Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Kantian Conceptualism/Nonconceptualism" by Colin McLear

This is an automatically generated and experimental page

If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.

This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.

Works of Kant

Quotations from Kant’s work are from the German edition of Kant’s works, the Akademie Ausgabe, with the first Critique cited by the standard A/B edition pagination, and the other works by volume and page.

  • [Ak.] Königlichen Preußischen (later Deutschen) Akademie der Wissenschaften (ed.), 1900-, Kants gesammelte Schriften, Berlin: Georg Reimer (later Walter De Gruyter). (Scholar)

The most authoritative English translation of Kant’s works is:

  • Guyer, Paul and Allen W. Wood (eds.), 1992–, The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)

English translations in most cases closely followed translations from the Cambridge Editions. Specific texts are abbreviated as follows:

An
Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
C
Correspondence
CPR
Critique of Pure Reason
CPJ
Critique of the Power of Judgment
JL
Jäsche Logic
LA
Lectures on Anthropology
LL
Lecturs on Logic
LM
Lectures on Metaphysics
OP
Opus Postumum
Pr
Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics

Individual volumes used in the preparation of this entry are:

  • Correspondence, Arnulf Zweig (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
  • Critique of Pure Reason, Paul Guyer and Allen Wood (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • Critique of the Power of Judgment, Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
  • History, Anthropology, and Education, Günter Zöller and Robert Louden (eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
  • Lectures on Anthropology, Allen W. Wood and Robert B. Louden (eds and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.
  • Lectures on Logic, J. Michael Young (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
  • Lectures on Metaphysics, Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon (eds and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
  • Practical Philosophy, Mary Gregor (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
  • Theoretical Philosophy 1755–1770, David Walford (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. (Scholar)
  • Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, Henry Allison and Peter Heath (eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002

Other Primary Sources

Hegel’s work cited in this entry (in translation):

  • The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, translated by H.S. Harris and W. Cerf, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1977. (Scholar)
  • Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A.V. Miller, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.
  • Faith and Knowledge, translated by H.S. Harris and W. Cerf, Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1977.
  • The Encyclopaedia Logic (with the Zusätze), translated by T. F. Geraets, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris, Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Press, 1991.

Solomon Maimon’s work cited in this entry (in translation):

  • Essay on Transcendental Philosophy, New York: Continuum, 2010.

Johann Gottfried von Herder’s work cited in this entry (in translation):

  • Treatise on the Origin of Language (1772), in Herder: Philosophical Writings, Michael Forster (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. (Scholar)

