Linked bibliography for the SEP article "The Language of Thought Hypothesis" by Michael Rescorla
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Arjo, Dennis, 1996, “Sticking Up for Oedipus: Fodor on Intentional Generalizations and Broad Content”, Mind & Language, 11(3): 231–245. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.1996.tb00044.x (Scholar)
- Armstrong, D. M., 1973, Belief Truth and Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511570827 (Scholar)
- Atherton, Margaret and Robert Schwartz, 1974, “Linguistic Innateness and Its Evidence”:, Journal of Philosophy, 71(6): 155–168. doi:10.2307/2024657 (Scholar)
- Aydede, Murat, 1995, “Connectionism and Language of Thought”, CSLI Technical Report 195, Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997a, “Language of Thought: The Connectionist Contribution”, Minds and Machines, 7(1): 57–101. doi:10.1023/a:1008203301671 (Scholar)
- –––, 1997b, “Has Fodor Really Changed His Mind on Narrow Content?”, Mind & Language, 12(3–4): 422–458. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.1997.tb00082.x (Scholar)
- –––, 1998, “Fodor on Concepts and Frege Puzzles”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79(4): 289–294. doi:10.1111/1468-0114.00063 (Scholar)
- –––, 2000, “On the Type/Token Relation of Mental Representations”, Facta Philosophica, 2: 23–49. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Computation and Functionalism: Syntactic Theory of Mind Revisited”, in Turkish Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, Gürol Irzik and Güven Güzeldere (eds.), (Boston Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 244), Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag, 177–204. doi:10.1007/1-4020-3333-8_13 (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “The Language of Thought Hypothesis”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition), Edward Zalta (ed.). URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/language-thought/>. (Scholar)
- Aydede, Murat and Güven Güzeldere, 2005, “Cognitive Architecture, Concepts, and Introspection: An Information-Theoretic Solution to the Problem of Phenomenal Consciousness”, Noûs, 39(2): 197–255. doi:10.1111/j.0029-4624.2005.00500.x (Scholar)
- Aydede, Murat and Philip Robbins, 2001, “Are Frege Cases Exceptions to Intentional Generalizations?”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31(1): 1–22. doi:10.1080/00455091.2001.10717558 (Scholar)
- Bach, Kent, 1987, “Review: Spreading the Word”, The Philosophical Review, 96(1): 120–123. doi:10.2307/2185336 (Scholar)
- Barsalou, Lawrence W., 1999, “Perceptual Symbol
Systems”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4):
577–660. doi:10.1017/s0140525x99002149 (Scholar)
- Bechtel, William and Adele Abrahamsen, 2002, Connectionism and the Mind: Parallel Processing, Dynamics and Evolution in Networks, second edition, Malden, MA: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Beck, Jacob, 2017, “Can Bootstrapping Explain Concept Learning?”, Cognition, 158: 110–121. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2016.10.017 (Scholar)
- Bermúdez, José Luis, 2010, Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Science of the Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Blackburn, Simon, 1984, Spreading the Word, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Block, Ned, 1983, “Mental Pictures and Cognitive Science”, The Philosophical Review, 92(4): 499–451. doi:10.2307/2184879 (Scholar)
- –––, 1987, “Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology”, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10: 615–678. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00558.x (Scholar)
- –––, 1990, “Can the Mind Change the World?”, in Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam, George Boolos (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2023, The Border Between Seeing and Thinking, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Blumson, Ben, 2012, “Mental Maps”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(2): 413–434. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2011.00499.x (Scholar)
- Braddon-Mitchell, David and John Fitzpatrick, 1990, “Explanation and the Language of Thought”, Synthese, 83(1): 3–29. doi: 10.1007/bf00413686 (Scholar)
- Braddon-Mitchell, David and Frank Jackson, 2007, Philosophy of
Mind and Cognition, second edition, Cambridge: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Brentano, Franz, 1874 [1973], Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, 1924 edition), Antos C. Rancurello, D.B. Terrell, and Linda McAlister (trans.), London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Scholar)
