Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Philosophy of Medicine" by Julian Reiss and Rachel A. Ankeny
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Amundson, R., 2000, “Against Normal Function”, Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 31: 33–53. (Scholar)
- Anand, S. and K. Hanson, 1997, “Disability-Adjusted Life
Years: A Critical Review”, Journal of Health Economics,
16: 685–702. (Scholar)
- Andersen, H., 2012, “Mechanisms: What Are They Evidence for in Evidence-based Medicine?” Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 18(5):992-999. (Scholar)
- Ankeny, R.A., 2002, “Reduction Reconceptualized: Cystic
Fibrosis as a Paradigm Case for Molecular Medicine”, in L.S.
Parker and R.A. Ankeny (eds.), Mutating Concepts and Evolving
Disciplines: Genetics, Medicine and Society, Dordrecht: Kluwer,
127–141. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Using Cases to Establish Novel
Diagnoses: Creating Generic Facts by Making Particular Facts Travel
Together”, in P. Howlett and M.S. Morgan (eds.), How Well Do
Facts Travel? The Dissemination of Reliable Knowledge, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 252–272. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “The Overlooked Role of Cases in Casual Attribution in Medicine”, Philosophy of Science, 81: 999–1011. (Scholar)
- Ankeny, R.A. and F. Mackenzie, 2016, “Three Approaches to
Chronic Fatigue Syndrome in the United Kingdom, Australia, and Canada:
Lessons for Democratic Policy”, in S.M. Dodds and R.A. Ankeny
(eds.), Big Picture Bioethics: Democratic Policy Making in
Contested Domains, Dordrecht: Springer, forthcoming. (Scholar)
- Aronowitz, R.A., 1998, Making Sense of Illness: Science, Society and Disease, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2001, “When Do Symptoms Become a
Disease?” Annals of Internal Medicine, 134:
803–808. (Scholar)
- Barro S. and R. Marin (eds), 2002, Fuzzy Logic in
Medicine, Heidelberg: Physika-Verlag. (Scholar)
- Bekelman, J., Y. Li and C. Gross, 2003, “Scope and Impact of
Financial Conflicts of Interest in Biomedical Research”,
Journal of the American Medical Association, 289:
454–465. (Scholar)
- Bernard, C., 1865 [1957], An Introduction to the Study of
Experimental Medicine, New York: Dover. (Scholar)
- Biddle, J., 2007, “Lessons from the Vioxx Debacle: What the Privatization of Science Can Teach Us About Social Epistemology”, Social Epistemology, 21: 21–39. (Scholar)
- Bishop, M. and J.D. Trout, 2005, Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Boorse, C., 1975, “On The Distinction Between Disease and Illness”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 5: 49–68. (Scholar)
- –––, 1977, “Health as a Theoretical Concept”, Philosophy of Science, 44: 542–573. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997, “A Rebuttal on Health”, in J.M. Humber and R.F. Almeder (eds.), What is Disease?, Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, 3–143. (Scholar)
- Campaner, R., 2012, Philosophy of Medicine: Causality,
Evidence and Explanation, Bologna: Archetipo Libri. (Scholar)
- Canguilhem, G. 1991, The Normal and the Pathological, trans. C.R. Fawcett, New York: Zone Books. (Scholar)
- Caplan, A.L., 1992, “Does the Philosophy of Medicine Exist?” Theoretical Medicine, 13: 67–77. (Scholar)
- Carel, H., 2007, “Can I Be Ill and Happy?” Philosophia, 35: 95–110. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, Illness: The Cry of the Flesh, Dublin: Acumen. (Scholar)
- Cartwright, N., 1989, Nature’s Capacities and Their
Measurement, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Are RCTs the Gold Standard?” BioSocieties, 2: 11–20. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “A Philosopher’s View of
the Long Road from RCTs to Effectiveness”, The Lancet,
377: 1400–1401. (Scholar)
- Cartwright, S., 1851 [2004], “Report on the Diseases and
Physical Peculiarities of the Negro Race”, reprinted in A.L.
