Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Parenthood and Procreation" by Elizabeth Brake and Joseph Millum
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Almond, Brenda, 2006, The Fragmenting Family, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Alstott, Anne, 2004, No Exit: What Parents Owe their Children
and What Society Owes Parents, Oxford: Oxford University
Press. (Scholar)
- Altman, Scott, 2018, “Parental Control Rights,” in Brake and Ferguson 2018, pp. 209–226. (Scholar)
- Anderson, Elizabeth, 1990, “Is Women’s Labor a
Commodity?,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 19:
71–92. (Scholar)
- Annas, George, 1984, “Redefining Parenthood and Protecting
Embryos: Why We Need New Laws,” The Hastings Center
Report, 51: 50–52. (Scholar)
- Archard, David, 1990, “Child Abuse: Parental Rights and the Interests of the Child,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 7: 183–194 (Scholar)
- –––, 2004, Children: Rights and Childhood, 2nd ed., New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “The Obligations and Responsibilities of Parenthood,” in Archard and Benatar 2010, pp. 103–127. (Scholar)
- Archard, David and David Benatar, (eds.), 2010, Procreation and Parenthood, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Archard, David and Colin Macleod, (eds.), 2002, The Moral and Political Status of Children: New Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Arneson, Richard, 1992, “Commodification and Commercial Surrogacy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21(2): 132–164. (Scholar)
- Asch, Adrienne, 1999, “Can Aborting ‘Imperfect’
Children be Immoral?,” in Ethical Issues in Modern
Medicine, 5th ed., ed. John D. Arras & Nancy K.
Rhoden, Mountain View, CA: Mayfield. (Scholar)
- Austin, Michael, 2004, “The Failure of Biological Accounts of Parenthood,” The Journal of Value Inquiry, 38: 499–510. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, Conceptions of Parenthood, Burlington, VT: Ashgate. (Scholar)
- Baron, Teresa, 2019, “Nobody Puts Baby in the Container: The Foetal Container Model at Work in Medicine and Commercial Surrogacy,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 36(3): 491–505. (Scholar)
- Bayles, Michael D., 1979, “Limits to a Right to
Procreate,” in O’Neill and Ruddick 1979, pp.
13–24. (Scholar)
- Baylis, Françoise, and Carolyn McLeod (eds.), 2014, Family-Making: Contemporary Ethical Challenges, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Bayne, T., 2003, “Gamete Donation and Parental Responsibility,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 20(3): 77–87. (Scholar)
- Bayne, T., and A. Kolers, 2003, “Toward a Pluralistic Account of Parenthood,” Bioethics, 17(3): 221–42. (Scholar)
- Belshaw, Christopher, 2003, “More Lives, Better Lives,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 6: 127–41. (Scholar)
- Benatar, David, 1997, “Why it is Better Never to Come into Existence,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 34: 345–55. (Scholar)
- –––, 1999, “The Unbearable Lightness of Bringing into Being,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 16(2): 173–80. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, Better Never to Have Been, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “The Limits of Reproductive Freedom,” in Archard and Benatar 2010, pp. 78–102. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “The Misanthropic Argument for
Anti-natalism,” in Hannan, Brennan, and Vernon 2015, pp.
34–64. (Scholar)
- Benatar, David and Michael Benatar, 2003, “Between Prophylaxis and Child Abuse: The Ethics of Neonatal Male Circumcision,” American Journal of Bioethics, 3: 35–48. (Scholar)
- Benatar, David, and David Wasserman, 2015, Debating Procreation: Is It Wrong to Reproduce?, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Bennett, Rebecca, 2014, “When Intuition Is Not Enough: Why
the Principle of Procreative Beneficence Must Work Much Harder to
Justify Its Eugenic Vision,” Bioethics, 28(9):
447–455. (Scholar)
- Ber, Rosalie, 2000, “Ethical Issues in Gestational Surrogacy,” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 21: 153–69. (Scholar)
- Bigelow, J., J. Campbell, S. Dodds, R. Pargetter, E. Prior and R.
