Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Biological Information" by Marc Artiga
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Alexander, J. McKenzie, 2002 [2021], “Evolutionary Game
Theory”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Summer 2021), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/game-evolutionary/>. (Scholar)
- Allen, Colin and Marc Hauser, 1993, “Communication and Cognition: Is Information the Connection?”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1992(2): 80–91. (Scholar)
- Andrews, Kristin and Jacob Beck (eds), 2018, The
Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal Minds (Routledge
Handbooks in Philosophy), Abingdon/New York: Routledge.
doi:10.4324/9781315742250
- Artiga, Marc, 2014, “Signaling without Cooperation”, Biology & Philosophy, 29(3): 357–378. doi:10.1007/s10539-014-9436-0 (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “Teleosemantic Modeling of Cognitive Representations”, Biology & Philosophy, 31(4): 483–505. doi:10.1007/s10539-016-9525-3 (Scholar)
- –––, 2021, “Signals Are Minimal Causes”, Synthese, 198(9): 8581–8599. doi:10.1007/s11229-020-02589-0 (Scholar)
- Austin, Christopher J., 2015, “The Dispositional Genome:
Primus Inter Pares”, Biology & Philosophy,
30(2): 227–246, doi:10.1007/s10539-014-9454-y. (Scholar)
- Bar-On, Dorit, 2018, “Communicative Intentions, Expressive
Communication, and Origins of Meaning”, in
Andrews and Beck 2018:
301–312 (ch. 28). (Scholar)
- Bar-On, Dorit and Richard Moore, 2018, “Pragmatic Interpretation and Signaler-Receiver Asymmetries in Animal Communication”, in Andrews and Beck 2018: 291–300 (ch. 27). (Scholar)
- Baetu, Tudor M., 2012, “Genomic Programs as Mechanism Schemas: A Non-Reductionist Interpretation”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3): 649–671. doi:10.1093/bjps/axr042 (Scholar)
- Bergstrom, Carl T. and Martin Rosvall, 2011, “The Transmission Sense of Information”, Biology & Philosophy, 26(2): 159–176. doi:10.1007/s10539-009-9180-z (Scholar)
- Birch, Jonathan, 2014, “Propositional Content in Signalling Systems”, Philosophical Studies, 171(3): 493–512. doi:10.1007/s11098-014-0280-5 (Scholar)
- Bourrat, Pierrick, 2019, “Variation of Information as a Measure of One-to-One Causal Specificity”, European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 9(1): article 11. doi:10.1007/s13194-018-0224-6 (Scholar)
- Bradbury, Jack W. and Sandra Lee Vehrencamp, 1998, Principles
of Animal Communication, Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates. (Scholar)
- Bruner, Justin, Cailin O’Connor, Hannah Rubin, and Simon M.
Huttegger, 2018, “David Lewis in the Lab: Experimental Results
on the Emergence of Meaning”, Synthese, 195(2):
603–621. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0535-x (Scholar)
- Calcott, Brett, 2014, “The Creation and Reuse of Information in Gene Regulatory Networks”, Philosophy of Science, 81(5): 879–890. doi: 10.1086/677687 (Scholar)
- Calcott, Brett, Arnaud Pocheville, and Paul Griffiths, 2020, “Signals That Make a Difference”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71(1): 233–258. doi:10.1093/bjps/axx022 (Scholar)
- Cao, Rosa, 2012, “A Teleosemantic Approach to Information in the Brain”, Biology & Philosophy, 27(1): 49–71. doi:10.1007/s10539-011-9292-0 (Scholar)
- –––, 2022, “Putting Representations to Use”, Synthese, 200(2): article 151. doi:10.1007/s11229-022-03522-3 (Scholar)
- Chemero, Anthony, 2009, Radical Embodied Cognitive Science (A Bradford Book), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Cohen, Jonathan and Aaron Meskin, 2006, “An Objective Counterfactual Theory of Information”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(3): 333–352. doi:10.1080/00048400600895821 (Scholar)
- Crick, Francis, 1958, “On Protein Synthesis”, in The
Biological Replication of Macromolecules (Symposia of the
Society for Experimental Biology, 12), New York: Academic Press,
138–163.