Secondary Literature

  • Abel, Günter and James Conant (eds), 2012, Rethinking Epistemology, 2 volumes, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
  • Abela, Paul, 2002, Kant’s Empirical Realism, New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199242740.001.0001 (Scholar)
  • Allais, Lucy, 2009, “Kant, Non-Conceptual Content and the Representation of Space”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 47(3): 383–413.
  • –––, 2010, “Kant’s Argument for Transcendental Idealism in the Transcendental Aesthetic”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 110(1/1): 47–75.
  • –––, 2011a, “Idealism Enough: Response to Roche”, Kantian Review, 16(3): 375–398.
  • –––, 2011b, “Transcendental Idealism and the Transcendental Deduction”, in Kant’s Idealism, Dennis Schulting and Jacco Verburgt (eds), Springer Netherlands, 91–107.
  • –––, 2015, Manifest Reality: Kant’s Idealism and His Realism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2016, “Conceptualism and Nonconceptualism in Kant: A Survey of the Recent Debate”, in Schulting 2016: 1–25.
  • –––, 2017a, “Synthesis and Binding”, in Gomes and Stephenson 2017: 25–45.
  • –––, 2017b, “Transcendental Idealism and the Transcendental Aesthetic: Reading the Critique of Pure Reason Forward”, in O’Shea 2017: 46–63.
  • Allais, Lucy and John Callanan (eds), forthcoming, Kant on Animals, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Allison, Henry E., 1973, The Kant-Eberhard Controversy, Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
  • –––, 1990, Kant’s Theory of Freedom, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1996, Idealism and Freedom: Essays on Kant’s Theoretical and Practical Philosophy, New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2000, “Where Have All the Categories Gone: Reflections on Longuenesse’s Reading of Kant’s Transcendental Deduction”, Inquiry, 43(1): 67–80.
  • –––, 2015, Kant’s Transcendental Deduction: An Analytical-Historical Commentary, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Allison, Henry E., and Nicholas Jolley, 1981, “Locke’s Pyrrhic Victory”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 42(4): 672–674.
  • Ameriks, Karl, 2000, Kant’s Theory of Mind: An Analysis of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Anderson, R. Lanier, 2015, The Poverty of Conceptual Truth: Kant’s Analytic/Synthetic Distinction and the Limits of Metaphysics, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Aquila, Richard E., 1974, “Kant’s Theory of Concepts”, Kant-Studien, 65(1–4): 1–19. doi:10.1515/kant.1974.65.1-4.1
  • –––, 1994, “The Holistic Character of Kantian Intuition”, in Kant and Contemporary Epistemology, Paulo Parrini (ed.), Dordrecht: Springer, 309–329.
  • –––, 2001, “Infinitude, Whole-Part Priority, and the Ambiguity of Kantian ‘Space’ and ‘Time’”, in Gerhardt et al. 2001: 99–109.
  • Banham, Gary, 2005, Kant’s Transcendental Imagination, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Bauer, Nathan, 2012, “A Peculiar Intuition: Kant’s Conceptualist Account of Perception”, Inquiry, 55(3): 215–237.
  • Beck, Lewis White, 1955, “Can Kant’s Synthetic Judgments Be Made Analytic”, Kant-Studien, 47(1–4): 168–181.
  • –––, 1978, “Did the Sage of Königsberg Have No Dreams”, in his Essays on Kant and Hume, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 38–60.
  • Bell, David, 2001, “The Inaugural Address: Some Kantian Thoughts on Propositional Unity”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 75: 1–16.
  • Bennett, Jonathan, 1966, Kant’s Analytic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1974, Kant’s Dialectic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Berg, Hein van den, 2018, “A Blooming and Buzzing Confusion: Buffon, Reimarus, and Kant on Animal Cognition”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 72: 1–9. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2018.10.002
  • Berman, David, 1974, “Francis Hutcheson on Berkeley and the Molyneux Problem”, Proceedings of the Royal Irish Academy. Section C: Archaeology, Celtic Studies, History, Linguistics, Literature, 74: 259–265.
  • Beth, Evert Willem, 1957, “Über Lockes ‘Allgemeines Dreieck’”, Kant-Studien, 48(1–4): 361–380.
  • Bird, Graham, 1962, Kant’s Theory of Knowledge: An Outline of One Central Argument in the Critique of Pure Reason, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • –––, 2006, The Revolutionary Kant: A Commentary on the Critique of Pure Reason, Peru, IL: Open Court Publishing Company.
  • Birrer, Mathias, 2017, Kant und die Heterogenität der Erkenntnisquellen, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG.
  • Blomme, Henny, 2012, “The Completeness of Kant’s Metaphysical Exposition of Space”, Kant-Studien, 103(2): 139–162.
  • BonJour, Laurence, 1985, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Bossart, William H., 1977, “Kant’s Transcendental Deduction”, Kant-Studien, 68(1–4): 383–403.
  • Bowman, Brady, 2011, “A Conceptualist Reply to Hanna’s Kantian Non-Conceptualism”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19(3): 417–446. doi:10.1080/09672559.2011.595191
  • Boyle, Matthew, 2012, “Essentially Rational Animals”, in Abel and Conant 2012: vol. 2, 395–427.
  • –––, 2016, “Additive Theories of Rationality: A Critique”, European Journal of Philosophy, 24(3): 527–555.
  • –––, 2017, “A Different Kind of Mind?” In The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal Minds, Kristin Andrews and Jacob Beck (eds), New York: Routledge, 109–118.
  • Broad, Charlie Dunbar, 1978, Kant: An Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Brook, Andrew, 1997, Kant and the Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Brown, Clifford, 2006, Peter Strawson, Stocksfield, UK: Acumen.
  • Byrne, Alex, 2005, “Perception and Conceptual Content”, In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, edited by Matthias Steup and Ernest Sosa, 231–250. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2009, “Experience and Content”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236): 429–451.