Young, 1988, “Parental Autonomy,” Journal of Applied
Philosophy, 5: 3–16. (Scholar)
- Blustein, Jeffrey, 1982, Parents and Children: The Ethics of
the Family, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997, “Procreation and Parental Responsibility,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 28(2): 79–86. (Scholar)
- Boucai, Michael, 2016, “Is assisted procreation an LGBT
right?” Wisconsin Law Review, 2016(6):
1065–1125. (Scholar)
- Botterell, Andrew and Carolyn McLeod, 2016, “Licensing
Parents in International Contract Pregnancies,” Journal of
Applied Philosophy, 33(2): 178–196. (Scholar)
- Bower, Carol and Michèle Hansen, 2005, “Assisted
reproductive technologies and birth outcomes: overview of recent
systematic reviews,” Reproduction, Fertility and
Development, 17(3): 329–333. (Scholar)
- Brake, Elizabeth, 2005, “Fatherhood and Child Support: Do Men have a Right to Choose?,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 22(1): 55–73. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Willing Parents: A Voluntarist Account of Parental Role Obligations,” in Archard and Benatar 2010, pp. 151–177. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Creation Theory: Do Genetic
Ties Matter?,” in Hannan, Brennan, and Vernon 2015, pp.
129–149. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Paid and Unpaid Care:
Marriage, Equality, and Domestic Workers,” in Brake and Ferguson
2018, pp. 75–94. (Scholar)
- Brake, Elizabeth and Lucinda Ferguson (eds.), 2018,
Philosophical Foundations of Children’s and Family Law,
Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Brandt, Reuven, 2017, “The Transfer and Delegation of
Responsibilities for Genetic Offspring in Gamete Provision,”
Journal of Applied Philosophy, 34(5): 665–678. (Scholar)
- Brazier, Margaret, 1998, “Reproductive Rights: Feminism or
Patriarchy?,” in Harris and Holm 1998, pp. 66–76. (Scholar)
- Brennan, Samantha and Robert Noggle, 1997, “The moral status
of children: Children’s rights, parents’ rights, and
family justice,” Social Theory and Practice, 23(1):
1–26. (Scholar)
- Brighouse, Harry and Adam Swift, 2006, “Parents’
Rights and the Value of the Family,” Ethics, 117(1):
80–108. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, Family Values: The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships, Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Brock, Dan, 2005, “Shaping Future Children: Parental Rights and Societal Interests,” Journal of Political Philosophy, 13(4): 377–98. (Scholar)
- Buchanan, Allen, 2008, “Enhancement and the Ethics of Development,” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 18(1): 1–34. (Scholar)
- Buchanan, Allen, et al., 2000, From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Card, Claudia, 1996, “Against Marriage and Motherhood,” Hypatia, 11(3): 1–23. (Scholar)
- Carter, J. Adam and Emma C. Gordon, 2013, “Intelligence, Wellbeing, and Procreative Beneficence,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 30(2): 122–135. (Scholar)
- Cassidy, Lisa, 2006, “That Many of Us Should Not Parent,” Hypatia, 21(4): 40–57. (Scholar)
- Chambers, Clare, 2017, Against Marriage: An Egalitarian Defence of the Marriage-Free State, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Chan, Sarah, and Muireann Quigley, 2007, “Frozen Embryos, Genetic Information and Reproductive Rights,” Bioethics, 21(8): 439–448. (Scholar)
- Christianson, Mindy S., et al., 2020 “Embryo
cryopreservation and utilization in the United States from
2004–2013.” F&S Reports, 1(2):
71–77. (Scholar)
- Clayton, Matthew, 2006, Justice and Legitimacy in Upbringing, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Cohen, Glenn, 2007, “The Constitution and The Rights Not to
Procreate,” Stanford Law Review, 60(4):
1135–1196. (Scholar)
- Coleman, Joe, 2003, “School Choice, Diversity, and a Life of
One’s Own,” Theory and Research in Education,
1(1): 101–120. (Scholar)
- Collins, Patricia Hill, 1991, Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment, New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Conly, Sarah, 2005, “The right to procreation: Merits and limits,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 42(2): 105–115. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, One Child: Do We Have a Right to More?, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Corea, Gena, 1985, The Mother Machine, New York: Harper
& Row. (Scholar)
- Cripps, Elizabeth, 2017, “Do parents have a special duty to mitigate climate change?,” Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 16(3): 308–325. (Scholar)
- Cutas, Daniela, 2007, “Postmenopausal Motherhood: Immoral, Illegal? A Case Study,” Bioethics, 21(8): 458–463. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “On Triparenting: Is Having Three Committed Parents Better Than Having Only Two?,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 37(12): 735–738. (Scholar)
- De Wispelaere, Jurgen, and Daniel Weinstock, 2014, “State
Regulation and Assisted Reproduction: Balancing the Interests of
Parents and Children,” in Baylis and McLeod 2014, pp.