[Crick 1958 available online] (Scholar)
- Dawkins, Richard, 1976, The Selfish Gene, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, River out of Eden: A Darwinian
View of Life (Science Masters Series), New York: Basic
Books. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, A Devil’s Chaplain:
Selected Essays, Latha Menon (ed.), London: Weidenfeld &
Nicolson. (Scholar)
- Dawkins, Richard and John R. Krebs, 1978, “Animal Signals: Information or Manipulation?”, in Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach, John R. Krebs and Nicholas B. Davies (eds), first edition, Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates, 282–309. (Scholar)
- Falk, Raphael, 1986, “What Is a Gene?”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 17(2): 133–173. doi:10.1016/0039-3681(86)90024-5 (Scholar)
- Fodor, Jerry A., 1987, Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (Explorations in Cognitive Science 2), Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Font, Enrique and Pau Carazo, 2010, “Animals in Translation:
Why There Is Meaning (but Probably No Message) in Animal
Communication”, Animal Behaviour, 80(2): e1–e6.
doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2010.05.015 (Scholar)
- Fox Keller, Evelyn, 2001, “Beyond the Gene but beneath the
Skin”, in Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and
Evolution (Life and Mind: Philosophical Issues in Biology and
Psychology), Susan Oyama, Paul E. Griffiths, and Russell D. Gray
(eds), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 299–312 (ch. 21). (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “Rethinking the Meaning of Biological Information”, Biological Theory, 4(2): 159–166. doi:10.1162/biot.2009.4.2.159 (Scholar)
- Fresco, Nir, Simona Ginsburg, and Eva Jablonka, 2020, “Functional Information: A Graded Taxonomy of Difference Makers”, Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11(3): 547–567. doi:10.1007/s13164-018-0410-7 (Scholar)
- Frick, Ramiro, Leonardo Bich, and Alvaro Moreno, 2019, “An Organisational Approach to Biological Communication”, Acta Biotheoretica, 67(2): 103–128. doi:10.1007/s10441-019-09342-2 (Scholar)
- Godfrey-Smith, Peter, 1999, “Genes and Codes: Lessons from
the Philosophy of Mind?”, in Where Biology Meets Psychology:
Philosophical Essays, Valerie Gray Hardcastle (ed.), Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 305–332 (ch. 15).
doi:10.7551/mitpress/7220.003.0017 (Scholar)
- –––, 2000a, “Information, Arbitrariness, and Selection: Comments on Maynard Smith”, Philosophy of Science, 67(2): 202–207. doi:10.1086/392770 (Scholar)
- –––, 2000b, “On the Theoretical Role of ‘Genetic Coding’”, Philosophy of Science, 67(1): 26–44. doi:10.1086/392760 (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, “Genes Do Not Encode
Information for Phenotypic Traits”, in Contemporary Debates
in Philosophy of Science (Contemporary Debates in Philosophy 2),
Christopher Hitchcock (ed.), Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing,
275–289. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Review of Signals: Evolution, Learning, and Information, by Brian Skyrms”, Mind, 120(480): 1288–1297. doi:10.1093/mind/fzs002 (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Sender-Receiver Systems within and between Organisms”, Philosophy of Science, 81(5): 866–878. doi:10.1086/677686 (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “In the Beginning There Was Information?”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 80: 101239. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2019.101239 (Scholar)
- Griesemer, James, 2005, “The Informational Gene and the Substantial Body: On the Generalization of Evolutionary Theory By Abstraction”, in Idealization XII, Correcting the Model: Idealization and Abstraction in the Sciences (Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 86), Martin R. Jones and Nancy Cartwright (eds), Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 59–115. (Scholar)
- Griffiths, Paul E., 2001, “Genetic Information: A Metaphor In Search of a Theory”, Philosophy of Science, 68(3): 394–412. doi:10.1086/392891 (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “Proximate and Ultimate Information in Biology”, in The Philosophy of Philip Kitcher, Mark Couch and Jessica Pfeifer (eds), New York: Oxford University Press, 74–97. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199381357.003.0004 (Scholar)