Caplan, J.J. McCartney, and D.A. Sisti (eds.), Health, Disease,
and Illness, Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press,
28–39. (Scholar)
- Clouser, K.D., C.M. Culver, and B. Gert, 1981, “Malady: A New Treatment of Disease”, Hastings Center Report, 11(3): 29–37. (Scholar)
- Collingwood, R., 1940, An Essay on Metaphysics, Oxford:
Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Cooper, R., 2002, “Disease”, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and the Biomedical Sciences, 33: 263–282. (Scholar)
- Cornfield, J., W. Haenszel, E.C. Hammond, A.M. Lilienfeld, M.B.
Shimkin, and E.L. Wynder, 1959, “Smoking and Lung Cancer: Recent
Evidence and A Discussion of Some Questions”, Journal of the
National Cancer Institute, 22: 173–203. (Scholar)
- Dalkey, N. and O. Helmer, 1963, “An Experimental Application
of the Delphi Method to the Use of Experts”, Management
Science, 9: 458–467. (Scholar)
- Dawes, R. and M. Mulford, 1996, “The False Consensus Effect
and Overconfidence: Flaws in Judgment or Flaws in How We Study
Judgment?” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
Processes, 65: 201–211. (Scholar)
- Degeling, C. and J. Johnson, 2013, “Evaluating Animal Models: Some Taxonomic Worries”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 38: 91–106. (Scholar)
- Dekeuwer, C., 2015, “Defining Genetic Disease”, in P.
Huneman, G. Lambert, and M. Silberstein (eds.), Classification,
Disease and Evidence: New Essays in the Philosophy of Medicine,
Dordrecht: Springer, 147–164. (Scholar)
- Dekkers, W. and M.O. Rikkert, 2006, “What is a Genetic
Cause? The Example of Alzheimer’s Disease”, Medicine,
Health Care and Philosophy, 9: 273–284. (Scholar)
- Demazeux, S. and P. Singy (eds), 2015, The DSM-5 in Perspective: Philosophical Reflections on the Psychiatric Babel, Dordrecht: Springer. (Scholar)
- De Vreese, L., E. Weber and J. Van Bouwel, 2010,
“Explanatory Pluralism in the Medical Sciences: Theory and
Practice”, Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 31:
371–390. (Scholar)
- Dodds, S.M., 2008, “Inclusion and Exclusion in Women's Access to Health and Medicine”, International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 1: 58–79. (Scholar)
- Dresser, R., 1992, “Wanted: Single, White Male for Medical Research”, Hastings Center Report, 22: 24–29. (Scholar)
- Engel, G.L., 1977, “The Need for a New Medical Model: A Challenge for Biomedicine”, Science, 196: 129–136. (Scholar)
- Engelhardt, H.T., 1974, “The Disease of Masturbation: Values
and the Concept of Disease”, Bulletin of the History of
Medicine, 48: 234–48. (Scholar)
- –––, 1975, “The Concepts of Health and Disease”, in H.T. Engelhardt Jr. and S.F. Spicker (eds), Evaluation and Explanation in the Biomedical Sciences, Dordrecht: Reidel, 125–141. (Scholar)
- –––, 1986, “Clinical Complaints and the Ens Morbi”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 11: 207–214. (Scholar)
- Epstein, S., 2007, Inclusion: The Politics of Difference in
Medical Research, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Scholar)
- Ereshefsky, M., 2009, “Defining ‘Health’ and
‘Disease’”, Studies in the History and
Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 40:
221–227. (Scholar)
- Evidence-Based Medicine Working Group, 1992, “Evidence-Based Medicine: A New Approach to Teaching the Practice of Medicine”, Journal of the American Medical Association, 268(17): 2420–2425. (Scholar)
- Fabrega, H., 1979, “The Scientific Usefulness of the Idea of
Illness”, Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 22:
545–558. (Scholar)
- FDA (U.S. Food and Drug Administration), 2009, Guidance for
Industry Patient-Reported Outcome Measures: Use in Medical Product
Development to Support Labeling Claims, Washington, DC: U.S.