131–150. (Scholar)
- Dodds, Susan and Karen Jones, 1989a, “Surrogacy and Autonomy,” Bioethics, 3(1): 1–17. (Scholar)
- –––, 1989b, “Response to Purdy’s ‘Surrogate Mothering’,” Bioethics, 3: 35–39. (Scholar)
- Dworkin, Ronald, 1993, Life’s Dominion, New York:
Knopf. (Scholar)
- Dwyer, James G., 2018, “Regulating Child Rearing in a
Culturally Diverse Society,” in Brake and Ferguson 2018, pp.
273–292. (Scholar)
- Engster, Daniel, 2010, “The Place of Parenting within a Liberal Theory of Justice: The Private Parenting Model, Parental Licenses, or Public Parental Support?,” Social Theory and Practice, 36(2): 233–62. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “Equal Opportunity and the
Family: Levelling Up the Brighouse-Swift Thesis,” Journal of
Applied Philosophy, 36(1): 34–49. (Scholar)
- ESHRE Task Force on ethics and Law 20, 2013, “Sex Selection
for Non-medical Reasons,” Human Reproduction, 28:
1448–1454 (Scholar)
- Etieyibo, Edwin, 2012, “Genetic Enhancement, Social Justice, and Welfare-Oriented Patterns of Distribution,” Bioethics, 26(6): 296–304. (Scholar)
- Fahmy, Melissa Seymour, 2011, “On the supposed moral harm of selecting for deafness.” Bioethics, 25(3): 128–136. (Scholar)
- Feinberg, Joel, 1980, “On the Child’s Right to an Open
Future,” in Whose Child?, W. Aiken and H. LaFollette
(eds.), Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 124–53. (Scholar)
- –––, 1986, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (Volume 1: Harm to Others), New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1992, “Wrongful Life and
Counterfactual Harming,” in Freedom & Fulfillment,
Joel Feinberg, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Feldman, S., 1992, “Multiple Biological Mothers: The Case for Gestation,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 23: 98–104. (Scholar)
- Fenton, Elizabeth, 2006, “Liberal Eugenics and Human Nature—Against Habermas,” Hastings Center Report, 36(6): 35–42. (Scholar)
- Fenton, Elizabeth and Loren Lomasky, 2005, “Dispensing with liberty: Conscientious refusal and the ‘morning-after pill’,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 30: 579–592. (Scholar)
- Ferracioli, Luara, 2018, “Procreative-Parenting,
Love’s Reasons and the Demands of Morality,”
Philosophical Quarterly, 68(270): 77–97. (Scholar)
- Fowler, Timothy, 2010, “The problems of liberal neutrality in upbringing,” Res Publica, 16(4): 367–381. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Perfectionism for children, anti-perfectionism for adults,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 44(3–4): 305–323. (Scholar)
- Franklin-Hall, Andrew, 2012, “Creation and Authority: The Natural Law Foundations of Locke’s Account of Parental Authority,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 42(3–4): 255–280. (Scholar)
- Freeman, Michael, 1997, The Moral Status of Children: Essays
on the Rights of Children, The Hague: Kluwer Law
International. (Scholar)
- Friedrich, Daniel, 2013, “A Duty to Adopt?,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 30(1): 25–39. (Scholar)
- Fuscaldo, Giulianna, 2006, “Genetic Ties: Are they Morally Binding?,” Bioethics, 20(2): 64–76. (Scholar)
- Galston, William, 1991, Liberal Purposes, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “Two Concepts of Liberalism,” Ethics, 105: 516–34. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Parents, government, and children: Authority over education in a pluralist liberal democracy.” Law & Ethics of Human Rights 5(2): 285–305. (Scholar)
- George, R., 1987, “Who Should Bear the Cost of Children?,” Public Affairs Quarterly, 1: 1–42. (Scholar)
- Gheaus, Anca, 2011, “Arguments for Nonparental care for Children,” Social Theory and Practice, 37(3): 483–509. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “The Right to Parent
One’s Biological Baby,” Journal of Political
Philosophy, 20(4): 432–455, first published online 2011,