  • Callanan, John, forthcoming, “The Comparison of Animals”, in Allais and John Callanan forthcoming.
  • Campbell, John, 2002, Reference and Consciousness, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2011, “Relational Vs. Kantian Responses to Berkeley’s Puzzle”, in Perception, Causation, and Objectivity, Johannes Roessler, Hemdat Lerman, and Naomi Eilan (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 35–50.
  • Carl, Wolfgang, 1992, Die transzendentale Deduktion der Kategorien in der ersten Auflage der Kritik der reinen Vernunft: ein Kommentar, Berlin: V. Klostermann.
  • Carson, Emily, 1997, “Kant on Intuition and Geometry”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 27(4): 489–512.
  • –––, 1999, “Kant on the Method of Mathematics”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 37(4): 629–652.
  • –––, 2006, “Locke and Kant on Mathematical Knowledge”, in Intuition and Axiomatic Method, Emily Carson and Renate Huber (eds), Dordrecht: Springer, 3–20.
  • Chalmers, David J., 2011, “Propositions and Attitude Ascriptions: A Fregean Account”, Noûs, 45(4): 595–639.
  • Chignell, Andrew. 2007a, “Belief in Kant”, The Philosophical Review, 116(3): 323–360.
  • –––, 2007b, “Kant’s Concepts of Justification”, Noûs, 41(1): 33–63.
  • –––, 2010, “Real Repugnance and Belief About Things-in-Themselves: A Problem and Kant’s Three Solutions”, in Lipscomb and Krueger 2010: 177–209. doi:10.1515/9783110220049.4.177
  • Child, William, 1994, Causality, Interpretation, and the Mind, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Chipman, Lauchlan, 1972, “Kant’s Categories and Their Schematism”, Kant-Studien, 63(1): 36–50.
  • Coffa, J. Alberto, 1991, The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap : To the Vienna Station, Linda Wessels (ed.), New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cohen, Hermann, 1871, Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, Berlin: Ferd. Dümmler.
  • –––, 1907, Kommentar zu Immanuel Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Vol. 113, Leipzig: F. Meiner.
  • Collins, Arthur, 1999, Possible Experience: Understanding Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
  • Conant, James, 2016, “Why Kant Is Not a Kantian”, Philosophical Topics, 44(1): 75–125.
  • Connolly, Kevin, 2014, “Which Kantian Conceptualism (or Nonconceptualism)”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 52(3): 316–337.
  • Dahlstrom, Daniel O., 1984, “Transzendentale Schemata, Kategorien und Erkenntnisarten”, Kant-Studien, 75(1–4): 38–54. doi:10.1515/kant.1984.75.1-4.38
  • Dufour, Éric, 2003, “Remarques sur la note du paragraphe 26 de l’Analytique transcendantale: Les interprétations de Cohen et de Heidegger”, Kant-Studien, 94(1): 69–79.
  • Dunlop, Katherine, 2012, “Kant and Strawson on the Content of Geometrical Concepts”, Noûs, 46(1): 86–126.
  • –––, 2017, “Understanding Non-Conceptual Representation of Objects: Empirical Models of Sensibility’s Operation”, in Gomes and Stephenson 2017: 46–66.
  • Engstrom, Stephen, 2006, “Understanding and Sensibility”, Inquiry, 49(1): 2–25.
  • –––, 2019, “The Category of Substance”, Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy: From Leibniz to Kant, 21: 235–260.
  • Evans, Gareth, 1982, The Varieties of Reference, John McDowell (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1985, “Molyneuxs Question”, in his Collected Papers, London: Oxford University Press, 364–399.
  • Faggion, Andrea, 2015, “Can Mere Intuitions Represent Objects”, in Kant’s Lectures, Robert Louden, Ubirajara Rancan de Azevedo Marques, Claudio La Rocca, and Bernd Dörflinger (eds), Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 91–103.
  • Falkenstein, Lorne, 1995, Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
  • Ferrarin, Alfredo, 1995, “Construction and Mathematical Schematism: Kant on the Exhibition of a Concept in Intuition”, Kant-Studien, 86: 131–174.
  • Fichant, Michel, 2004, “Espace esthétique et espace géométrique chez Kant”, Revue de métaphysique et de morale, no. 4: 530–550.
  • Fisher, Naomi, 2017, “Kant on Animal Minds”, Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Philosophy, 4: art. 15. doi:10.3998/ergo.12405314.0004.015
  • Fodor, Jerry A., 1987, Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
  • Frege, Gottlob, 1956, “The Thought: A Logical Inquiry”, Mind, 65(259): 289–311.
  • Friedman, Michael, 1990, “Kant on Concepts and Intuitions in the Mathematical Sciences”, Synthese, 84(2, The Philosophy of Mathematics, Part I): 213–257.
  • –––, 1992, Kant and the Exact Sciences, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2012, “Kant on Geometry and Spatial Intuition”, Synthese, 186(1): 231–255.
  • –––, 2015, “Kant on Geometry and Experience”, in Mathematizing Space, Vincenzo De Risi (ed.), Dordrecht: Springer, 275–309.
  • –––, 2019, “Henry Allison and the B-Deduction”, Virtual Critique, 7 September 2019. URL = <https://virtualcritique.wordpress.com/2019/04/19/henry-allison-and-the-b-deduction/>]
  • Garver, Newton, 1971, “The Variability of the Analytic”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 31(3): 409–414.
  • Geach, Peter Thomas, 1957, Mental Acts: Their Content and Their Objects, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • George, Rolf, 1981, “Kant’s Sensationism”, Synthese, 47(2): 229–255.
  • Gerhardt, Volker, Rolf-Peter Horstmann, and Ralph Schumacher, 2001, Kant und die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des IX. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. (Scholar)
  • Gibbons, Sarah, 2002, Kant’s Theory of Imagination: Bridging Gaps in Judgement and Experience, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Ginsborg, Hannah. 2006a, “Empirical Concepts and the Content of Experience”, European Journal of Philosophy, 14(3): 349–372.