- Burge, Tyler, 2007, Foundations of Mind, (Philosophical Essays, 2), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, Origins of Objectivity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199581405.001.0001 (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Iconic Representation: Maps, Pictures, and Perception”, in The Map and the Territory: Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought, and Reality, Shyam Wuppuluri and Francisco Antonio Doria (eds.), Cham: Springer International Publishing, 79–100. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-72478-2_5 (Scholar)
- –––, 2022, Perception: First Form of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Camp, Elisabeth, 2009, “A Language of Baboon Thought?”, in Lurz 2009: 108–127. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511819001.007">10.1017/cbo9780511819001.007 (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Why Maps Are Not Propositional”, in Non-Propositional Intentionality, Alex Grzankowski and Michelle Montague (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198732570.003.0002 (Scholar)
- Carey, Susan, 2009, The Origin of Concepts, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195367638.001.0001 (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “On Learning New Primitives in the Language of Thought: Reply to Rey”, Mind and Language, 29(2): 133–166. doi:10.1111/mila.12045 (Scholar)
- Casati, Roberto and Achille C. Varzi, 1999, Parts and Places: The Structures of Spatial Representation, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Chalmers, David J., 1990, “Syntactic Transformations on Distributed Representations”, Connection Science, 2(1–2): 53–62. doi:10.1080/09540099008915662 (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, “Connectionism and Compositionality: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn Were Wrong”, Philosophical Psychology, 6(3): 305–319. doi:10.1080/09515089308573094 (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “The Varieties of Computation: A Reply”, Journal of Cognitive Science, 13(3): 211–248. doi:10.17791/jcs.2012.13.3.211 (Scholar)
- Chomsky, Noam, 1965, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Churchland, Patricia S., 1986, Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of Mind-Brain, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Churchland, Patricia S. and Terrence J. Sejnowski, 1989, “Neural Representation and Neural Computation”, in Neural Connections, Neural Computation, Lynn Nadel, Lynn A. Cooper, Peter W. Culicover, and Robert M. Harnish, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Churchland, Paul M., 1990, A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Churchland, Paul M., and Patricia S. Churchland, 1990, “Could a Machine Think?”, Scientific American, 262(1): 32–37. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0190-32 (Scholar)
- Clark, Andy, 1991, “Systematicity, Structured Representations and Cognitive Architecture: A Reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn”, in Horgan and Tienson 1991: 198–218. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-3524-5_9">10.1007/978-94-011-3524-5_9 (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, Mindware: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Cognitive Science, second edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Cowie, Fiona, 1999, What’s Within? Nativism
Reconsidered, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195159783.001.0001 (Scholar)
- Cummins, Robert, 1989, Meaning and Mental Representation, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Dennett, Daniel C., 1977 [1981], “Critical Noticw: Review of
The Language of Thought by Jerry Fodor”, Mind, 86(342):
265–280. Reprinted as “A Cure for the Common Code”,
in Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXXVI.342.265 (Scholar)
- –––, 1991, “Mother Nature Versus the Walking Encyclopedia: A Western Drama”, in Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, W. Ramsey, S. Stich, and D. Rumelhart, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. [available online] (Scholar)
- Devitt, Michael, 1995, Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511609190 (Scholar)
- Dretske, Fred, 1981, Knowledge and the Flow of Information, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1988. Explaining Behavior, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Egan, Frances, 1992, “Individualism, Computation, and Perceptual Content”, Mind, 101(403): 443–459. doi:10.1093/mind/101.403.443 (Scholar)
- Elman, Jeffrey L., 1989, “Structured Representations and
Connectionist Models”, in Proceedings of the Eleventh Annual
Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Mahwah: Laurence
Erlbaum Associates. (Scholar)
- Field, Hartry, 2001, Truth and the Absence of Fact, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199242895.001.0001 (Scholar)
- Figdor, Carrie, 2009, “Semantic Externalism and the Mechanics of Thought”, Minds and Machines, 19(1): 1–24. doi:10.1007/s11023-008-9114-6 (Scholar)
- Fodor, Jerry A., 1975, The Language of Thought, New York: Thomas Y. Crowell. (Scholar)
- –––, 1981, Representations, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1987, Psychosemantics, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1990, A Theory of Content and Other Essays, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1991, “Replies”, in Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, Barry M. Loewer and Georges Rey (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, The Elm and the Expert, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1998, Concepts: Where Cognitive Science
Went Wrong, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/0198236360.001.0001 (Scholar)
- –––, 2001, “Doing without What’s within: Fiona Cowie’s Critique of Nativism”, Mind, 110(437): 99–148. doi:10.1093/mind/110.437.99 (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, Hume Variations, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199287338.001.0001 (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199548774.001.0001 (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Woof, Woof. Review of The
Origin of Concepts by Susan Carey”, The Times Literary
Supplement, October 8: pp. 7–8. (Scholar)
- Fodor, Jerry and Brian P. McLaughlin, 1990, “Connectionism and the Problem of Systematicity: Why Smolensky’s Solution Doesn’t Work”, Cognition, 35(2): 183–204. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(90)90014-b (Scholar)
- Fodor, Jerry A. and Zenon W. Pylyshyn, 1981, “How Direct Is Visual Perception?: Some Reflections on Gibson’s ‘Ecological Approach’”, Cognition, 9(2): 139–196. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(81)90009-3 (Scholar)
- –––, 1988, “Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis”, Cognition, 28(1–2): 3–71. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(88)90031-5 (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, Minds Without Meanings, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Frege, Gottlob, 1879 [1967], Begriffsschrift, eine der Arithmetischen Nachgebildete Formelsprache des Reinen Denkens. Translated as Concept Script, a Formal Language of Pure Thought Modeled upon that of Arithmetic in From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, J. van Heijenoort (ed.), S. Bauer-Mengelberg (trans.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1892 [1997], “On Sinn and
Bedeutung”. Reprinted in The Frege Reader,
M. Beaney (ed.), M. Black (trans.), Malden, MA: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- –––, 1918 [1997], “Thought”.
Reprinted in The Frege Reader, M. Beaney (ed.), P. Geach and
R. Stoothof (trans.), Malden, MA: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Gallistel, Charles R., 1990, The Organization of
Learning, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Gallistel, Charles R. and Adam Philip King, 2009, Memory and
the Computational Brain, Malden, MA: Wiley- Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Gallistel, C.R. and Louis D. Matzel, 2013, “The Neuroscience
of Learning: Beyond the Hebbian Synapse”, Annual Review of
Psychology, 64(1): 169–200.
doi:10.1146/annurev-psych-113011-143807 (Scholar)
- Gibson, James J., 1979, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin. (Scholar)
- Greenberg, Gabriel, 2013, “Beyond Resemblance”, Philosophical Review, 122(2): 215–287. doi:10.1215/00318108-1963716 (Scholar)
- Greenberg, Mark, 2014, “Troubles for Content I”, in
Metasemantics: New Essays on the Foundations of Meaning,
Alexis Burgess and Brett Sherman (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 147–168.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199669592.003.0006 (Scholar)
- Harman, Gilbert, 1973, Thought, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Harnad, Stevan, 1994, “Computation Is Just Interpretable Symbol Manipulation; Cognition Isn’t”, Minds and Machines, 4(4): 379–390. doi:10.1007/bf00974165 (Scholar)
- Harnish, Robert M., 2002, Minds, Brains, Computers: An Historical Introduction to the Foundations of Cognitive Science, Malden, MA: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Haugeland, John, 1985, Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press (Scholar)
- Helmholtz, Hermann von, 1867 [1925], Treatise on Physiological
Optics (Handbuch der physiologischen Optik), James P.C.