doi:10.1111/j.1467–9760.2011.00402.x (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Could There Ever Be a Duty to Have Children?,” in Hannan, Brennan, and Vernon 2015, pp. 87–106. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016a, “The Right to Parent and Duties Concerning Future Generations,” Journal of Political Philosophy, 24(1): 487–508, doi:10.1111/jopp.12091 (Scholar)
- –––, 2016b, “The Normative Importance of Pregnancy Challenges Surrogacy Contracts,” Analize: Journal of Gender and Feminist Studies, 6(20): 20–31. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018a, “Biological Parenthood:
Gestational, Not Genetic,” Australasian Journal of
Philosophy, 96(2): 225–240. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018b, “Children’s
Vulnerability and Legitimate Authority over Children,”
Journal of Applied Philosophy, 35(1): 60–75. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “More Co-Parents, Fewer Children: Multiparenting and Sustainable Population,” Essays in Philosophy, 20(1): 3–23. (Scholar)
- Glannon, Walter, 2001, Genes and Future People: Philosophical Issues in Human Genetics, Boulder, CO: Westview Press. (Scholar)
- Glover, Jonathan, 1998, “Eugenics: Some Lessons from the
Nazi Experience,” in Harris and Holm 1998, pp. 55–65. (Scholar)
- Glover, Jonathan, et al., 1989, Fertility & the Family:
The Glover Report on Reproductive Technologies to the European
Commission, London: Fourth Estate. (Scholar)
- Grill, Kalle, 2020, “How Many Parents Should There Be in a Family?,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 37(3): 467–484. (Scholar)
- Habermas, Jurgen, 2003, The Future of Human Nature, Cambridge: Polity Press. (Scholar)
- Hall, Barbara, 1999, “The origin of parental rights,” Public Affairs Quarterly, 13: 73–82. (Scholar)
- Hanna, Jason, 2019, “Causal parenthood and the ethics of gamete donation,” Bioethics, 33(2): 267–273. (Scholar)
- Hannan, Sarah, Samantha Brennan, and Richard Vernon, (eds.), 2015, Permissible Progeny, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Hannan, Sarah, and R. J. Leland, 2018 “Childhood bads, parenting goods, and the right to procreate.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 21(3): 366–384. (Scholar)
- Hanser, Matthew, 1990, “Harming Future People”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 19(1): 47–70. (Scholar)
- Harman, Elizabeth, 2004, “Can We Harm and Benefit in Creating?”, Philosophical Perspectives, 18: 89–113. (Scholar)
- Harris, John, 1998, “Rights and Reproductive Choice,”
in Harris and Holm 1998, pp. 5–37. (Scholar)
- Harris, John and Soren Holm, (eds.), 1998, The Future of Human Reproduction: Ethics, Choice and Regulation, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- Haslanger, Sally, 2009, “Family, Ancestry and Self: What is
the Moral Significance of Biological Ties?,” Adoption &
Culture, 2(1): 91–122. (Scholar)
- Haslanger, Sally and Charlotte Witt, eds., 2006, Adoption
Matters: Philosophical and Feminist Essays, Ithaca: Cornell
University Press. (Scholar)
- Held, Virginia, 1987, “Non-Contractual Society: A Feminist View,” in Science, Morality, and Feminist Theory, eds. Marsha Hanen and Kai Nielsen, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 13 (Supplementary Volume): 111–137. (Scholar)
- Henderson, Tammy L., 2005, “Grandparent Visitation Rights:
Successful Acquisition of Court-Ordered Visitation,” Journal
of Family Issues, 26(1): 107–137. (Scholar)
- Heyd, David, 2003, “Male or Female, We Will Create Them: The Ethics of Sex Selection for Non-Medical Reasons,” Ethical Perspectives, 10(3–4): 204–214. (Scholar)
- Hill, J. L., 1991, “What does it mean to be a
‘Parent’? The claims of biology as a basis for parental
rights,” New York University Law Review, 66:
353–420. (Scholar)
- Holtug, Nils, 2001, “On the Value of Coming into Existence,” The Journal of Ethics, 5: 361–84. (Scholar)
- hooks, bell, 1984, Feminist Theory: From Margin to