Department of Health and Human Services. (Scholar)
- Fischhoff, B., 1975, “Hindsight is Not Equal to Foresight:
The Effect of Outcome Knowledge on Judgement under Uncertainty”,
Journal of Experimental Psychology, Human Perception &
Performance, 1: 288–299. (Scholar)
- Fisher, R.A., 1935, The Design of Experiments, Oxford:
Oliver & Boyd. (Scholar)
- –––, 1958, “Cancer and Smoking”,
Nature, 182: 596. (Scholar)
- Foucault, M., 1963 [1973], The Birth of the Clinic: An
Archaeology of Medical Perception, New York: Pantheon. (Scholar)
- Gaines, A.D., 1992, “From DSM-I to III-R, Voices of Self,
Mastery and the Other: A Cultural Constructivist Reading of U.S.
Psychiatric Classification”, Social Science and Medicine, 35:
3–24. (Scholar)
- Gannett, L., 1999, “What’s in a Cause? The Pragmatic
Dimensions of Genetic Explanations”, Biology and Philosophy, 14:
349–373. (Scholar)
- Gasking, D., 1955, “Causation and Recipes”, Mind, 64: 479–87. (Scholar)
- Giere, R., 1984, Understanding Scientific Reasoning, New
York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston. (Scholar)
- Gifford, F., 1990, “Genetic Traits”, Biology and Philosophy, 5: 327–47. (Scholar)
- Gigerenzer, G., 2014, Risk Savvy: How to Make Good Decisions, New York (NY), Viking Penguin. (Scholar)
- Gilliam, A., 1955, “Trends of Mortality Attributed to
Carcinoma of the Lung: Possible Effects of Faulty Certification of
Deaths Due to Other Respiratory Diseases”, Cancer, 8:
1130–1136. (Scholar)
- Gillies, D., 2011, “The Russo–Williamson Thesis and the Question of Whether Smoking Causes Heart Disease”, in P. McKay Illari, F. Russo, and J. Williamson (eds.), Causality in the Sciences, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 110–125. (Scholar)
- Glennan, S., 2002, “Rethinking Mechanistic Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, 69: S342–353. (Scholar)
- Goldberg, L., 1968, “Simple Models of Simple Processes? Some
Research on Clinical Judgments”, American Psychologist,
23: 483–496. (Scholar)
- Goosens, W., 1980, “Values, Health and Medicine”, Philosophy of Science, 47: 100–115. (Scholar)
- Gorovitz, S. and A. MacIntyre, 1976, “Toward a Theory of Medical Fallibility”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 1: 51–71. (Scholar)
- Grove, W. and P. Meehl, 1996, “Comparative Efficiency of
Informal (Subjective, Impressionistic) and Formal (Mechanical,
Algorithmic) Prediction Procedures: The Clinical-Statistical
Controversy”, Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 2:
293–323. (Scholar)
- Hare, R.M., 1986, “Health”, Journal of Medical Ethics, 12: 174–181. (Scholar)
- Harris, G., 2005, “F.D.A. Official Admits
‘Lapses’ on Vioxx”, New York Times, 2
March. (Scholar)
- Harris, H.W. and K.F. Schaffner, 1992, “Molecular Genetics, Reductionism, and Disease Concepts in Psychiatry”, Journal of Medical Philosophy, 17: 127–153. (Scholar)
- Hesslow, G., 1984, “What Is A Genetic Disease? On the Relative Importance of Causes”, in L. Nordenfelt and B.I.B. Lindahl (eds.), Health, Disease and Causal Explanation in Medicine, Doredrecht : Reidel, 183–193. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, “Do We Need A Concept of Disease?” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 14: 1–14. (Scholar)
- Hofmann, B., 2002, “On the Triad Disease, Illness, and Sickness”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 27: 651–673. (Scholar)
- Horwitz, A.V. and J.C. Wakefield, 2007, The Loss of
Sadness, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Howick, J., 2011a, “Exposing the Vanities—and a Qualified Defense—of Mechanistic Reasoning in Health Care Decision Making”, Philosophy of Science, 78: 926–940. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011b, The Philosophy of Evidence-Based Medicine, Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Huang, H. and A.D. Coker, 2010, “Examining Issues Affecting
African-American Participation in Research Studies”, Journal
of Black Studies, 40: 619–636. (Scholar)
- Hubbard, R. and E. Wald, 1999, Exploding the Gene Myth,
