Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Kant’s Theory of Judgment" by Robert Hanna
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
Internal references to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason contain page numbers from both the A (1781) and B (1787) German editions. All other internal references to Kant’s writings are cited using the relevant volume and page number from the standard “Akademie” edition of Kant’s works: Kants Gesammelte Schriften, edited by the Königlich Preussischen (now Deutschen) Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin: G. Reimer [now de Gruyter], 1902–).
- Abela, P., 2002, Kant’s Empirical Realism, Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Allais, L., 2009, “Non-Conceptual Content and the Representation of Space,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 47: 383–413. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, Manifest Reality: Kant’s Idealism and His Realism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “ Conceptualism and Nonconceptualism in Kant: A Survey of the Recent Debate,” in D. Schulting (ed.), Kantian Nonconceptualism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 1–25. (Scholar)
- Anderson, R.L., 2001, “Synthesis, Cognitive Normativity, and the Meaning of Kant’s Question ‘How are synthetic cognitions a priori possible’” European Journal of Philosophy, 9: 275–305. (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, “It Adds Up After All: Kant’s Philosophy of Arithmetic in Light of the Traditional Logic,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69: 501–540. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “The Wolffian Paradigm and its Discontents: Kant’s Containment Definition of Analyticity in Historical Context,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 87: 22–74. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, The Poverty of Conceptual Truth: Kant’s Analytic/Synthetic Distinction and the Limits of Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Arnaud, A. & Nicole, P. N., 1996, Logic or the Art of Thinking, Trans. J.V. Buroker, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Bauer, N., 2012, “A Peculiar Intuition: Kant’s Conceptualist Account of Perception,” Inquiry, 55: 215–237. (Scholar)
- Bell, D., 1979, Frege’s Theory of Judgement, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, D., 1987, “The Art of Judgement,” Mind, 96: 221–244. (Scholar)
- Benacerraf, P., 1965, “What Numbers Could Not Be,”Philosophical Review, 74: 47–73. (Scholar)
- –––, 1981, “Frege: the Last Logicist,” in P. French, et al (eds.), The Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 17–35. (Scholar)
- Bermúdez, J., 2003, Thinking without Words, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Bermúdez, J. & Cahen, A., 2015, “Nonconceptual Mental Content,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/content-nonconceptual/>. (Scholar)
- Bolzano, B., 1972, Theory of Science, trans. R. George, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. (Scholar)
- BonJour, L., 1998, In Defense of Pure Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Boole, G., 1854, An Investigation of the Laws of Thought, Cambridge: Macmillan. (Scholar)
- Boolos, G., 1998, Logic, Logic, and Logic, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Boolos, G., and Jeffrey, R., 1989, Computability and Logic, 3rd edn., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Bowman, B., 2011, “A Conceptualist Reply to Hanna’s Kantian Non-Conceptualism,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19: 417–446. (Scholar)
- Brandt, R., 1995, The Table of Judgments: Critique of Pure Reason A67–76; B92–101, trans. E. Watkins, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview. (Scholar)
- Breitenbach, A., 2015, “Beauty in Proofs: Kant on Aesthetics in Mathematics,” European Journal of Philosophy, 23: 955–977. (Scholar)
- Chignell, A., 2007a, “Belief in Kant,” Philosophical Review, 116: 323–360. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007b, “Kant’s Concepts of Justification,” Noûs, 41: 33–63. (Scholar)
- Chomsky, N., 1975, Reflections on Language, New York: Pantheon. (Scholar)
- Cook, V., and Newson, M., 1996, Chomsky’s Universal Grammar: An Introduction, 2nd edn., Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Denyer, N., 1992, “Pure Second-Order Logic,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 33: 220–224. (Scholar)
- Frege, G., 1953, Foundations of Arithmetic, trans. J.L. Austin, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1972, Conceptual Notation and Related Articles, trans. T.W. Bynum, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1979, “Logic (1897),”, inn G. FregeFrege: Posthumous Writings, trans. P. Long et al., Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp. 127–151. (Scholar)
- –––, 1984, “Thoughts,”, in G. Frege, Frege: Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy, trans. M. Black, et al., Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp. 351–372. (Scholar)