Center, Boston: South End Press. (Scholar)
- Hubin, Don, 2003, “Daddy Dilemmas: Untangling the Puzzles of
Paternity,” The Cornell Journal of Law and Public
Policy, 13: 29–80. (Scholar)
- Kahane, Guy, 2009, “Non-identity, self-defeat, and attitudes to future children.” Philosophical Studies, 145(2): 193–214. (Scholar)
- Karpin, Isabel, 2007, “Choosing disability: preimplantation genetic diagnosis and negative enhancement,” Journal of Law and Medicine, 15(1): 89–102. (Scholar)
- Kavka, Gregory S., 1982, “The Paradox of Future Individuals,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 11(2): 93–112. (Scholar)
- Kelleher, J. Paul, 2010, “Emergency Contraception and Conscientious Objection,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 27(3): 290–304 (Scholar)
- Kittay, Eva, 1999, Love’s Labor, New York:
Routledge. (Scholar)
- Kolers, Avery and T. Bayne, 2001, “”Are You My Mommy?“ On the Genetic Basis of Parenthood,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 18(3): 273–85. (Scholar)
- Krishnamurthy, Meena, 2015, “We Can Make Rational Decisions to Have a Child: On the Grounds for Rejecting L.A. Paul’s Arguments,” in Hannan, Brennan, and Vernon 2015, pp. 170–183. (Scholar)
- Kukla, Rebecca, 2005, Mass Hysteria: Medicine, Culture, and Mothers’ Bodies, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. (Scholar)
- LaFollette, Hugh, 1980, “Licensing Parents,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 9(2): 183–97. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Licensing Parents Revisited,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 27(4): 327–343. (Scholar)
- LaFollette, Eva and Hugh LaFollette, 2007, “Private consciences, public acts,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 33: 249–254. (Scholar)
- Lev, Ori, 2011, “Will Biomedical Enhancements Undermine Solidarity, Responsibility, Equality and Autonomy?,” Bioethics, 25(4): 177–184. (Scholar)
- Liao, S. Matthew, 2015, The Right to Be Loved, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Lotz, Mianna, 2006, “Feinberg, Mills, and the Child’s
Right to an Open Future,” Journal of Social Philosophy,
37(4): 537–551. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Adoptee Vulnerability and
Post-Adoptive Parental Obligation,” in Baylis and McLeod 2014,
pp. 198–221. (Scholar)
- MacIver, Corey, 2015, “Procreation or Appropriation?,”
in Hannan, Brennan, and Vernon 2015, pp. 107–128. (Scholar)
- Macleod, Colin, 2010, “Parental Responsibilities in an Unjust World,” in Archard and Benatar 2010, pp. 128–150. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Parental Competency and the
Right to Parent,” in Hannan, Brennan, and Vernon 2015, pp.
227–245. (Scholar)
- Manning, W., M. Fettro, and E. Lamidi, 2014, “Child
Well-Being in Same-Sex Parent Families: Review of Research Prepared
for American Sociological Association Amicus Brief,”
Population Research & Policy Review, 33(4):
485–502. (Scholar)
- Mazor, Joseph, 2019, “On the Strength of Children’s
Right to Bodily Integrity: The Case of Circumcision,”
Journal of Applied Philosophy, 36(1): 1–16. (Scholar)
- McFall, Michael T., 2009, Licensing Parents: Family, State, and Child Maltreatment, Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. (Scholar)
- McLeod, Carolyn, 2010, “Harm or Mere Inconvenience? Denying Women Emergency Contraception,” Hypatia, 25(1): 11–30. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, “The medical nonnecessity of in vitro fertilization.” IJFAB: International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 10(1): 78–102. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, Conscience in Reproductive Health Care: Prioritizing Patient Interests, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- McLeod, Carolyn, and Andrew Botterell, 2014, “‘Not for
the Faint of Heart’: Assessing the Status Quo on Adoption and
Parental Licensing,” in Baylis and McLeod 2014, pp.