  • –––, 2006b, “Kant and the Problem of Experience”, Philosophical Topics, 34(1&2): 59–106.
  • –––, 2006c, “Thinking the Particular as Contained Under the Universal”, in Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant’s Critical Philosophy, Rebecca Kukla (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 35–60.
  • –––, 2008, “Was Kant a Nonconceptualist”, Philosophical Studies, 137(1): 65–77.
  • Golob, Sacha, 2011, “Kant on Intentionality, Magnitude, and the Unity of Perception”, European Journal of Philosophy, 22(4): 505–528.
  • –––, 2016a, “Kant as Both Conceptualist and Nonconceptualist”, Kantian Review, 21(3): 367–391. doi:10.1017/S1369415416000248
  • –––, 2016b, “Why the Transcendental Deduction Is Compatible with Nonconceptualism”, in Schulting 2016: 27–52.
  • –––, 2017, “The Separability of Understanding and Sensibility: A Reply to James Conant”, Virtual Critique, [Golub 2017 available online] (Scholar)
  • –––, forthcoming, “What Do Animals See? Intentionality, Objects and Kantian Nonconceptualism”, in Allais and Callanan forthcoming.
  • Gomes, Anil, 2010, “Is Kant’s Transcendental Deduction of the Categories Fit for Purpose”, Kantian Review, 15(2): 118–137.
  • –––, 2013, “Kant and the Explanatory Role of Experience”, Kant-Studien, 104(3): 277–300.
  • –––, 2014, “Kant on Perception: Naïve Realism, Non-Conceptualism and the B-Deduction”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 64(254): 1–19.
  • –––, 2017a, “Naïve Realism In Kantian Phrase”, Mind, 126(502): 529–578. doi:10.1093/mind/fzw009
  • –––, 2017b, “Nonconceptualism, Hume’s Problem, and the Deduction”, Philosophical Studies, 174(7): 1687–1698. doi:10.1007/s11098-016-0833-x
  • Gomes, Anil, and Andrew Stephenson, 2016, “On the Relation of Intuition to Cognition”, in Schulting 2016: 53–79.
  • ––– (eds), 2017, Kant and the Philosophy of Mind: Perception, Reason, and the Self, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
  • Griffith, Aaron M., 2012, “Perception and the Categories: A Conceptualist Reading of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason”, European Journal of Philosophy, 20(2): 193–222.
  • Grüne, Stefanie, 2008, “Begriffe als Regeln der Wahrnehmung”, in Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Akten des X Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, Valerio Rohden, Ricardo R Terra, Guido Antonio Almedia, and Margit Ruffing (eds), Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 267–278..
  • –––, 2009, Blinde Anschauung, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
  • –––, 2011, “Is There a Gap in Kants B Deduction”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19(3): 465–490.
  • –––, 2014a, “Précis of Blinde Anschauung”, Virtual Critique,
  • –––, 2014b, “Reply to Colin Mclear”, Virtual Critique,
  • –––, 2016, “Sensible Synthesis and the Intuition of Space”, in Schulting 2016: 81–98.
  • –––, 2017a, “Are Kantian Intuitions Object-Dependent”, in Gomes and Stephenson 2017: 67–85.
  • –––, 2017b, “Givenness, Objective Reality, and a Priori Intuitions”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 55(1): 113–130. doi:10.1353/hph.2017.0004
  • Guyer, Paul, 1987, Kant and the Claims of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2010a, “The Deduction of the Categories: The Metaphysical and Transcendental Deductions”, in Guyer 2010b: 118–150.
  • –––, 2010b, The Cambridge Companion to Kant’s “Critique of Pure Reason”, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/ccol9780521883863 (Scholar)
  • –––, 2018, “The Infinite Given Magnitude and Other Myths About Space and Time”, in Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy, Ohad Nachtomy and Reed Winegar (eds.), (The New Synthese Historical Library 76), Cham: Springer International Publishing, 181–204. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-94556-9_11
  • Haag, Johannes, 2007, Erfahrung und Gegenstand, Vittorio Klostermann.
  • –––, 2013, “Kant on Imagination and the Natural Sources of the Conceptual”, in Contemporary Perspectives on Early Modern Philosophy: Nature and Norms in Thought, Martin Lenz and Anik Waldow (eds), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 65–85.
  • Hanks, Peter, 2009, “Recent Work on Propositions”, Philosophy Compass, 4(3): 469–486.
  • Hanna, Robert, 1993, “Direct Reference, Direct Perception, and the Cognitive Theory of Demonstratives”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 74(2): 96–117.
  • –––, 2001, Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2005, “Kant and Nonconceptual Content”, European Journal of Philosophy, 13(2): 247–290.
  • –––, 2008, “Kantian Non-Conceptualism”, Philosophical Studies, 137(1): 41–64.
  • –––, 2011a, “Beyond the Myth of the Myth: A Kantian Theory of Non-Conceptual Content”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19(3): 323–398.
  • –––, 2011b, “Kant’s Non-Conceptualism, Rogue Objects, and the Gap in the B Deduction”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19(3): 399–415.
  • –––, 2016, “Directions in Space, Nonconceptual Form and the Foundations of Transcendental Idealism”, in Schulting 2016: 99–116.
  • Hatfield, Gary, 2003, “What Were Kant’s Aims in the Deduction”, Philosophical Topics, 31(1/2, Modern Philosophy): 165–198.
  • Heck, Richard G., 2000, “Nonconceptual Content and the ‘Space of Reasons’”, The Philosophical Review, 109(4): 483–523.
  • –––, 2007, “Are There Different Kinds of Content”, in Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, Brian P McLaughlin and Jonathan Cohen (eds), Malden, MA: John Wiley & Sons, 117–138.
  • Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1977, Faith and Knowledge: An English Translation of G. W. F. Hegel’s Glauben Und Wissen, Edited by Walter Cerf and Henry Silton Harris. Albany: SUNY Press.
  • Heidegger, Martin, 1997, Phenomenological Interpretation of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Indiana University Press.