- Griffiths, Paul E. and Russell D. Gray, 1994, “Developmental Systems and Evolutionary Explanation”:, Journal of Philosophy, 91(6): 277–304. doi:10.2307/2940982 (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Discussion: Three Ways to Misunderstand Developmental Systems Theory”, Biology & Philosophy, 20(2–3): 417–425. doi:10.1007/s10539-004-0758-1 (Scholar)
- Griffiths, Paul E. and Robin D. Knight, 1998, “What Is the Developmentalist Challenge?”, Philosophy of Science, 65(2): 253–258. doi:10.1086/392636 (Scholar)
- Griffiths, Paul E. and Karola Stotz, 2013, Genetics and Philosophy: An Introduction (Cambridge Introductions to Philosophy and Biology), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511744082 (Scholar)
- Haldane, John B. S. and Helen Spurway, 1954, “A Statistical
Analysis of Communication in ‘Apis mellifera’ and a
Comparison with Communication in Other Animals”, Insectes
Sociaux, 1(3): 247–283. doi:10.1007/bf02222949 (Scholar)
- Hauser, Marc D., 1996, The Evolution of Communication,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/2867.001.0001 (Scholar)
- Huttegger, Simon M., 2007, “Evolution and the Explanation of Meaning”, Philosophy of Science, 74(1): 1–27. doi:10.1086/519477 (Scholar)
- Hutto, Daniel D. and Erik Myin, 2013, Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262018548.001.0001 (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, Evolving Enactivism: Basic Minds Meet Content, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262036115.001.0001 (Scholar)
- Isaac, Alistair M. C., 2019, “The Semantics Latent in Shannon Information”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(1): 103–125. doi:10.1093/bjps/axx029 (Scholar)
- Jablonka, Eva, 2002, “Information: Its Interpretation, Its Inheritance, and Its Sharing”, Philosophy of Science, 69(4): 578–605. doi:10.1086/344621 (Scholar)
- Kalkman, David, 2019, “New Problems for Defining Animal Communication in Informational Terms”, Synthese, 196(8): 3319–3336. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1598-2 (Scholar)
- Kight, Caitlin R., John M. McNamara, David W. Stephens, and Sasha
R. X. Dall, 2013, “Communication as Information Use:
Insights from Statistical Decision Theory”, in
Stegmann 2013a:
89–112 (ch. 3). doi:10.1017/cbo9781139003551.006 (Scholar)
- Kõiv, Riin, 2020, “Elusive Vehicles of Genetic Representation”, Biology & Philosophy, 35(1): article 24. doi:10.1007/s10539-020-9741-8 (Scholar)
- Krebs, John R. and Richard Dawkins, 1984, “Animal Signals:
Mind-Reading and Manipulation”, in Behavioural Ecology: An
Evolutionary Approach, John R. Krebs and Nicholas B. Davies
(eds), second edition, Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates,
380–402. (Scholar)
- Lean, Oliver M., 2014, “Getting the Most out of Shannon Information”, Biology & Philosophy, 29(3): 395–413. doi:10.1007/s10539-013-9410-2 (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “Chemical Arbitrariness and the Causal Role of Molecular Adapters”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 78: 101180. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2019.101180 (Scholar)
- Lehman, Daniel S., 1970, “Semantic and Conceptual Issues in
the Nature-Nurture Problem”, in Development and Evolution of
Behavior: Essays in Memory of T. C. Schneirla (A Series of Books
in Psychology), Lester R. Aronson, Ethel Tobach, Daniel S. Lehman, and
Jay S. Rosenblatt (eds), San Francisco, CA: W. H. Freeman,
17–52. (Scholar)
- Levy, Arnon, 2011, “Information in Biology: A Fictionalist Account”, Noûs, 45(4): 640–657. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00792.x (Scholar)
- Lewis, David K., 1969, Convention: A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Lewontin, Richard, 1974, “Annotation: The Analysis of
Variance and the Analysis of Causes”, American Journal of
Human Genetics, 26(3): 400–411. (Scholar)
- –––, 2000, The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism, and Environment, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Macedonia, Joseph M. and Christopher S. Evans, 1993, “Essay
on Contemporary Issues in Ethology: Variation among Mammalian Alarm
Call Systems and the Problem of Meaning in Animal Signals”,
Ethology, 93(3): 177–197.