New York: Beacon. (Scholar)
- Hugh, T. and S. Dekker, 2009, “Hindsight Bias and Outcome
Bias in the Social Construction of Medical Negligence: A
Review”, Journal of Law and Medicine, 16:
846–857. (Scholar)
- Hunter, K.M., 1991, Doctors’ Stories: The Narrative
Structure of Medical Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University
Press. (Scholar)
- Hurwitz, B., 2006, “Form and Representation in Clinical Case
Reports”, Literature and Medicine, 25:
216–240. (Scholar)
- IARC [International Agency for Research on Cancer], 2006, IARC
Monographs on the Evaluation of Carcinogenic Risks to Humans:
Preamble, Lyon: International Agency for Research on Cancer. (Scholar)
- Illari, P., 2011, “Mechanistic evidence: Disambiguating the Russo-Williamson Thesis”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 25(2):139-157. (Scholar)
- Inborn, M. and K. Whittle, 2001, “Feminism Meets the
‘New’ Epidemiologies: Towards an Appraisal of Antifeminist
Biases in Epidemiological Research on Women’s Health”,
Social Science and Medicine, 53: 553–567. (Scholar)
- Janis, I., 1982, Groupthink: Psychological Studies of Policy
Decisions and Fiascoes, Boston: Houghton Mifflin. (Scholar)
- Jones, J. and D. Hunter, 1995, “Consensus Methods for
Medical and Health Services Research”, British Medical
Journal, 311: 376–380. (Scholar)
- Juengst, E., 2004, “FACE Facts: Why Human Genetics Will Always Provoke Bioethics”, Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 32: 267–275. (Scholar)
- Kass, L.R., 1975, “Regarding the End of Medicine and the
Pursuit of Health”, Public Interest, 40:
11–42. (Scholar)
- Kingma, E., 2007, “What Is It To Be Healthy?” Analysis, 67: 128–133. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Paracetamol, Poison and Polio:
Why Boorse’s Account of Function Fails to Distinguish Health and
Disease”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science, 61: 241–264. (Scholar)
- Kitcher, P., 1997, The Lives To Come: The Genetic Revolution
and Human Possibilities, New York: Simon & Schuster. (Scholar)
- La Caze, A., 2011, “The Role of Basic Science in Evidence-based Medicine”, Biology and Philosophy, 26(1):81-98. (Scholar)
- LaFollette, H. and N. Shanks, 1997, Brute Science: Dilemmas of Animal Experimentation, London: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Lennox, J.G., 1995, “Health as an Objective Value”, Philosophy of Medicine, 20: 499–511. (Scholar)
- Lexchin, J., 2012, “Those Who Have the Gold Make the Evidence: How the Pharmaceutical Industry Biases the Outcomes of Clinical Trials of Medications”, Science and Engineering Ethics, 18: 247–261. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012b, “Sponsorship Bias in Clinical
Research”, International Journal of Risk & Safety in
Medicine, 24: 233–242. (Scholar)
- Lippman, A., 1991, “Prenatal Genetic Testing and Screening:
Constructing Needs and Reinforcing Inequities”, American
Journal of Law and Medicine, 17: 15–50. (Scholar)
- Lloyd, E.A., 2002, “Reductionism in Medicine: Social Aspects of Health”, in M.H.V. Van Regenmortel and D.L. Hull (eds.), Promises and Limits of Reductionism in the Biomedical Sciences, New York: John Wiley & Sons, 67–82. (Scholar)
- Machamer, P., L. Darden and C. Craver, 2000, “Thinking About Mechanisms”, Philosophy of Science, 67: 1–25. (Scholar)
- Macklin, R., 1972, “Mental Health and Mental Illness: Some Problems of Definition and Concept Formation”, Philosophy of Science, 39: 341–365. (Scholar)
- Magner, L., 2002, A History of the Life Sciences, New
York: Marcel Dekker. (Scholar)
- Margolis, J., 1976, “The Concept of Disease”, The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 1: 238–255. (Scholar)
- Mathers, C., C. Stein, D. Ma Fat, C. Rao, M. Inoue, N. Tomijima,
C. Bernard, A.D. Lopez, and C.J.L. Murray, 2002, Global Burden of
Disease 2000: Version 2 Methods and Results, Geneva: World Health
Organization. (Scholar)
- McClimans, L., 2010, “Towards Self-Determination in Quality of Life Research”, Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 13: 67–76. (Scholar)
