduction: Beyond Pedestals”, in Fine and Asch 1988: 1-40. (Scholar)
  • Asch, A. and D. Wasserman, 2005, “Where Is the Sin in Synecdoche: Prenatal Testing and the Parent-Child Relationship”, in Wasserman, Wachbroit, and Bickenbach 2005b: 172–216. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2010, “Making Embryos Healthy or Making Healthy Embryos: How much of a Difference between Prenatal Treatment and Selection?” in The “Health” Embryo: Social, Biomedical, Legal and Philosophical Perspectives, J. Nisker, F. Baylis, I. Karpin, C. McLeod, and R. Mykitiuk (eds), New York: NY: Cambridge University Press, 201–219. (Scholar)
  • Aschbrenner, K.A., J.S. Greenberg, S.M. Allen, M.M. Seltzer, 2010, “Subjective burden and personal gains among older parents of adults with serious mental illness”, Psychiatric Services, 61(6): 605–611. (Scholar)
  • Barnes, E., 2009a, “Disability, Minority, and Difference”, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 26(4): 337–355. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009b, “Disability and adaptive preference”, Philosophical Perspectives, 23:1, pp 1–22. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2014, “Valuing Disability, Causing Disability”, Ethics, 125(1): 88–113. (Scholar)
  • Becker, L.C., 1998, “Afterword: Disability, Strategic Action, and Reciprocity”, in Silvers, Wasserman, and Mahowald 1998: 293–303. (Scholar)
  • Becker, L., 2000, “The Good of Agency”, in Americans with Disabilities: Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions, L. Frances and A. Silvers (eds.), New York: Routledge: 54–63. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, “Reciprocity, Justice, and Disability”, Ethics, 116(1): 9–39. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2012, Habilitation, Health, and Agency: A Framework for Basic Justice, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Bickenbach, J., 1993, Physical Disability and Social Policy, Toronto and London: University of Toronto Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, “Disability and Health Systems Assessment”, in Wasserman, Wachbroit, and Bickenbach 2005b: 237–66. (Scholar)
  • Blacher, J. and B.L. Baker, 2007, “Positive impact of intellectual disability on families”, American Journal on Mental Retardation, 112(5): 330–348. (Scholar)
  • Blustein, J., 1982, Parents and Children: The Ethics of the Family, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Bodenheimer, T., 1997, “The Oregon health plan: lessons for the nation”, New England Journal of Medicine, 337(10): 720–3. (Scholar)
  • Boorse, C., 1987, “Concepts of Health”, in Health Care Ethics: An Introduction, D. VanDeveer and T. Regan (eds.), Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 359–393. (Scholar)
  • Botkin, J.R. 1995, “Fetal Privacy and Confidentiality”, The Hastings Center Report, 25: 32–39. (Scholar)
  • Bradley, B., 2012, “Doing away with Harm”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(2): 390–412. (Scholar)
  • Brickman, P. and D. Campbell, 1971, “Hedonic relativism and planning the good society”, in Adaptation-level theory: a symposium, M.H. Apley (ed.), New York: Academic Press, pp. 287–305. (Scholar)
  • Brightman, A.J., 1985, Ordinary Moments: The Disabled Experience, Baltimore: Human Policy Press. (Scholar)
  • Brock, D.W., 1995, “Justice and the ADA: does prioritizing and rationing health care discriminate against the disabled?”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 12(2): 159–185. (Scholar)
  • Brock, Dan, 2005, “Preventing Genetically Transmitted Disabilities while Pespecting Persons with Disabilities”, in Wasserman, Wachbroit, and Bickenbach 2005b: 67–100. (Scholar)
  • Callahan, D., 1988, “Families as Caregivers: The Limits of Morality”, Archives of Physical Medicine and Rehabilitation, 69(5) 323–8. (Scholar)
  • Campbell, S.M., 2014, “When the Shape of a Life Matters”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18(3): 565–575. (Scholar)
  • Carel, H., 2007, “Can I Be Ill and Happy?Philosophia, 35: 95–110 (Scholar)
  • Chappell, A.L., 1994, “A question of friendship: community care and the relationship of people with learning difficulties”, Disability and Society, 9(4): 419–434.