Southall, Manasha, WI: George Banta Publishing Company. (Scholar)
- Hinton, G. 1990. “Mapping Part-Whole Hierarchies into
Connectionist Networks”. Artificial Intelligence 46:
pp. 47–75. (Scholar)
- Horgan, Terence and John Tienson (eds.), 1991, Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, (Studies in Cognitive Systems 9), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-3524-5 (Scholar)
- –––, 1996, Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Hume, David, 1739 [1978], A Treatise on Human Nature, second edition, P. H. Nidditch (ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Jacobs, Lucia F and Randolf Menzel, 2014, “Navigation
Outside of the Box: What the Lab Can Learn from the Field and What the
Field Can Learn from the Lab”, Movement Ecology, 2(1):
3. doi:10.1186/2051-3933-2-3 (Scholar)
- Johnson, Kent, 2004, “On the Systematicity of Language and Thought”:, Journal of Philosophy, 101(3): 111–139. doi:10.5840/jphil2004101321 (Scholar)
- Johnson-Laird, Philip N., 2004, “The History of Mental
Models”, in Psychology of Reasoning: Theoretical and
Historical Perspectives, Ken Manktelow and Man Cheung Chung, New
York: Psychology Press. (Scholar)
- Kant, Immanuel, 1781 [1998], The Critique of Pure Reason, P. Guyer and A. Wood (eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Kaplan, David, 1989, “Demonstratives”, in Themes from Kaplan, Joseph Almog, John Perry, and Howard Wettstein (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Kazez, Jean R., 1994, “Computationalism and the Causal Role of Content”, Philosophical Studies, 75(3): 231–260. doi:10.1007/bf00989583 (Scholar)
- King, Peter, 2005, “William of Ockham: Summa
Logicae”, in Central Works of Philosophy: Ancient and
Medieval, volume 1: Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, John Shand
(ed.), Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press,
242–270. (Scholar)
- Knill, David C. and Whitman Richards (eds.), 1996, Perception as Bayesian Inference, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511984037 (Scholar)
- Knowles, Jonathan, 1998, “The Language of Thought and Natural Language Understanding”, Analysis, 58(4): 264–272. doi: 10.1093/analys/58.4.264 (Scholar)
- Kosslyn, Stephen, 1980, Image and Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Kulvicki, John, 2015, “Maps, Pictures, and Predication”, Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy, 2(7): 149–174. (Scholar)
- Laurence, Stephen and Eric Margolis, 1997, “Regress Arguments Against the Language of Thought”, Analysis, 57(1): 60–66. (Scholar)
- Loar, Brian, 1982, Mind and Meaning, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Loewer, Barry, 1997, “A Guide to Naturalizing Semantics”, in A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Bob Hale and Crispin Wright (eds.), Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Lurz, Robert W. (ed.), 2009, The Philosophy of Animal Minds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511819001 (Scholar)
- Mackintosh, Nicholas John, 2002, “Do Not Ask Whether They
Have a Cognitive Map, but How They Find Their Way about”,
Psicológica, 23(1): 165–185.
[Mackintosh 2002 available online] (Scholar)
- Mandelbaum, Eric, Yarrow Dunham, Roman Freiman, Chaz Firestone, E.