  • Heidemann, Dietmar H., 2011, “Introduction: Kant and Nonconceptual Content—Preliminary Remarks”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19(3): 319–322.
  • Heis, Jeremy, 2013, “The Priority Principle from Kant to Frege”, Noûs, 48(2): 268–97.
  • Henrich, Dieter, 1967, “Kants Denken 1762/3. Über den Ursprung der Unterscheidung Analytischer und Synthetischer Urteile”, in Studien zu Kants philosophischer Entwicklung, Heinz Heimsoeth (ed.), Hamburg: Olms, 9–38.
  • –––, 1989, “Kant’s Notion of a Deduction and the Methodological Background of the First Critique”, in Kant’s Transcendental Deductions: The Three Critiques and the Opus Postumum, Eckart Förster (ed.), Stanford: Stanford University Press, 29–46.
  • Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 2018, Kant’s Power of Imagination, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Howell, Robert, 1992, Kant’s Transcendental Deduction: An Analysis of Main Themes in His Critical Philosophy, Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Indregard, Jonas Jervell, forthcoming, “Kant and the Pre-Conceptual Use of the Understanding”, Archiv Für Geschichte Der Philosophie, [Indregard forthcoming available online]
  • Janaway, Christopher, 1997, “Kant’s Aesthetics and the ‘Empty Cognitive Stock’”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 47(189): 459–476.
  • Janiak, Andrew, 2012, “Kant’s Views on Space and Time”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N Zalta.
  • Jankowiak, Tim, 2014, “Sensations as Representations in Kant”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 22(3): 492–513. doi:10.1080/09608788.2014.913550
  • Kain, Patrick, 2010, “Practical Cognition, Intuition, and the Fact of Reason”, in Lipscomb and Krueger 2010: 211–230.
  • Kalderon, Mark Eli, 2011, “Before the Law”, Philosophical Issues, 21(1): 219–244.
  • Keller, Pierre, 1998, Kant and the Demands of Self-Consciousness, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Kemp Smith, Norman, 2003, A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Kneller, Jane, 2007, Kant and the Power of Imagination, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Kohl, Markus, 2015, “Kant on the Inapplicability of the Categories to Things in Themselves”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 23(1): 90–114. doi:10.1080/09608788.2014.978838
  • Kolb, Daniel C., 1986, “Thought and Intuition in Kant’s Critical System”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 24(2): 223–241. doi:10.1353/hph.1986.0032
  • Korsgaard, Christine M., 2011, “Interacting with Animals: A Kantian Account”, in The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics, Tom L Beauchamp and R. G. Frey (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 91–118.
  • Krausser, Peter, 1973, “‘Form of Intuition’ and ‘Formal Intuition’ in Kant’s Theory of Experience and Science”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 4(3): 279–287.
  • Kukla, Rebecca, ed, 2006, Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant’s Critical Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Land, Thomas, 2012, “Kantian Conceptualism”, in Abel and Conant 2012: vol. 1, 197–239.
  • –––, 2014, “Spatial Representation, Magnitude and the Two Stems of Cognition”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 44(5–6): 1–27.
  • –––, 2015a, “Nonconceptualist Readings of Kant and the Transcendental Deduction”, Kantian Review, 20(1): 25–51.
  • –––, 2015b, “No Other Use Than in Judgment?: Kant on Concepts and Sensible Synthesis”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 53(3): 461–484.
  • –––, 2018, “Conceptualism and the Objection from Animals”, in Natur und Freiheit: Akten des XII Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, V. L. Waibel and Margit Ruffing (eds), Berlin: De Gruyter, 1269–1276..
  • Landy, David, 2015, Kant’s Inferentialism: The Case Against Hume, Routledge.
  • Laywine, Alison, 1998, “Problems and Postulates: Kant on Reason and Understanding”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 36(9).
  • –––, 2003, “Kant on Sensibility and the Understanding in the 1770s”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33(4): 443–482.
  • Leech, Jessica, 2014, “Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the Possible, the Actual, and the Intuitive Understanding”, Kantian Review, 19(3): 339–365. doi:10.1017/S1369415414000156
  • –––, 2016, “The Mereology of Representation”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 116(2): 205–228. doi:10.1093/arisoc/aow010
  • Leland, Patrick R. 2018a, “Kant on Consciousness in Animals”, Studi Kantiani, 31: 75–107. doi:10.19272/201802901004
  • –––, 2018b, “Unconscious Representations in Kant’s Early Writings”, Kantian Review, 23(2): 257–284. doi:10.1017/S1369415418000055
  • Lipscomb, Benjamin J. Bruxvoort and James Krueger (eds.), 2010, Kant’s Moral Metaphysics: God, Freedom, and Immortality, Berlin: De Gruyter. doi:10.1515/9783110220049 (Scholar)
  • Longuenesse, Béatrice, 1998, Kant and the Capacity to Judge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2000, “Kant’s Categories and the Capacity to Judge: Responses to Henry Allison and Sally Sedgwick”, Inquiry, 43(1): 91–110.
  • Lovejoy, Arthur O., 1906, “Kant’s Antithesis of Dogmatism and Criticism”, Mind, 15(58): 191–214.
  • Lowe, E J., 2007, “Sortals and the Individuation of Objects”, Mind & Language, 22(5): 514–533.
  • Lu-adler, Hauping, 2013, “The Objects and the Formal Truth of Kantian Analytic Judgments”, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 30(2): 177–193.
  • Makkreel, Rudolf A., 1990, Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgment, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Matherne, Samantha, 2014, “Kant and the Art of Schematism”, Kantian Review, 19(2): 181–205.
  • –––, 2015, “Images and Kant’s Theory of Perception”, Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Philosophy, 2(29): 737–777. doi:10.3998/ergo.12405314.0002.029