- Friedman, M., 1992, Kant and the Exact Sciences, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Gardner, S., 2013, “Transcendental Philosophy and the Given,” in J. Schear (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, London: Routledge, pp. 110–142. (Scholar)
- Ginsborg, H., 2006, “Empirical Concepts and the Content of Experience,”, European Journal of Philosophy, 14: 349–372. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, “Was Kant a Nonconceptualist?,”, Philosophical Studies, 137: 65–77. (Scholar)
- Golob, S., 2012, “Kant on Intentionality, Magnitude, and the Unity of Perception,” European Journal of Philosophy, 22: 505–528 (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “Why the Transcendental Deduction Is Compatible With Nonconceptualism,” in D. Schulting (ed.), Kantian Nonconceptualism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 27–52. (Scholar)
- –––, forthcoming, “Kant as Both Conceptualist and Nonconceptualist,” Kantian Review. (Scholar)
- Griffith, A., 2010, “Perception and the Categories: A Conceptualist Reading of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason,” European Journal of Philosophy, 20: 193–222. (Scholar)
- Grüne, S., 2009, Blinde Anschauung: Die Rolle von Begriffen in Kants Theorie sinnlicher Synthesis, Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Is There a Gap in Kant’s B Deduction?,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19: 465–490. (Scholar)
- Hanna, R., 2001, Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Kant and Nonconceptual Content,” European Journal of Philosophy, 13: 247–290. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006a, Rationality and Logic, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006b, Kant, Science, and Human Nature, Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Kant’s Non-Conceptualism, Rogue Objects, and the Gap in the B Deduction,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19: 399–415. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Kant, Hegel, and the Fate of Non-Conceptual Content,” Hegel Society of Great Britain Bulletin, 65 (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Forward to Idealism: On Eckart Förster’s The Twenty-Five Years of Philosophy,” Kantian Review, 18(2): 301-315. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, Cognition, Content, and the A Priori: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind and Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016a, “Directions in Space, Nonconceptual Form, and the Foundations of Transcendental Idealism,” in D. Schulting (ed.), Kantian Nonconceptualism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 99–115. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016b, “Kantian Madness: Blind Intuitions, Essentially Rogue Objects, Nomological Deviance, and Categorial Anarchy,” Contemporary Studies in Kantian Philosophy, 1: 44–64. (Scholar)
- Hazen, A., 1999, “Logic and Analyticity,” in A.C. Varzi (ed.), The Nature of Logic, Stanford, CA: CSLI, pp. 79–110. (Scholar)
- Heidegger, M., 1990, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. R. Taft, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. (Scholar)
- Hylton, P., 1984, “The Nature of the Proposition and the Revolt against Idealism,” in R. Rorty (ed.), Philosophy in History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 375–397. (Scholar)
- Kain, P., 2010, “Practical Cognition, Intuition, and the Fact of Reason,” in B. Lipscomb and J. Krueger (eds.), Kant’s Moral Metaphysics: God, Freedom, and Immortality, Berlin: DeGruyter, pp. 211–230. (Scholar)
- Kitcher, P., 1990, Kant’s Transcendental Psychology, New York: Oxford. (Scholar)
- Laiho, H., 2012, Perception in Kant’s Model of Experience, PhD dissertation, Turku: University of Turku. (Scholar)
- Land, T., 2011, “Kantian Conceptualism,” in G. Abel et al. (eds.), Rethinking Epistemology, Berlin: DeGruyter, pp. 197–239. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Nonconceptualist Readings of Kant and the Transcendental Deduction,”, Kantian Review, 20: 25–51. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “Moderate Conceptualism and Spatial Representation,” in D. Schulting (ed.), Kantian Nonconceptualism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 145–170. (Scholar)
- Landy, D., 2009, “Inferentialism and the Transcendental Deduction,” Kantian Review, 14: 1–30. (Scholar)
- Leech, J., 2010, “Kant’s Modalities of Judgment,” European Journal of Philosophy, 20: 260–284. (Scholar)
- Linsky, L., 1992, “The Problem of the Unity of the Proposition,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 30: 243–273. (Scholar)
- Longuenesse, B., 1998, Kant and the Capacity to Judge, trans. C. Wolfe, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- MacFarlane, J., 2002, “Kant, Frege, and the Logic in Logicism,” Philosophical Review, 111: 25–65. (Scholar)