- McClimans, L. and J. Browne, 2011, “Choosing a Patient-Reported Outcome Measure”, Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 32: 47–60. (Scholar)
- Méthot, P.-O., 2011, “Research Traditions and
Evolutionary Explanations in Medicine”, Theoretical Medicine
and Bioethics, 32: 75–90. (Scholar)
- Mezzich J.E., A. Kleinman, H. Fabrega Jr., D.L. Parron (eds),
1996, Culture and Psychiatric Diagnosis: A DSM IV
Perspective, Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press. (Scholar)
- Murphy, D. and R.L. Woolfolk, 2000, “The Harmful Dysfunction Analysis of Mental Disorder”, Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 7: 241–252. (Scholar)
- Murray, C., 1994, “Quantifying the Burden of Disease: The
Technical Basis for Disability-Adjusted Life Years”,
Bulletin of the World Health Organization, 72:
429–445. (Scholar)
- –––, 1996, “Rethinking DALYs”, in C.
Murray and A. Lopez, The Global Burden of Disease: A Comprehensive
Assessment of Mortality and Disability from Diseases, Injuries, and
Risk Factors in 1990 and Projected to 2020, Boston: Harvard
University Press, 1–98. (Scholar)
- Parsons, T., 1951, The Social System, Glencoe, IL: The Free Press. (Scholar)
- Pellegrino, E.D., 1979, Humanism and the Physician, Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press. (Scholar)
- Pettit, P., 2001, “Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma”, Philosophical Issues, 11: 268–299. (Scholar)
- Prüss-Üstün, A., C. Mathers, C. Corvalán,
and A. Woodward, 2003, Introduction and Methods: Assessing the
Environmental Burden of Disease at National and Local Levels,
Geneva: World Health Organization. (Scholar)
- Rao, G., 2009, “Probability Error in Diagnosis: The
Conjunction Fallacy among Beginning Medical Students”,
Family Medicine, 41: 262–265. (Scholar)
- Rapkin, B. and C. Schwartz, 2004, “Toward a Theoretical
Model of Quality-of-Life Appraisal: Implications of Findings from
Studies of Response Shift”, Health and Quality of Life
Outcomes, 2: 14–25. (Scholar)
- Reiss, J., 2005, “Causal Instrumental Variables and Interventions”, Philosophy of Science, 74: 962–976. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Time Series, Nonsense
Correlations and the Principle of the Common Cause”, in F. Russo
and J. Williamson (eds.), Causality and Probability in the
Sciences, London: College Publications, 179–196. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, Error in Economics: Towards a More Evidence-Based Methodology, London: Routledge. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010a, “Across the Boundaries:
Extrapolation in Biology and Social Science, Daniel P. Steel. Oxford
University Press, 2007. xi + 241 pages”, Economics and
Philosophy, 26: 382–390. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010b, “In Favour of a Millian Proposal to Reform Biomedical Research”, Synthese, 177: 427–447. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Third Time’s a Charm:
Wittgensteinian Pluralisms and Causation”, in P. McKay Illari,
F. Russo and J. Williamson (eds.), Causality in the Sciences,
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 907–927. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015a, “A Pragmatist Theory of Evidence”, Philosophy of Science, 82: 341–362. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015b, Causation, Evidence, and Inference, New York (NY): Routledge. (Scholar)
- –––, forthcoming-a, “On the Causal
Wars”, in H.-K. Chao, J. Reiss and S.-T. Chen (eds.),
Philosophy of Science in Practice, Dordrecht: Springer. (Scholar)
- –––, forthcoming-b, “Meanwhile, Why Not Biomedical Capitalism?”, in K. Elliott and D. Steel (eds.), Current Controversies in Science and Values, New York (NY): Routledge (Scholar)
- Reiss, J. and P. Kitcher, 2009, “Biomedical Research, Neglected Diseases, and Well-Ordered Science”, Theoria, 24: 263–282. (Scholar)
- Reiss, J. and S. Wieten, “On Justin Biddle’s ‘Lessons from the Vioxx Debacle’”, Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 4(5), 2015: 20-22.