J. Green, Daniel Harris, Melissa Kibbe, Benedek Kurdi, Myrto
Mylopoulos, Joshua Sheperd, Alexis Wellwood, Nicholas Porot, and Jake
Quilty-Dunn, 2022, “Problems and Mysteries of the Many Languages
of Thought”, Cognitive Science, 46(12): e13225. (Scholar)
- Margolis, Eric, 1998, “How to Acquire a Concept”, Mind & Language, 13(3): 347–369. doi:10.1111/1468-0017.00081 (Scholar)
- Margolis, Eric and Stephen Laurence, 2011, “Learning Matters: The Role of Learning in Concept Acquisition”, Mind & Language, 26(5): 507–539. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2011.01429.x (Scholar)
- McDermott, Drew V., 2001, Mind and Mechanism, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- McLaughlin, B. P. and T. A. Warfield, 1994, “The Allure of Connectionism Reexamined”, Synthese, 101(3): 365–400. doi:10.1007/bf01063895 (Scholar)
- Marcus, G., 2001, The Algebraic Mind, Cambridge: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Millikan, Ruth Garrett, 1984, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Neander, Karen, 2017, A Mark of the Mental: In Defense of Informational Teleosemantics, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Niklasson, Lars F. and Tim Gelder, 1994, “On Being Systematically Connectionist”, Mind & Language, 9(3): 288–302. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.1994.tb00227.x (Scholar)
- Normore, Calvin, 1990, “Ockham on Mental Language”, in
The Historical Foundations of Cognitive Science, J. Smith
(ed.), Dordrecht: Kluwer. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “Burge, Descartes, and Us”, in Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge, Martin Hahn and Bjørn Ramberg, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “The End of Mental Language”, in Le Langage Mental du Moyen Âge à l’Âge Classique, J. Biard (ed.), Leuven: Peeters. (Scholar)
- O’Brien, Gerard and Jon Opie, 2006, “How Do Connectionist Networks Compute?”, Cognitive Processing, 7(1): 30–41. doi:10.1007/s10339-005-0017-7 (Scholar)
- O’Keefe, John and Lynn Nadel, 1978, The Hippocampus as a
Cognitive Map, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Ockham, William of, c. 1323 [1957], Summa Logicae,
Translated in his Philosophical Writings, A Selection,
Philotheus Boehner (ed. and trans.), London: Nelson, 1957. (Scholar)
- Panaccio, Claude, 1999 [2017], Mental Language: From Plato to
William of Ockham (Discours intérieur), Joshua P.
Hochschild and Meredith K. Ziebart (trans.), New York: Fordham
University Press. (Scholar)
- Papineau, David, 1987, Reality and Representation, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Peacocke, Christopher, 1992, A Study of Concepts, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, “Content, Computation and Externalism”, Mind & Language, 9(3): 303–335. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.1994.tb00228.x (Scholar)
- –––, 1999, “Computation as Involving Content: A Response to Egan”, Mind & Language, 14(2): 195–202. doi:10.1111/1468-0017.00109 (Scholar)
- Perry, John, 1998, “Broadening the Mind”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(1): 223–231. doi:10.2307/2653644 (Scholar)
- Piccinini, Gualtiero, 2008, “Computation without Representation”, Philosophical Studies, 137(2): 205–241. doi:10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4 (Scholar)
- Pinker, Steven, 2005, “So How Does the Mind Work?”, Mind & Language, 20(1): 1–24. doi:10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00274.x (Scholar)
- Pinker, Steven and Alan Prince, 1988, “On Language and Connectionism: Analysis of a Parallel Distributed Processing Model of Language Acquisition”, Cognition, 28(1–2): 73–193. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(88)90032-7 (Scholar)
- Polger, Thomas W., 2004, Natural Minds, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Pollack, Jordan B., 1990, “Recursive Distributed Representations”, Artificial Intelligence, 46(1–2): 77–105. doi:10.1016/0004-3702(90)90005-k (Scholar)
- Prinz, Jesse, 2002, Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and Their Perceptual Basis, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Has Mentalese Earned Its Keep?
On Jerry Fodor’s LOT 2”, Mind, 120(478):
485–501. doi:10.1093/mind/fzr025 (Scholar)
- Putnam, Hilary, 1967, “Psychophysical Predicates”, In
Art, Mind, and Religion: Proceedings of the 1965 Oberlin
Colloquium in Philosophy, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds),
Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 37–48. (Scholar)
- –––, 1988, Representation and Reality, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Pylyshyn, Zenon W., 1984, Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, Seeing and Visualizing: It’s Not What You Think, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Quilty-Dunn, Jake, Nicholas Porot, and Eric Mandelbaum, forthcoming, “The Best Game in Town: The Re-Emergence of the Language of Thought Hypothesis Across the Cognitive Sciences”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences. (Scholar)
- Quine, W. V., 1951 [1980], “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”,
The Philosophical Review, 60(1): 20–43. Reprinted in
his From a Logical Point of View, second edition, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1980, 20–46.