doi:10.1111/j.1439-0310.1993.tb00988.x (Scholar)
- Mann, Stephen Francis, 2018, “Attribution of Information in Animal Interaction”, Biological Theory, 13(3): 164–179. doi:10.1007/s13752-018-0299-5 (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “Consequences of a Functional Account of Information”, Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11(3): 669–687. doi:10.1007/s13164-018-0413-4 (Scholar)
- Martínez, Manolo, 2019, “Representations Are Rate-Distortion Sweet Spots”, Philosophy of Science, 86(5): 1214–1226. doi:10.1086/705493 (Scholar)
- Martínez, Manolo and Peter Godfrey-Smith, 2016, “Common Interest and Signaling Games: A Dynamic Analysis”, Philosophy of Science, 83(3): 371–392. doi:10.1086/685743 (Scholar)
- Meunier, Robert, 2022 [2023], “Gene”, in The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023), Edward N. Zalta
and Uri Nodelman (eds), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2023/entries/gene/>. (Scholar)
- Maynard Smith, John, 2000, “The Concept of Information in Biology”, Philosophy of Science, 67(2): 177–194. doi:10.1086/392768 (Scholar)
- Maynard Smith, John and David Harper, 2003, Animal
Signals (Oxford Series in Ecology and Evolution), Oxford/New
York: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/oso/9780198526841.001.0001 (Scholar)
- McAninch, Andrew, Grant Goodrich, and Colin Allen, 2009, “Animal Communication and Neo-Expressivism”, in The Philosophy of Animal Minds, Robert W. Lurz (ed.), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 128–144. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511819001.008 (Scholar)
- McCowan, Brenda, Sean F. Hanser, and Laurance R. Doyle, 1999,
“Quantitative Tools for Comparing Animal Communication Systems:
Information Theory Applied to Bottlenose Dolphin Whistle
Repertoires”, Animal Behaviour, 57(2): 409–419.
doi:10.1006/anbe.1998.1000 (Scholar)
- Millikan, Ruth Garrett, 1984, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1989, “In Defense of Proper Functions”, Philosophy of Science, 56(2): 288–302. doi:10.1086/289488 (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “Pushmi-Pullyu Representations”, Philosophical Perspectives, 9: 185–200. doi:10.2307/2214217 (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, Varieties of Meaning: The 2002 Jean Nicod Lectures, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Monod, Jacques, 1970, Le hasard et la nécessité: essai sur la philosophie naturelle de la biologie moderne, Paris: Éditions du Seuil. (Scholar)
- Moss, Lenny, 1992, “A Kernel of Truth? On the Reality of the Genetic Program”, PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1992(1): 335–348. doi:10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1992.1.192766 (Scholar)
- Neander, Karen, 1991, “Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst’s Defense”, Philosophy of Science, 58(2): 168–184. doi:10.1086/289610 (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, A Mark of the Mental: In Defense of Informational Teleosemantics (Life and Mind: Philosophical Issues in Biology and Psychology), Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262036146.001.0001 (Scholar)
- O’Connor, Cailin, 2014, “Evolving Perceptual Categories”, Philosophy of Science, 81(5): 840–851. doi:10.1086/677885 (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, Games in the Philosophy of Biology (Cambridge Elements. Elements in the Philosophy of Biology), Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781108616737 (Scholar)
- Otte, Daniel, 1974, “Effects and Functions in the Evolution
of Signaling Systems”, Annual Review of Ecology and
Systematics, 5: 385–417.
doi:10.1146/annurev.es.05.110174.002125 (Scholar)
- Owren, Michael J., Drew Rendall, and Michael J. Ryan, 2010, “Redefining Animal Signaling: Influence versus Information in Communication”, Biology & Philosophy, 25(5): 755–780. doi:10.1007/s10539-010-9224-4 (Scholar)
- Oyama, Susan, 1985, The Ontogeny of Information: Developmental
Systems and Evolution, Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University
Press. (Scholar)
- Pfeifer, Jessica, 2006, “The Use of Information Theory in Biology: Lessons from Social Insects”, Biological Theory, 1(3): 317–330. doi:10.1162/biot.2006.1.3.317 (Scholar)
- Planer, Ronald J., 2014, “Replacement of the ‘Genetic Program’ Program”, Biology & Philosophy, 29(1): 33–53. doi:10.1007/s10539-013-9388-9 (Scholar)
- Planer, Ronald J. and David Kalkman, 2021, “Arbitrary Signals and Cognitive Complexity”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 72(2): 563–586. doi:10.1093/bjps/axz018 (Scholar)
- Pocheville, Arnaud, 2018, “Biological Information as Choice and Construction”, Philosophy of Science, 85(5): 1012–1025. doi:10.1086/699832 (Scholar)
- Rendall, Drew and Michael J. Owren, 2013, “Communication
without Meaning or Information: Abandoning Language-Based and
Informational Constructs in Animal Communication Theory”, in
Stegmann 2013a:
151–188 (ch. 6). doi:10.1017/cbo9781139003551.010 (Scholar)
- Rendall, Drew, Michael J. Owren, and Michael J. Ryan, 2009,
“What Do Animal Signals Mean?”, Animal Behaviour,
78(2): 233–240. doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2009.06.007 (Scholar)
- Ruxton, Graeme D. and H. Martin Schaefer, 2011, “Resolving
Current Disagreements and Ambiguities in the Terminology of Animal
Communication: Definitions in Animal Communication”, Journal
of Evolutionary Biology, 24(12): 2574–2585.
doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2011.02386.x (Scholar)
- Sarkar, Sahotra, 1996, “Biological Information: A Skeptical
Look at Some Central Dogmas of Molecular Biology”, in The
Philosophy and History of Molecular Biology: New Perspectives
(Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 183), Sahotra Sarkar
(ed.), Dordrecht/Boston: Kluwer Academic, 187–232. (Scholar)
- –––, 2000, “Information in Genetics and Developmental Biology: Comments on Maynard Smith”, Philosophy of Science, 67(2): 208–213. doi:10.1086/392771 (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Information in Animal
Communication: When and Why Does It Matter?1”, in
Stegmann 2013a:
189–206 (ch. 7). doi:10.1017/cbo9781139003551.011 (Scholar)
- Scarantino, Andrea, 2010, “Animal Communication between
Information and Influence”, Animal Behaviour, 79(6):
e1–e5. doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2010.03.005 (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Animal Communication as
Information-Mediated Influence”, in
Stegmann 2013a:
63–88 (ch. 2). doi:10.1017/cbo9781139003551.005 (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Information as a Probabilistic Difference Maker”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(3): 419–443. doi:10.1080/00048402.2014.993665 (Scholar)
- Schulte, Peter, 2018, “Perceiving the World Outside: How to Solve the Distality Problem for Informational Teleosemantics”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 68(271): 349–369. (Scholar)
- Scott‐Phillips, Thomas C., 2008, “Defining Biological
Communication”, Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 21(2):
387–395. doi:10.1111/j.1420-9101.2007.01497.x (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Animal Communication: Insights
from Linguistic Pragmatics”, Animal Behaviour, 79(1):
e1–e4. doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2009.10.013 (Scholar)
- Searcy, William A., 1992, “Song Repertoire and Mate Choice
in Birds”, American Zoologist, 32(1): 71–80.
doi:10.1093/icb/32.1.71 (Scholar)
- Searcy, William A. and Stephen Nowicki, 2005, The Evolution of
Animal Communication: Reliability and Deception in Signaling
Systems (Monographs in Behavior and Ecology), Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press. doi:10.1515/9781400835720 (Scholar)
- Seyfarth, Robert M., Dorothy L. Cheney, and Peter Marler, 1980,
“Vervet Monkey Alarm Calls: Semantic Communication in a
Free-Ranging Primate”, Animal Behaviour, 28(4):
1070–1094. doi:10.1016/s0003-3472(80)80097-2 (Scholar)
- Seyfarth, Robert M., Dorothy L. Cheney, Thore Bergman, Julia
Fischer, Klaus Zuberbühler, and Kurt Hammerschmidt, 2010,
“The Central Importance of Information in Studies of Animal
Communication”, Animal Behaviour, 80(1): 3–8.
doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2010.04.012 (Scholar)
- Shannon, Claude E., 1948, “A Mathematical Theory of Communication”, Bell System Technical Journal, 27(3): 379–423. doi:10.1002/j.1538-7305.1948.tb01338.x (Scholar)
- Shea, Nicholas, 2007, “Representation in the Genome and in Other Inheritance Systems”, Biology & Philosophy, 22(3): 313–331. doi:10.1007/s10539-006-9046-6 (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Developmental Systems Theory Formulated as a Claim about Inherited Representations”, Philosophy of Science, 78(1): 60–82. doi:10.1086/658110 (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, Representation in Cognitive Science, Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Shea, Nicholas, Peter Godfrey-Smith, and Rosa Cao, 2018, “Content in Simple Signalling Systems”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(4): 1009–1035. doi:10.1093/bjps/axw036 (Scholar)
- Skyrms, Brian, 2009, “Evolution of Signalling Systems with Multiple Senders and Receivers”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364(1518): 771–779. doi:10.1098/rstb.2008.0258 (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, Signals: Evolution, Learning, and Information, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199580828.001.0001 (Scholar)
- Skyrms, Brian and Jeffrey A. Barrett, 2019, “Propositional Content in Signals”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 74: 34–39. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2019.01.005 (Scholar)
- Smith, W. John, 1977, The Behavior of Communicating: An
Ethological Approach, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press. (Scholar)
- Sprevak, Mark, 2013, “Fictionalism about Neural Representations”:, The Monist, 96(4): 539–560. doi:10.5840/monist201396425 (Scholar)
- Stegmann, Ulrich E., 2004, “The Arbitrariness of the Genetic Code”, Biology & Philosophy, 19(2): 205–222. doi:10.1023/b:biph.0000024412.82219.a6 (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Genetic Information as Instructional Content”, Philosophy of Science, 72(3): 425–443. doi:10.1086/498472 (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “A Consumer-Based Teleosemantics for Animal Signals”, Philosophy of Science, 76(5): 864–875. doi:10.1086/605820 (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Varieties of Parity”, Biology & Philosophy, 27(6): 903–918. doi:10.1007/s10539-012-9331-5 (Scholar)
- ––– (ed.), 2013a, Animal
Communication Theory: Information and Influence, Cambridge/New
York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139003551
- –––, 2013b, “Introduction: A Primer on
Information and Influence in Animal Communication”, in
Stegmann 2013a:
1–40. doi:10.1017/cbo9781139003551.002 (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Causal Control and Genetic Causation”, Noûs, 48(3): 450–465. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2012.00867.x (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Prospects for Probabilistic Theories of Natural Information”, Erkenntnis, 80(4): 869–893. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9679-9 (Scholar)
- Sterelny, Kim, 2000, “The ‘Genetic Program’ Program: A Commentary on Maynard Smith on Information in Biology”, Philosophy of Science, 67(2): 195–201. doi:10.1086/392769 (Scholar)
- Sterelny, Kim, Kelly C. Smith, and Michael Dickison, 1996, “The Extended Replicator”, Biology & Philosophy, 11(3): 377–403. doi:10.1007/bf00128788 (Scholar)
- Stotz, Karola and Paul E. Griffiths, 2017a, “Biological Information, Causality, and Specificity: An Intimate Relationship”, in From Matter to Life: Information and Causality, Sara Imari Walker, Paul C. W. Davies, and George F. R. Ellis (eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 366–390. doi:10.1017/9781316584200.015 (Scholar)
- –––, 2017b, “Genetic, Epigenetic, and
Exogenetic Information”, in The Routledge Handbook of
Evolution and Philosophy, Richard Joyce (ed.), New York:
Routledge, 106–119 (ch. 8). (Scholar)
- Šustar, Predrag, 2007, “Crick’s Notion of Genetic Information and the ‘Central Dogma’ of Molecular Biology”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(1): 13–24. doi:10.1093/bjps/axl018 (Scholar)
- Waters, C. Kenneth, 2007, “Causes That Make a Difference”, The Journal of Philosophy, 104(11): 551–579. doi:10.5840/jphil2007104111 (Scholar)
- Weber, Marcel, 2006, “The Central Dogma as a Thesis of Causal Specificity”, History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 28(4): 595–609. (Scholar)
- Wheeler, Brandon C., William A. Searcy, Morten H. Christiansen,
Michael C. Corballis, Julia Fischer, Christoph Grüter, Daniel
Margoliash, Michael J. Owren, Tabitha Price, Robert Seyfarth, and
Markus Wild, 2011, “Communication”, in Animal
Thinking: Contemporary Issues in Comparative Cognition
(Strüngmann Forum Reports), Randolf Menzel and Julia Fischer
(eds), Cambridge: MA: The MIT Press, 187–206 (ch. 13).
doi:10.7551/mitpress/9187.003.0018 (Scholar)
- Williams, George C., 1992, Natural Selection: Domains, Levels,
and Challenges (Oxford Series in Ecology and Evolution 4), New
York: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/oso/9780195069327.001.0001 (Scholar)
- Wilson, Edward O., 1962, “Chemical Communication among
Workers of the Fire Ant Solenopsis saevissima (Fr. Smith) 2.
An Information Analysis of the Odour Trail”, Animal
Behaviour, 10(1–2): 148–158.
doi:10.1016/0003-3472(62)90142-2 (Scholar)
- Zahavi, Amotz, 1975, “Mate Selection—A Selection for a
Handicap”, Journal of Theoretical Biology, 53(1):
205–214. doi:10.1016/0022-5193(75)90111-3 (Scholar)