  • McDowell, John. 1994a, Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1994b, “The Content of Perceptual Experience”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 44(175): 190–205.
  • –––, 1996, Mind and World: With a New Introduction, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1998, “The Woodbridge Lectures”, Journal of Philosophy, 95: 431–491.
  • –––, 2003, “Hegel and the Myth of the Given”, In, edited by Wolfgang Welsch and Klaus Vieweg, 75–88. München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.
  • –––, 2006, “Sensory Consciousness in Kant and Sellars”, Philosophical Topics, 34(1&2): 311–326.
  • –––, 2007a, “Hegel’s Idealism as Radicalization of Kant”, Internationales Jahrbuch Des Deutschen Idealismus=International Yearbook of German Idealism, no. 5: 157–175.
  • –––, 2007b, “What Myth”, Inquiry, 50(4): 338–351.
  • –––, 2008, “Avoiding the Myth of the Given”, In, edited by Jakob Lindgaard, 1–14. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2009, “Conceptual Capacities in Perception”, in his Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 127–144.
  • –––, 2010, “Autonomy and Its Burdens”, The Harvard Review of Philosophy, 17(1): 4–15.
  • –––, 2016, “Rationalism Without Dogmas”, in Giving a Damn, Zed Adams and Jacob Browning (eds), Cambridgee: MIT Press, 311–328.
  • McGinn, Colin, 1982, “The Structure of Content”, In, edited by Andrew Woodfield, 207–258. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • McGrath, Matthew, 2005 [2014], “Propositions”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). url = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/propositions/>
  • McLear, Colin, 2011, “Kant on Animal Consciousness”, Philosophers’ Imprint, 11(15): 1–16.
  • –––, 2014a, “Comments on Stefanie Grüne’s Blinde Anschauung”, Virtual Critique,
  • –––, 2014b, “The Kantian (Non)-Conceptualism Debate”, Philosophy Compass, 9(11): 769–790.
  • –––, 2015, “Two Kinds of Unity in the Critique of Pure Reason”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 53(1): 79–110.
  • –––, 2016a, “Getting Acquainted with Kant”, in Schulting 2016: 171–197.
  • –––, 2016b, “Kant on Perceptual Content”, Mind, 125(497): 95–144.
  • –––, 2017, “Intuition & Presence”, in Gomes and Stephenson 2017: 86–103.
  • –––, forthcoming-a, “Animals & Objectivity”, in Allais and Callanan forthcoming.
  • –––, forthcoming-b, “On the Transcendental Freedom of the Intellect”, Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Philosophy.
  • Melnick, Arthur, 1973, Kant’s Analogies of Experience, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
  • –––, 1989, Space, Time, and Thought in Kant, Vol. 204. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • –––, 2013, “Two Charges of Intellectualism Against Kant”, Kantian Review, 18(2): 197–219. doi:10.1017/S1369415413000010
  • Messina, James, 2014, “Kant on the Unity of Space and the Synthetic Unity of Apperception”, Kant-Studien, 105(1): 5–40.
  • –––, 2015, “Conceptual Analysis and the Essence of Space: Kant’s Metaphysical Exposition Revisited”, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 97(4): 416–457. doi:10.1515/agph-2015-0017
  • Mohr, Georg, 1998, Transzendentale Ästhetik, § 4–8, Vol. Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
  • Naragon, Steve, 1990, “Kant on Descartes and the Brutes”, Kant-Studien, 81(1): 1–23.
  • Newton, Alexandra, 2016, “Non-Conceptualism and Knowledge in Lucy Allais’s Manifest Reality”, Kantian Review, 21(2): 273–282.
  • Oittinen, V., 2009, “Linné zwischen Wolff und Kant. Zu einigen Kantischen Motiven in Linnés Biologischer Klassifikation”, in Kants Philosophie der Natur, E O Onnasch (ed.), Berlin: de Gruyter, 51–77.
  • Okrent, Mark, 2006, “Acquaintance and Cognition”, in Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant’s Critical Philosophy, Rebecca Kukla (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 85–108. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511498220.004
  • –––, 2007, Rational Animals: The Teleological Roots of Intentionality, Ohio University Press.
  • Onof, Christian, and Dennis Schulting, 2014, “Kant, Kästner and the Distinction Between Metaphysical and Geometric Space”, Kantian Review, 19(2): 285–304.
  • –––, 2015, “Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition. On the Note to B160 in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason”, The Philosophical Review, 124(1): 1–58.
  • O’Shea, James R. (ed.), 2017, Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: A Critical Guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
  • Palmquist, Stephen R., ed, 2019, Kant on Intuition: Western and Asian Perspectives on Transcendental Idealism, London: Routledge.
  • Parsons, Charles, 1964, “Infinity and Kant’s Conception of the ‘Possibility of Experience’”, The Philosophical Review, 73(2): 182–197.
  • –––, 1992a, “Kant’s Philosophy of Arithmetic, with Postscript”, in Posy 1992: 43–79.
  • –––, 1992b, “The Transcendental Aesthetic”, in The Cambridge Companion to Kant, Paul Guyer (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 62–100. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521365872
  • Pasternack, Lawrence, 2014, “Kant on Opinion: Assent, Hypothesis, and the Norms of General Applied Logic”, Kant-Studien, 105(1): 41–82. doi:10.1515/kant-2014-0003
  • Paton, H. J., 1936, Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience, Vol. 1. London: G. Allen & Unwin, Ltd.
  • –––, 1947, The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy, London: Hutchinson & Company.
  • Peacocke, Christopher, 1992, A Study of Concepts, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2009, “Objectivity”, Mind, 118(471): 739–769.
  • Pendlebury, Michael, 1990, “Sense Experiences and Their Contents: A Defence of the Propositional Account”, Inquiry, 33(2): 215–230.
  • –––, 1994, “Content and Causation in Perception”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54(4): 767–785.