doi:10.2307/2181906 (Scholar)
- Ramsey, William M., 2007, Representation Reconsidered, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9780511597954 (Scholar)
- Rescorla, Michael, 2009a, “Chrysippus’ Dog as a Case
Study in Non-Linguistic Cognition”, in Lurz 2009: 52–71.
doi:10.1017/cbo9780511819001.004 (Scholar)
- –––, 2009b, “Cognitive Maps and the Language of Thought”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(2): 377–407. doi:10.1093/bjps/axp012 (Scholar)
- –––, 2009c, “Predication and Cartographic Representation”, Synthese, 169(1): 175–200. doi:10.1007/s11229-008-9343-5 (Scholar)
- –––, 2012a, “Are Computational Transitions Sensitive to Semantics?”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(4): 703–721. doi:10.1080/00048402.2011.615333 (Scholar)
- –––, 2012b, “How to Integrate
Representation into Computational Modeling, and Why We Should”,
Journal of Cognitive Science, 13(1): 1–37.
doi:10.17791/jcs.2012.13.1.1 (Scholar)
- –––, 2014a, “The Causal Relevance of Content to Computation”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1): 173–208. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00619.x (Scholar)
- –––, 2014b, “A Theory of Computational Implementation”, Synthese, 191(6): 1277–1307. doi:10.1007/s11229-013-0324-y (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Bayesian Perceptual Psychology”, in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, Mohan Matthen (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199600472.013.010 (Scholar)
- –––, 2017a, “From Ockham to
Turing—and Back Again”, in Philosophical Explorations
of the Legacy of Alan Turing, Juliet Floyd and Alisa Bokulich
(eds.), (Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 324),
Cham: Springer International Publishing, 279–304.
doi:10.1007/978-3-319-53280-6_12 (Scholar)
- –––, 2017b, “Maps in the Head?”,
The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal Minds, Kristin
Andrews and Jacob Beck (eds.), New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “Reifying
Representations”, in What Are Mental Representations?,
Tobias Schlicht, Krzysztof Doulega, and Joulia Smortchkova (eds.),
Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Rey, Georges, 2014, “Innate and Learned: Carey, Mad Dog Nativism, and the Poverty of Stimuli and Analogies (Yet Again): Innate and Learned”, Mind & Language, 29(2): 109–132. doi:10.1111/mila.12044 (Scholar)
- Rumelhart, David and James L. McClelland, 1986, “PDP Models
and General Issues in Cognitive Science”, in Rumelhart, et al.
1986: 110–146. (Scholar)
- Rumelhart, David E., James L. McClelland, and the PDP Research
Group, 1986, Parallel Distributed Processing, volume 1:
Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition: Foundations,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Russell, Bertrand, 1918–1919 [1985], “The Philosophy
of Logical Atomism: Lectures 1–2”, Monist, 28(4):
495–527, doi:10.5840/monist19182843, 29(1): 32–63,
doi:10.5840/monist191929120, 29(2): 190–222,
doi:10.5840/monist19192922, 29(3): 345–380,
doi:10.5840/monist19192937. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Logical
Atomism, David F. Pears (ed.), La Salle, IL: Open Court. (Scholar)
- Rupert, Robert D., 2008, “Frege’s Puzzle and Frege
Cases: Defending a Quasi-Syntactic Solution”, Cognitive
Systems Research, 9(1–2): 76–91.