  • Cohen, S., B. Gottlieb, and L. Underwood, 2001, “Social Relationships and Health: Challenges for Measurement and Intervention”, Advances in Mind-Body Medicine, 17(2): 129ff. (Scholar)
  • Cohen, S. and T. Wills, 1985, “Stress, Social Support and the Buffering Hypothesis”, Psychological Bulletin, 98(2): 310–357. (Scholar)
  • Coombs, R., 1991, “Marital Status and Personal Well-Being: A Literature Review”, Family Relations, 40(1): 97–102. (Scholar)
  • Coleman, C.H., 2002, “Conceiving Harm: Disability Discrimination in Assisted Reproductive Technologies”, UCLA Law Review, 50: 17. (Scholar)
  • Collings, S., and G. Llewellyn, 2012, “Children of Parents with Intellectual Disability: Facing Poor Outcomes or Faring Okay?”, Journal of Intellectual and Developmental Disability, 37(1): 65–82. (Scholar)
  • Crisp, R., 2013, “Well-Being”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <Well-Being/" target="other">https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/Well-Being/>. (Scholar)
  • Crocker, D., 1995, “Functioning and Capability: The Foundations of Sen’s and Nussbaum’s Development Ethics: Part II”, in Women, Culture, and Development, Martha Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover (eds), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 153–98. (Scholar)
  • Crocker, D.A., 2013, “Review of Habilitation, Health, and Agency: A Framework for Basic Justice by Lawrence C. Becker”, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 2013.02.28. [Crocker 2013 available online] (Scholar)
  • Daniels, N., 1985, Just Health Care, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • Davis, F., 1961, “Deviance Disavowel: The Management of Strained Interaction by the Visibly Handicapped”, Social Problems, 9(2): 120–132. (Scholar)
  • DeVito, S., 2000, “On the Value-Neutrality of the Concepts of Health and Disease: Unto the Breach Again”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25: 538–67 (Scholar)
  • Disability Discrimination Act (DDA), 1995, United Kingdom. [DDA 1995 available online] (Scholar)
  • Dougherty, Tom, 2014, “Ethics Discussion at PEA Soup: Elizabeth Barnes’ Valuing Disability, Causing Disability, with Critical Précis by Tom Dougherty”, PEA Soup: A blog dedicated to philosophy, ethics, and academia, November 25, 2014. [Dougherty 2014 online] (Scholar)
  • Emens, E.F., 2009, “Intimate Discrimination: The State’s Role in the Accidents of Sex and Love”, Harvard Law Review, 122: 1307–1402. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2012, “Framing Disability”, University of Illinois Law Review, 5: 1383–1441. (Scholar)
  • Engelhardt, H.T. Jr., 1986, The Foundations of Bioethics, New York, Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • English, J., 1979, “What Do Grown Children Owe Their Parents?” in Having Children: Philosophical and Legal Reflections on Parenthood, O. O’Neill and W. Ruddick (eds), New York: Oxford University Press: 351–356. (Scholar)
  • Feinberg, J., 1986, “Wrongful life and the counterfactual element in harming”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 4(1): 145–178. (Scholar)
  • Feldman, F., 2008, “Whole life satisfaction concepts of happiness”, Theoria, 74(3): 219–238. (Scholar)
  • Ferguson, P.M., 2001, “Mapping the Family: Disability Studies and the Exploration of Parental Response to Disability”, in Handbook of Disability Studies, Gary L. Albrecht, Katherine D. Seelman, and Michael Bury (eds.), Thousand Oaks, California: Sage Publications, 373–95. (Scholar)
  • Fine, M. and A. Asch (eds.) 1988, Women with Disabilities: Essays in Psychology, Culture, and Politics, Philadelphia: Temple University Press. (Scholar)
  • Fisher B. and R. Galler, 1988, “Friendship and fairness: How disability affects friendship between women”, in Fine and Asch 1988: 172–194. (Scholar)
  • Francis, L.P., 2009, “Understanding Autonomy in Light of Intellectual Disability”, in Disability and Disadvantage, K. Brownlee and A. Cureton (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: 200–215 (Scholar)
  • Gerstein, E.D., K. Crnic, J. Blacher, and B.L. Baker, 2009, “Resilience and the course of daily parenting stress in families of young children with intellectual disabilities”, Journal of Intellectual Disability Research, 53(12): 981–997. (Scholar)