  • –––, 1995, “Making Sense of Kant’s Schematism”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55(4): 777–797.
  • –––, 1996, “The Role of Imagination in Perception”, South African Journal of Philosophy, 15(4): 133–138.
  • –––, 2017, “A Kantian Account of Animal Cognition”, The Philosophical Forum, 48(4): 369–393. doi:10.1111/phil.12171
  • Pereboom, Derk, 1988, “Kant on Intentionality”, Synthese, 77(3): 321–352.
  • –––, 1995, “Self-Understanding in Kant’s Transcendental Deduction”, Synthese, 103(1): 1–42.
  • –––, 2006, “Kant’s Metaphysical and Transcendental Deductions”, in A Companion to Kant, Graham Bird (ed.), Blackwell Publishing, 154–168.
  • –––, 2009 [2019], “Kant’s Transcendental Arguments”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). url = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/kant-transcendental/>
  • Pippin, Robert B., 1982, Kant’s Theory of Form: An Essay on the Critique of Pure Reason, New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • –––, 1987, “Kant on the Spontaneity of Mind”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17(2): 449–475.
  • –––, 1989, Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2005, “Concept and Intuition. On Distinguishability and Separability”, Hegel-Studien, 39: 25–39.
  • Posy, Carl J. (ed.), 1992, Kant’s Philosophy of Mathematics: Modern Essays, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. (Scholar)
  • Prichard, Harold Arthur, 1909, Kant’s Theory of Knowledge, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Proops, Ian, 2005, “Kant’s Conception of Analytic Judgment”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(3): 588–612.
  • Pryor, James, 2005, “There Is Immediate Justification”, In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, edited by Matthias Steup and Ernest Sosa, 181–202. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Redding, Paul, 2007, Analytic Philosophy and the Return of Hegelian Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Risjord, Mark, 2006, “Evolution and the Kantian Worldview”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 44 (S1): 72–84.
  • Rives, Bradley, 2010, “Concepts and Perceptual Belief: How (Not) to Defend Recognitional Concepts”, Acta Analytica, 25(4): 369–391.
  • Roche, Andrew F., 2010, “Kant’s Principle of Sense”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 18(4): 663–691.
  • –––, 2011, “Allais on Transcendental Idealism”, Kantian Review, 16(3): 351–374.
  • –––, 2018, “Kant’s Transcendental Deduction and the Unity of Space and Time”, Kantian Review, 23(1): 41–64. (Scholar)
  • Rohs, Peter, 2001, “Bezieht sich nach Kant die Anschauung unmittelbar auf Gegenstände”, in Gerhardt et al. 2001: 214–228. doi:10.1515/9783110874129.584
  • Rosenberg, Jay F., 2005, Accessing Kant: A Relaxed Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Russell, Bertrand, 1913, The Problems of Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Sá Pereira, Roberto Horácio de, 2013, “What Is Nonconceptualism in Kant’s Philosophy”, Philosophical Studies, 164(1): 233–254.
  • –––, 2016a, “A Nonconceptualist Reading of the B-Deduction”, Philos Stud,
  • –––, 2016b, “Combining the Representational and the Relational View”, Philos Stud,
  • Schafer, Karl, forthcoming-a, “Kant’s Conception of Cognition and Our Knowledge of Things-in-Themselves”, in The Sensible and Intelligible Worlds: New Essays on Kant’s Metaphysics and Epistemology, Karl Schafer and Nicholas Stang (eds). New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, forthcoming-b, “Practical Cognition and Knowledge of Things-in-Themselves”, in The Idea of Freedom: New Essays on the Kantian Theory of Freedom, Dai Heide and Evan Tiffany (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Schulting, Dennis, 2012, “Kant, Non-Conceptual Content and the ‘Second Step’ of the B-Deduction”, Kant Studies Online, 51–92.
  • –––, 2015, “Probleme des,kantianischen‘ Nonkonzeptualismus im Hinblick auf die B-Deduktion”, Kant-Studien, 106(4).
  • ––– (ed.), 2016, Kantian Nonconceptualism, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Searle, John R., 1983, Intentionality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sedgwick, Sally, 1997, “McDowell’s Hegelianism”, European Journal of Philosophy, 5(1): 21–38.
  • Sellars, Wilfrid, 1956, “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind”, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1: 253–329.
  • –––, 1963, Science, Perception, and Reality, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
  • –––, 1968, Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes, London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.
  • –––, 1978, “The Role of the Imagination in Kant’s Theory of Experience”, in Kant’s Transcendental Metaphysics, Jeffrey F. Sicha (ed.), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company, 419–430.
  • Shabel, Lisa, 2003, “Reflections on Kant’s Concept (and Intuition) of Space”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 34(1): 45–457.
  • –––, 2004, “Kant’s ‘Argument from Geometry’”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 42(2): 195–215.
  • –––, 2010, “The Transcendental Aesthetic”, in Guyer 2010b: 93–117.
  • –––, 2013, “Kant’s Philosophy of Mathematics”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N Zalta.
  • –––, 2017, “Kant’s Mathematical Principles of Pure Understanding”, in O’Shea 2017: 163–183.
  • Shaddock, Justin B., 2014, “Kant and the Most Difficult Thing That Could Ever Be Undertaken on Behalf of Metaphysics”, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 31(1): 41–58.
  • Siegel, Susanna, 2005 [2010], “The Contents of Perception”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). url = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/perception-contents/>
  • –––, 2011, The Contents of Visual Experience, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Smit, Houston, 2000, “Kant on Marks and the Immediacy of Intuition”, The Philosophical Review, 109(2): 235–266.