(Scholar)
- Reznek, L., 1987, The Nature of Disease, New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Ritchie, K., 1989, “The Little Woman Meets Son of DSM-III”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 14: 695–708. (Scholar)
- Russo, F. and J. Williamson, 2007, “Interpreting Causality in the Health Sciences”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21: 157–170. (Scholar)
- Sackett, D.L., W.M. Rosenberg, J.A. Gray, R.B. Haynes, and W.S.
Richardson, 1996, “Evidence-Based Medicine: What it Is and What
it Isn't”, British Medical Journal, 312: 71–72.
pmcid:PMC2349778 (Scholar)
- Sadegh-Zadeh, K., 2000, “Fuzzy Health, Illness, and Disease”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25: 605–638. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “The Logic of Diagnosis”, in F. Gifford (ed.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, Volume 16: Philosophy of Medicine, Amsterdam: Elsevier, 357–424. (Scholar)
- Sadler, J.Z. and G.J. Agich, 1995, “Diseases, Functions, Values, and Psychiatric Classification”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 2: 219–231. (Scholar)
- Scadding, J., 1990, “The Semantic Problem of
Psychiatry”, Psychological Medicine, 20:
243–248. (Scholar)
- Schaffner, K..F., 1981, “Modeling Medical Diagnosis: Logical
and Computer Approaches”, Synthese, 47:
163–199. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, Discovery and Explanation in
Biology and Medicine, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Interpretive Practices in
Medicine”, in P. Machamer and G. Wolters (eds.),
Interpretation: Ways of Thinking about the Sciences and the
Arts, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press,
158–178. (Scholar)
- Schwartz, P., 2007, “Decision and Discovery in Defining
‘Disease’”, in H. Kincaid and J. McKitrick (eds.),
Establishing Medical Reality, Amsterdam: Springer,
47–63. (Scholar)
- Sedgewick, P., 1982, PsychoPolitics, New York: Harper and
Row. (Scholar)
- Shorter, E., 2008, From Paralysis to Fatigue: A History of
Psychosomatic Illness in the Modern Era, New York: Simon &
Schuster. (Scholar)
- Sismondo, S., 2008, “Ghost Management: How Much of the Medical Literature is Shaped Behind the Scenes by the Pharmaceutical Industry?” PLoS Medicine, 4(9). (Scholar)
- Smith, K.C., 1992, “The New Problem of Genetics: A Response to Gifford”, Biology and Philosophy, 7: 331–348. (Scholar)
- Sober, E., 1980, “Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism”, Philosophy of Science, 47: 350–383. (Scholar)
- Solomon, M., 2007, “The Social Epistemology of NIH Consensus
Conferences”, in H. Kincaid and J. McKitrick (eds.),
Establishing Medical Reality, New York: Springer,
167–177. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Group Judgment and the Medical Consensus Conference”, in F. Gifford (ed.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, Volume 16: Philosophy of Medicine, Amsterdam: Elsevier, 239–254. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, Making Medical Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Staley, K., 2004, The Evidence for the Top Quark. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Stanley, D.E. and D.G. Campos, 2013, “The Logic of Medical Diagnosis”, Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 56: 300–315. (Scholar)
- Steel, D., 2008, Across the Boundaries: Extrapolation in Biology and Social Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Mechanisms and Extrapolation
in the Abortion-Crime Controversy”, in H.-K. Chao, S.-T. Chen
and R. Millstein, Mechanism and Causality in Biology and
Economics, Dordrecht, Springer: 185-206. (Scholar)
- Szasz, T., 1961, The Myth of Mental Illness, New York:
Harper & Row. (Scholar)
- –––, 1973, The Second Sin, New York:
Doubleday. (Scholar)
- –––, 1987, Insanity, New York:
Wiley. (Scholar)
- Thagard, P., 1999, How Scientists Explain Disease, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “What is a Medical Theory?” in R. Payton and L. McNamara, Multidisciplinary Approaches to Theory in Medicine, vol. 3, Amsterdam: Elsevier, 47–62. (Scholar)