  • Gill, Carol J., 1992, “Suicide Intervention for People with Disabilities: A Lesson in Inequality”, Issues in Law & Medicine, 8(1): 37–54. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2000, “Health Professionals, Disability, and Assisted Suicide: An Examination of Empirical Evidence”, Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 6(2) 526–45. (Scholar)
  • Gliedman, J. and W. Roth, 1980, The Unexpected Minority: Handicapped Children in America, New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. (Scholar)
  • Glover, J., 2006, Choosing Children: The Ethical Dilemmas of Genetic Intervention, Oxford: Clarendon Press, Ch. 3. (Scholar)
  • Goering, S., 2008, “’You say you’re happy, but …’: Contested Quality of Life Judgments in Bioethics and Disability Studies”, Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, 5: 125–135. (Scholar)
  • Goode, D.A. (ed.), 1994, Quality of Life for Persons with Disabilities: International Perspectives and Issues, Brookline, MA: Brookline Books. (Scholar)
  • Green, R., 2008, Babies by Design: The Ethics of Genetic Choice, New Haven: Yale University Press. (Scholar)
  • Hardwig, J., 2000, Is There A Duty to Die?, New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
  • Hare, C., 2007, “Voices from Another World: Must We Respect the Interests of People Who Do Not, and Will Never, Exist?Ethics, 117(3): 498–523. (Scholar)
  • Harman, E., 2009, “Harming as Causing Harm”, in Roberts and Wasserman 2009: 137–154. (Scholar)
  • Harris, John, 1987, “QALYfying the Value of Life”, Journal of Medical Ethics, 23:227–23. (Scholar)
  • Hausman, D., 2001, “Valuing Health”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 34(3) 246–79 (Scholar)
  • Heyd, D., 2009, “The Intractability of the Nonidentity Problem”, in Roberts and Wasserman 2009: 3–25. (Scholar)
  • Hofman, B., 2005, “Simplified Models of the Relationship between Health and Disease”, Theoretical Medicine and Biology, 26: 355–377. (Scholar)
  • Kaeser, F., 1992, “Can People with Severe Mental Retardation Consent to Mutual Sex?” Sexuality and Disability, 10(1): 33–42. (Scholar)
  • Kahane, G.; Savulescu, J., 2009, “The Welfarist Account of Disability”, in Disability and Disadvantage, K. Brownlee and A. Cureton (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: 14–53. (Scholar)
  • Kittay, E.F., 1999, Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency, New York and London: Routledge. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2003, “When Caring Is Just and Justice Is Caring: Justice and Mental Retardation”, in The Subject of Care: Feminist Perspectives on Dependency, E.F. Kittay and E.K. Feder (eds), Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 257–276. (Scholar)
  • Kristjansson, K., 2006, “Parents and Children as Friends”, Journal of Social Philosophy, 37(2): 250–265. (Scholar)
  • LaFollette, H. 1996, Personal Relationships: Love, Identity, and Morality, Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Press. (Scholar)
  • Levine, C., 2004, Always on Call: When Illness Turns Families into Caregivers, Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press. (Scholar)
  • Lindemann, H. and J.L. Nelson, 2008, “The Romance of the Family”, The Hastings Center Report, 38(4): 19–21. (Scholar)
  • Litvak, S., Heumann, J. and Zukas, H.,1987, Attending to America: Personal Assistance for Independent Living, Berkeley: World Institute on Disability. (Scholar)
  • Longmore, P.K. 1987,“Elizabeth Bouvia, Assisted Suicide and Social Prejudice”, Issues in Law & Medicine, 3(2): 141–170. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1995, “The Second Phase: From Disability Rights to Disability Culture”, Disability Rag, 16(Sept/Oct): 4–11. (Scholar)
  • Malek, J. 2008, “Disability and the Duties of Potential Parents”, St. Louis University Journal of Health, Law and Policy, 2: 119–134. (Scholar)
  • McBryde-Johnson, H., 2003, “Unspeakable Conversations”, New York Times (Magazine section), February 16. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, Too Late to Die Young: Nearly True Tales from a Life, New York, Henry Holt & Co. (Scholar)
  • McClimans, L., J. Bickenbach, M. Westerman, L. Carlson, D. Wasserman, and C. Schwartz, 2013, “Philosophical perspectives on response shift”, Quality of Life Research, 22(7): 1871–1878. (Scholar)