  • –––, 2009, “Kant on Apriority and the Spontaneity of Cognition”, in Metaphysics and the Good: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Adams, Samuel Newlands and Larry M. Jorgensen (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 188–251.
  • Stang, Nicholas F. 2016a, Kant’s Modal Metaphysics, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2016b, “Kant’s Transcendental Idealism”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by N. Zalta Edward.
  • –––, 2018, “Kant’s Schematism of the Categories: An Interpretation and Defense”,
  • Stephenson, Andrew, 2015, “Kant on the Object-Dependence of Intuition and Hallucination”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 65(260): 486–508.
  • –––, 2017, “Imagination and Inner Intuition”, in Gomes and Stephenson 2017: 104–123.
  • Stevenson, Leslie, 2003, “Opinion, Belief or Faith, and Knowledge”, Kantian Review, 7(1): 72–101.
  • Strawson, Peter Frederick, 1959, Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics, London: Routledge.
  • –––, 1966, The Bounds of Sense, London: Routledge.
  • –––, 1970, “Imagination and Perception”, in Experience and Theory, Lawrence Foster and Joe William Swanson (eds), Amherst, MA: University of Massachusets Press.
  • Thomas, Alan, 1997, “Kant, Mcdowell and the Theory of Consciousness”, European Journal of Philosophy, 5(3): 283–305.
  • Tolley, Clinton, 2011, “Kant on the Content of Cognition”, European Journal of Philosophy, 22(2): 200–228.
  • –––, 2013, “The Non-Conceptuality of the Content of Intuitions: A New Approach”, Kantian Review, 18(1): 107–136.
  • –––, 2016a, “Between ‘Perception’ and Understanding, from Leibniz to Kant”, Estudos Kantianos, 4(2): 71–98. [Tolley 2016a available online]
  • –––, 2016b, “The Relation Between Ontology and Logic in Kant”, International Yearbook for German Idealism, 12: 75–98.
  • –––, 2017, “Kant on the Place of Cognition in the Progression of Our Representations”, Synthese, 1–30. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1625-3
  • –––, 2019, “Kant on the Role of the Imagination (and Images) in the Transition from Intuition to Experience”, in The Imagination in German Idealism and Romanticism, Gerad Gentry and Konstantin Pollok (eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 27–47.
  • Tomaszewska, Anna, 2014, The Contents of Perceptual Experience: A Kantian Perspective, Berlin: De Gruyter.
  • Tonelli, Giorgio, 1963, “Die Umwälzung von 1769 Bei Kant”, Kant-Studien, 54(4): 369–375.
  • Tracz, Brian, forthcoming, “Imagination and the Distinction Between Image and Intuition in Kant”, Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Philosophy. (Scholar)
  • Van Cleve, James, 1999, Problems from Kant, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Vanzo, Alberto, 2017, “Kant and Abstractionism About Concept Formation”, in The Problem of Universals in Early Modern Philosophy, Stefano Di Bella and Tad M. Schmaltz (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 305–323.
  • –––, 2018, “Leibniz on Innate Ideas and Kant on the Origin of the Categories”, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 100(1): 19–45.
  • Watkins, Eric, 2008, “Kant and the Myth of the Given”, Inquiry, 51(5): 512–531.
  • –––, 2012, “Kant, Sellars, and the Myth of the Given”, The Philosophical Forum, 43(3): 311–326.
  • Watkins, Eric and Marcus Willaschek. 2017a, “Givenness and Cognition: Reply to Grüne and Chignell”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 55(1): 143–152. doi:10.1353/hph.2017.0006
  • –––, 2017b, “Kant’s Account of Cognition”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 55(1): 83–112. doi:10.1353/hph.2017.0003
  • Waxman, Wayne, 1991, Kant’s Model of the Mind: A New Interpretation of Transcendental Idealism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2014, Kant’s Anatomy of the Intelligent Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Wenzel, Christian Helmut, 2005, “Spielen nach Kant die Kategorien schon bei der Wahrnehmung eine Rolle? Peter Rohs und John McDowell”, Kant-Studien, 96(4): 407–426.
  • Willaschek, Marcus, 1997, “Der Transzendentale Idealismus und die Idealität von Raum und Zeit”, Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 51(4): 537–564.
  • –––, 2006, “Die „Spontaneität des Erkenntnisses“. Über die Abhängigkeit der „Transzendentalen Analytik“ von der Auflösung der Dritten Antinomie”, in Metaphysik und Kritik: Interpretationen zur “Transzendentalen Dialektik” der “Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Jiři Chotaš, Jindřich Karásek, and Jürgen Stolzenberg (eds), Würzberg: Konigshausen & Neumann, 165–183.
  • –––, 2015, “The Sensibility of Human Intuition. Kant’s Causal Condition on Accounts of Representation”, in Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, Rainer Enskat (eds), Dordrecht: De Gruyter, 129–150.
  • Willaschek, Marcus and Eric Watkins, 2017, “Kant on Cognition and Knowledge”, Synthese, 1–19. doi:10.1007/s11229-017-1624-4
  • Williams, Jessica J., 2012, “How Conceptually Guided Are Kantian Intuitions”, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 29(1): 57–78.
  • –––, 2018, “Kant on the Original Synthesis of Understanding and Sensibility”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 26(1): 66–86. doi:10.1080/09608788.2017.1334189
  • Wilson, Kirk Dallas, 1975, “Kant on Intuition”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 25(100): 247–265.
  • Winkler, Kenneth P., 2010, “Kant, the Empiricists, and the Enterprise of Deduction”, in Guyer 2010b: 41–72.
  • Young, J Michael, 1988, “Kant’s View of Imagination”, Kant-Studien, 79(1–4): 140–164.
  • –––, 1992, “Construction, Schematism, and Imagination”, in Posy 1992: 159–175.
  • Zuckert, Rachel, 2007, Kant on Beauty and Biology: An Interpretation of the ‘Critique of Judgment, Cambridge University Press.

Generated Sun Aug 2 18:09:07 2020