- Tiles, M., 1993, “The Normal and Pathological: The Concept of a Scientific Medicine”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44: 729–742. (Scholar)
- Timmermans, S. and M. Berg, 2003, The Gold Standard: The
Challenge of Evidence-Based Medicine and Standardization in Health
Care, Philadelphia: Temple University Press. (Scholar)
- Tonelli, M., 2006, “Evidence-Based Medicine and Clinical
Expertise”, Virtual Mentor, 8: 71–74. (Scholar)
- Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman, 1983, “Extensional vs. Intuitive Reasoning: The Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment”, Psychological Review, 90: 293–315. (Scholar)
- van Bouwel, J., E. Weber, and L. de Vreese, 2011,
“Indispensability Arguments in Favour of Reductive
Explanations”, Journal for General Philosophy of
Science, 42: 33–46. (Scholar)
- Vandenbroucke, J.P., 2009, “The HRT Controversy:
Observational Studies and RCTs Fall in Line”, The
Lancet, 373: 1233–1235. (Scholar)
- Wachbroit, R., 1994, “Normality as a Biological Concept”, Philosophy of Science, 61: 579–591. (Scholar)
- Wakefield, J.C., 1992, “The Concept of Mental Disorder: On
the Boundary between Biological and Social Values”, American
Psychologist, 47: 373–388. (Scholar)
- –––, 1996, “Dysfunction as a Value-Free
Concept”, Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 2:
233–246. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “What Makes a Mental Disorder
Mental?” Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 13:
123–131. (Scholar)
- Wartofsky, M., 1986, “Clinical Judgment, Expert Programs, and Cognitive Style: A Counter-Essay in the Logic of Diagnosis”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 11: 81–92. (Scholar)
- Weber, M., 2008, “Causes without Mechanisms: Experimental Regularities, Physical Laws, and Neuroscientific Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, 75: 995-1007. (Scholar)
- Weightman, A., S. Ellis, A. Cullum, L. Sander, and R.L. Turley
(eds), 2005, Grading Evidence and Recommendations for Public
Health Interventions: Developing and Piloting a Framework,
London: Health Development Agency. (Scholar)
- Whitbeck, C., 1977, “Causation in Medicine: The Disease Entity Model”, Philosophy of Science, 44: 619–637 (Scholar)
- –––, 1981, “A Theory of Health”, in A.L. Caplan and H.T. Engelhardt, Jr. (eds.), Concepts of Health and Disease: Interdisciplinary Perspectives. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 611–626. (Scholar)
- WHO [World Health Organization], 1948, Preamble to the
Constitution of the World Health Organization as adopted by the
International Health Conference, New York, 19 June–22 July 1946;
signed on 22 July 1946 by the representatives of 61 States (Official
Records of the World Health Organization, no. 2, p. 100) and entered
into force on 7 April 1948. (Scholar)
- Williams, T.N., T.W. Mwangi, S. Wambua, N.D. Alexander, M. Kortok,
R.W. Snow, and K. Marsh, 2005, “Sickle Cell Trait and the Risk
of Plasmodium falciparum Malaria and Other Childhood Diseases”,
Journal of Infectious Diseases, 192: 178–186. (Scholar)
- Woodward, J., 2002, “What Is a Mechanism?” Philosophy of Science, 69: S366–377. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, Making Things Happen, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Worrall, J., 2002, “What Evidence in Evidence-Based Medicine”, Philosophy of Science, 69: S316–330. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007a, “Evidence in Medicine and Evidence-Based Medicine”, Philosophy Compass, 2: 981–1022. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007b, “Why There’s No Cause to
Randomize”, British Journal for Philosophy of Science,
58: 451–488. (Scholar)
- Worrall, J. and J. Worrall, 2001, “Defining Disease: Much Ado about Nothing”, in A. Tymieniecka and E. Agazzi (eds.), Life Interpretation and the Sense of Illness Within the Human Condition, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 33–55. (Scholar)