  • McMahan, J., 2001, The ethics of killing: Problems at the margins of life, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2005, “Causing Disabled People to Exist and Causing People to be Disabled”, Ethics, 116(1): 77–99. (Scholar)
  • Menzel, P., P. Dolan, J. Richardson, and J.A. Olsen, 2002, “The Role of Adaptation to Disability and Disease in Health State Aaluation: a Preliminary Normative Analysis”, Social Science & Medicine, 55(12): 2149–2158. (Scholar)
  • Murray, C., 1996, “Rethinking DALYs”, in The Global Burden of Disease: A Comprehensive Assessment of Mortality and Disability From Diseases, Injuries, and Risk Factors In 1990 and Projected to 2020, C. Murray, and A. Lopez (eds.), Geneva: World Health Organization. (Scholar)
  • Mutcherson, K., 2008, “Making Mommies: Law, Pre-Implantation Genetic Diagnosis, and the Complications of Pre-Motherhood”, Columbia Journal of Gender and Law, 18: 313. (Scholar)
  • Nelson, J.L. and J. Frader, 2004, “Brain Trauma and Surrogate Decision Making: Dogmas, Challenges, and Response”, Journal of Clinical Ethics, 15(4): 264 (Scholar)
  • Nordenfelt, L., 1995, On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Perspective, 2nd ed., Dordecht: Kluwer. (Scholar)
  • Nussbaum, M., 1998, “Aristotelian Social Democracy”, in G. Brock (ed.), Necessary Goods: Our Responsibilities to Meet Others’ Needs, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 135–156. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2006, Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2009, “The Capabilities of People with Cognitive Disabilities”, Metaphilosophy, 40(3/4): 331–351. (Scholar)
  • O’Neill, O., 2002, Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics, New York: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • Overall, C., 2003, Aging, Death, and Human Longevity, Berkeley, CA: Norton & Company. (Scholar)
  • Parfit, D., 1984, Reasons and Person, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 493–502. (Scholar)
  • Picciuto, E., 2015, March 16, “Mom With Disabilities and Daughter Reunited After Two-Year Court Battle”, The Daily Beast. [Picciuto 2015 available online] (Scholar)
  • Ratzka, A.D., 2004, “Model National Personal Assistance Policy”, A project of the European Center for Excellence in Personal Assistance (ECEPA). [Ratzka 2004 available online] (Scholar)
  • Roberts, M.A. and D.T. Wasserman (eds), 2009, Harming Future Persons: Ethics, Genetics and the Nonidentity Problem, Netherlands: Springer. (Scholar)
  • Robertson, J.A., 2004, “Procreative Liberty and Harm to Offspring in Assisted Reproduction”, American Journal of Law & Medicine, 30(1): 7–40. (Scholar)
  • Ruddick, W., 1998, “Parenthood: Three Concepts and a Principle”, in Morals, Marriage, and Parenthood: An Introduction to Family Vales, L.D. Houlgate (ed.), Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2000, “Ways to Limit Prenatal Testing”, in Prenatal Testing and Disability Rights, E. Parens and A. Asch (eds.), Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press: 95–107. (Scholar)
  • Saigal, Saroj and P. Rosenbaum, 1996, “Health Related Quality of Life Considerations in the Outcome of High-Risk Babies”, Seminars in Fetal and Neonatol Medicine, 1(4): 305–312. doi:10.1016/s1084-2756(96)80050-9 (Scholar)
  • Salomon, J.A. and C. Murray, 2002 “Estimating Health State Valuations Using a Multiple-Method Protocol”, Summary Measures of Population Health: Concepts, Ethics, Measurement and Applications, Geneva: World Health Organization. (Scholar)
  • Scanlon, T.M., 1998, What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press, 109ff. (Scholar)
  • Scheffler, Samuel, 2014, “The Practice of Equality”, Social Equality: Essays on What it Means to be Equals, Carina Fourie, Fabian Schuppert, and Ivo Wallimann-Helmer (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Scotch, R.K. and K. Schriner, 1997, “Disability as Human Variation: Implications for Policy”,The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 549(1): 148–159. (Scholar)
  • Segal, J.M., 1998, “Living at a High Economics Standard: A Functionings Analysis”, in Ethics of Consumption: The Good Life Justice, and Global Stewardship, David Crocker and Toby Linden (eds), Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 342–365. (Scholar)