- Martin, W., 2006, Theories of Judgment, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- McDowell, J., 1994, Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “Avoiding the Myth of the Given,” in J. McDowell, Having the World in View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 256–272. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “The Myth of the Mind as Detached,” in J. Schear (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, London: Routledge, pp. 41–58. (Scholar)
- McLear, C., 2011, “Kant on Animal Consciousness,” Philosophers' Imprint, 11: 1–16. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “The Kantian (Non)Conceptualism Debate,” Philosophy Compass, 9: 769–790. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Two Kinds of Unity in the Critique of Pure Reason,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 53: 79–110. (Scholar)
- Newton, A., 2015, “Kant on the Logical Origin of Concepts,” European Journal of Philosophy, 23: 456–484. (Scholar)
- Onof, C., 2016,“Is There Room For Nonconceptual Content in Kant’s Critical Philosophy?,” in D. Schulting (ed.), Kantian Nonconceptualism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 199–226. (Scholar)
- Parsons, C., “Kant’s Philosophy of Arithmetic,” in C. Parsons, Mathematics in Philosophy, New York: Cornell University Press, pp. 110–149. (Scholar)
- Pasternack, L., 2011, “The Development and Scope of Kantian Belief: The Highest Good, The Practical Postulates, and the Fact of Reason,” Kant-Studien, 102: 290–315. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Kant on Opinion, Hypothesis, and the Norms of Applied Logic,” Kant-Studien, 105: 41–82. (Scholar)
- Pippin, R., 2013, “What is ‘Conceptual Activity’?,” in J. Schear (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, London: Routledge, pp. 91–109. (Scholar)
- Priest, G., 2001, An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Quine, W.V.O., 1961, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, 2nd edn., New York: Harper and Row, pp. 20–46. (Scholar)
- Reich, K., 1992, The Completeness of Kant’s Table of Judgments, trans. J. Kneller and M. Losonsky, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. (Scholar)
- Rödl, S., 2006, “Logical Form as a Relation to the Object,” Philosophical Topics, 34: 345–369. (Scholar)
- Rohs, P., 2001, “Bezieht sich nach Kant die Anschauung unmittelbar auf Gegenstände?,” Akte des IX. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, vol. II, Berlin: De Gruyter. (Scholar)
- Russell, B., 1966, “On the Nature of Truth and Falsehood,” in B. Russell, Philosophical Essays, London: Allen & Unwin, pp. 147–159. (Scholar)
- Schulting, D., 2012, “Kant, Non-Conceptual Content, and the ‘Second Step’ of the B Deduction,” Kant Studies Online, 51–92. (Scholar)
- Shabel, L., 2003, Mathematics in Kant’s Critical Philosophy, London: Routledge. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “Kant’s Philosophy of Mathematics,” in P. Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant, 2nd edn., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Sellars, W., 1963, “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,” in W. Sellars, Science, Perception, and Reality, New York: Humanities Press, pp. 127–196. (Scholar)
- –––, 1968, Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Scholar)
- Soboleva, M., forthcoming, “How We Read Kant: An Empiricist and a Transcendental Reading of Kant’s Theory of Experience,” Philosophia, first online 22 July 2017, doi:10.1007/s11406-017-9878-0 (Scholar)
- Stevenson, L., 2003, “Opinion, Belief or Faith, and Knowledge,” Kantian Review, 7: 72–101. (Scholar)
- Strawson, P.F., 1966, The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, London: Methuen. (Scholar)
- Thompson, M., 1972, “Singular Terms and Intuitions in Kant's Epistemology,” The Review of Metaphysics, 26(2): 314–343. (Scholar)
- Tolley, C., 2012, “The Generality of Kant’s Transcendental Logic,” Journal of the History of Philosophy. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “The Non-Conceptuality of the Content of Intuitions: A New Approach,” Kantian Review, 18: 107–136. (Scholar)
- Van Cleve, J., 2012, “Defining and Defending Nonconceptual Contents and States,” Philosophical Perspectives, 26: 411–430. (Scholar)
- Von Humboldt, W., 1988, On Language, trans. P. Heath, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Waxman, W., 1991, Kant’s Model of the Mind, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Wenzel, C., 2005, “Spielen nach Kant die Kategorien schon bei der Wahrnehmung eine Rolle?,” Kant-Studien, 96: 407–426. (Scholar)
- Whitehead, A.N., and Russell, B., 1962, Principia Mathematica to *56, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Williams, J., 2012, “How Conceptually-Guided are Kantian Intuitions?,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 29: 57–78. (Scholar)
- Wittgenstein, L., 1922, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. C.K. Ogden, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Scholar)
- –––, 1953, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe, New York: Macmillan. (Scholar)
- Wolff, M., 1995, Die Vollständigkeit der kantischen Urteilstafel, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. (Scholar)