doi:10.1016/j.cogsys.2007.07.003 (Scholar)
- Schiffer, Stephen, 1981, “Truth and the Theory of Content”, in Meaning and Understanding, Herman Parret and Jacques Bouveresse, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 204–222. (Scholar)
- Schneider, Susan, 2005, “Direct Reference, Psychological Explanation, and Frege Cases”, Mind & Language, 20(4): 423–447. doi:10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00294.x (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, The Language of Thought: A New Philosophical Direction, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Sellars, Wilfrid, 1975, “The Structure of Knowledge”, in Action, Knowledge and Reality: Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, Hector-Neri Castañeda (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 295–347. (Scholar)
- Shagrir, Oron, 2020, “In Defense of the Semantic View of Computation”, Synthese, 197(9): 4083–4108. doi:10.1007/s11229-018-01921-z (Scholar)
- Shea, Nicholas, 2016, “Representational Development Need Not Be Explicable-By-Content”, in Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence, Vincent C. Müller (ed.), Cham: Springer International Publishing, 223–240. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-26485-1_14 (Scholar)
- Sloman, Aaron, 1978, The Computer Revolution in Philosophy: Philosophy, Science and Models of the Mind, Hassocks: The Harvester Press. (Scholar)
- Smolensky, Paul, 1990, “Tensor Product Variable Binding and the Representation of Symbolic Structures in Connectionist Systems”, Artificial Intelligence, 46(1–2): 159–216. doi:10.1016/0004-3702(90)90007-m (Scholar)
- –––, 1991, “Connectionism, Constituency, and the Language of Thought”, in Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, Barry M. Loewer and Georges Rey (eds), Cambridge, MA: Blackwell. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “Constituent Structure and
Explanation in an Integrated Connectionist/Symbolic Cognitive
Architecture”, in Connectionism: Debates on Psychological
Explanation, Cynthia Macdonald and Graham Macdonald (eds),
Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Stalnaker, Robert C., 1984, Inquiry, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Stich, Stephen P., 1983, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Stojnić, Una and Ernie Lepore, 2020, “Fodor and
Demonstratives in LOT”, Theoria, 35(1):
75–92. (Scholar)
- Tarski, Alfred, 1933 [1983], “Pojęcie prawdy w
językach nauk dedukcyjnych”, Warsaw: Nakładem
Towarzystwa Naukowego Warszawskiego. Translated into German (1935) by
L. Blaustein as “Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten
Sprachen”, Studia Philosophica, 1: 261–405.
Translated into English (1983) as “The Concept of Truth in
Formalized Languages”, in Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics:
Papers from 1923 to 1938, second edition, J.H. Woodger (trans.),
John Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. (Scholar)
- Tolman, Edward C., 1948, “Cognitive Maps in Rats and Men.”, Psychological Review, 55(4): 189–208. doi:10.1037/h0061626 (Scholar)
- Touretzky, David S., 1990, “BoltzCONS: Dynamic Symbol Structures in a Connectionist Network”, Artificial Intelligence, 46(1–2): 5–46. doi:10.1016/0004-3702(90)90003-i (Scholar)
- Turing, Alan M., 1936, “On Computable Numbers, with an
Application to the Entscheidungsproblem”, Proceedings of the
London Mathematical Society, s2–42(1): 230–265.
doi:10.1112/plms/s2–42.1.230 (Scholar)
- van Gelder, Timothy, 1991, “Classical Questions, Radical Answers: Connectionism and the Structure of Mental Representations”. In Horgan and Tienson 1991: 355–381, doi:10.1007/978-94-011-3524-5_16 (Scholar)
- Wakefield, Jerome C., 2002, “Broad versus Narrow Content in the Explanation of Action: Fodor on Frege Cases”, Philosophical Psychology, 15(2): 119–133. doi:10.1080/09515080220127099 (Scholar)
- Weiner, Jan, Sara Shettleworth, Verner P. Bingman, Ken Cheng,
Susan Healy, Lucia F. Jacobs, Kathryn J. Jeffery, Hanspeter A. Mallot,
Randolf Menzel, and Nora S. Newcombe, 2011, “Animal Navigation:
A Synthesis”, in Animal Thinking, Randolf Menzel and
Julia Fischer (eds), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1921 [1922], Logisch-Philosophische
Abhandlung, in W. Ostwald (ed.), Annalen der
Naturphilosophie, 14. Translated as Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus, C.K. Ogden (trans.), London: Kegan Paul,
1922. (Scholar)
- –––, 1953, Philosophical Investigations, G.E.M. Anscombe (trans.), Oxford: Blackwell. (Scholar)