  • Sen, A., 1980, “Equality of What?” in S. MacMurrin (ed.) Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • Shakespeare, T., 1996, The Sexual Politics of Disability, London, UK: Cassell. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2006, Disability Rights and Wrongs, London: Routledge. (Scholar)
  • Shiffrin, S., 1999, “Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm”, Legal Theory, 5: 117–148. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2012, “Harm and Its Moral Significance”, Legal Theory, 1(1): 1–42. (Scholar)
  • Silvers, A. and L.P. Francis, 2009, “Thinking About the Good: Reconfiguring Liberal Metaphysics (or Not) for People with Cognitive Disabilities”, Metaphilosophy, 40(3–4): 475–498. (Scholar)
  • –––, “Cloudy crystal balls do not ‘gray’ babies make”, American Journal of Biothics, 11(2): 36–38. (Scholar)
  • Silvers, Anita, D. Wasserman, and M.B. Mahowald (eds.), 1998, Disability, Difference, Discrimination: Perspectives on Justice in Bioethics and Public Policy, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. (Scholar)
  • Stack, M.F., 1987, “Who Should Pay for Infertility?” The Hastings Center Report, 17(6): 3–4. (Scholar)
  • Temkin, L.S., 2008, “Is Living Longer Living Better?Journal of Applied Philosophy, 25(3): 193–210. (Scholar)
  • Urchino, B., J. Cacioppo, and J. Kiecolt-Glaser, 1996, “The Relationship Between Social Support and Psychological Processes: A Review with Emphasis on Underlying Mechanisms and Implications for Health”, Psychological Bulletin, 119(3): 488–531. (Scholar)
  • Velleman, J.D., 2008, “Persons in Prospect”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 36(3): 221–288. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1991, “Well-Being and Time”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 72: 48–77 (Scholar)
  • Venkatapuram, S., 1998, Health Justice: An argument from the capabilities approach, Cambridge: Polity Press. (Scholar)
  • Wachbroit, R., 1998, “Health and Disease, Concepts of”, Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics vol. 2, Ruth Chadwick, Daniel Callahan, and Peter Singer (eds), Waltham, MA: Academic Press, pp. 533–538. (Scholar)
  • Wasserman, D., 1998, “Distributive Justice”, in Silvers, Wasserman, and Mahowald 1998: 147-207. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2008, “Hare on De Dicto Betterness and Prospective Parents*”, Ethics, 118(3): 529–535. (Scholar)
  • Wasserman, D., R. Wachbroit, and J. Bickenbach, 2005a, “Introduction”, in Wasserman, Wachbroit, and Bickenbach 2005b: 1–26. (Scholar)
  • ––– (eds), 2005b, Quality of Life and Human Difference: Genetic Testing, Health Care, and Disability, New York: Cambridge University Press, (Scholar)
  • Wasserman, David and Jeff McMahan, 2012, “Cognitive Surrogacy, Assisted Participation, and Moral Status”, Medicine and Social Justice: Essays on the Distribution of Health Care, New York: Oxford University Press, 325–333. (Scholar)
  • Wendell, S., 1989, “Toward A Feminist Theory of Disability”, Hypatia, 4(2): 63–81. (Scholar)
  • –––, 1996, The Rejected Body: Feminist Philosophical Reflections on Disability, Hove, East Sussex, UK: Psychology Press. (Scholar)
  • –––, 2001, “Unhealthy disabled: Treating chronic illnesses as disabilities”, Hypatia, 16(4): 17–33. (Scholar)
  • Wertz, D., 1998, “What’s Missing from Genetic Counseling: A Survey of 476 Counseling Sessions”, abstract, Journal of Genetic Counseling, 7(6): 499–500. (Scholar)
  • Wertz, D.C. and J.C. Fletcher, 1993, “A Critique of Some Feminist Challenges to Prenatal Diagnosis”, Journal of Women’s Health, 2(2): 173–188 (Scholar)
  • Wilkinson, D., 2011, “A Life Worth Giving? The Threshold for Permissible Withdrawal of Life Support from Disabled Newborn Infants”, The American Journal of Bioethics, 11(2): 20–32. (Scholar)
  • Williams, B., 1973, “The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality”, Problems of the Self, Cambridge University Press: 82–100. (Scholar)
  • World Health Organization [WHO], 1948, “WHO Definition of Health”, in Preamble to the Constitution of the World Health Organization, as adopted by the International Health Conference, New York, 19–22 June, 1946; signed on 22 July 1946 by the representatives of 61 states (Official Records of the World Health Organization, no. 2, p. 100), and entered into force on 7 April 1948. [WHO 1948 available online] (Scholar)

Generated Sun Aug 14 05:51:19 2022