151–167. (Scholar)
- McMahan, Jeff, 1998, “Wrongful Life: Paradoxes in the Morality of Causing People to Exist,” in J. Coleman and C. Morris, (eds.), Rational Commitment and Social Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Meilaender, Gilbert, 1987, The Limits of Love: Some Theological Explorations, University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press. (Scholar)
- Melo‐Martín, Inmaculada De, 2014, “The ethics
of anonymous gamete donation: is there a right to know one’s
genetic origins?” Hastings Center Report, 44(2):
28–35. (Scholar)
- Mills, Claudia, 2003, “The Child’s Right to an Open
Future?,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 34(4):
499–509. (Scholar)
- Millum, Joseph, 2008, “How Do We Acquire Parental Responsibilities?,” Social Theory and Practice, 34(1): 71–93 (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “How Do We Acquire Parental Rights?” Social Theory and Practice, 36(1): 112–132. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “The Foundation of the
Child’s Right to an Open Future,” Journal of Social
Philosophy, 45(4): 522–538. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, The Moral Foundations of Parenthood. New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Moschella, Melissa, 2014, “Rethinking the moral permissibility of gamete donation.” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 35(6): 421–440. (Scholar)
- Mullin, Amy, 2005, Reconceiving Pregnancy and Childcare: Ethics, Experience, and Reproductive Labor, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Filial Responsibilities of Dependent Children,” Hypatia, 25(1): 157–173. (Scholar)
- Murray, Thomas H., 1996, The Worth of a Child, Berkeley: University of California Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “What Are Families for? Getting to an Ethics of Reproductive Technology,” The Hastings Center Report, 32(3): 41–45. (Scholar)
- Narayan, U., 1999, “Family Ties: Rethinking Parental Claims
in the Light of Surrogacy and Custody,” in Narayan and
Bartkowiak 1999, pp. 65–86. (Scholar)
- Narayan, U. and J.J. Bartkowiak, 1999, Having and Raising Children: Unconventional Families, Hard Choices, and the Social Good, University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press. (Scholar)
- Narveson, Jan, 2002, Respecting Persons in Theory and Practice, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. (Scholar)
- Nelson, James Lindemann, 1991, “Parental Obligations and the Ethics of Surrogacy: A Causal Perspective,” Public Affairs Quarterly, 5: 49–61. (Scholar)
- Neumann, Peter J, 1997, “Should health insurance cover IVF?
Issues and options.” Journal of Health Politics, Policy and
Law, 22(5): 1215–1239. (Scholar)
- Oakley, Justin, 1992, “Altruistic Surrogacy and Informed Consent”, Bioethics, 6(4): 269–87. (Scholar)
- Okin, Susan Moller, 1989, Justice, Gender, and the Family, New York: Basic Books. (Scholar)
- –––, 1994, “Political Liberalism,
Justice, and Gender,” Ethics, 105: 23–43. (Scholar)
- Olsaretti, Serena, 2013, “Children as Public Goods?” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 41(3): 226–258. (Scholar)
- O’Neill, Onora, 1979, “Begetting, Bearing, and
Rearing,” in O’Neill and Ruddick 1979, pp.
25–38. (Scholar)
- O’Neill, Onora and William Ruddick, 1979, (eds.), Having
Children: Philosophical and Legal Reflections on Parenthood, New
York: Oxford University Press.
- Overall, Christine, 1993, Human Reproduction: Principles, Practices, Policies, Toronto: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “Frozen Embryos and
’Fathers’ Rights’: Parenthood and Decision Making in
the Cryopreservation of Embryos,” in Joan Callahan, ed.,
Reproduction, Ethics, and the Law: Feminist Perspectives,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, Why Have Children?: The Ethical Debate, Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Page, Edgar, 1985, “Donation, Surrogacy, and Adoption,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 2(2): 161–172; reprinted in B. Almond and D. Hill, (eds.), Applied Philosophy, Routledge: New York, 1992. (Scholar)
- Panitch, Vida, 2013, “Surrogate tourism and reproductive rights,” Hypatia, 28(2): 274–289. (Scholar)
- Parens, Erik, (ed.), 2006, Surgically Shaping Children,
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. (Scholar)
- Parfit, D., 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon. (Scholar)
- Parker, Michael, 2010, “An Ordinary Chance of a Desirable Existence,” in Archard and Benatar 2010, pp. 57–77. (Scholar)
- Parker, P., 1982, “Surrogate Motherhood: The Interaction of
Litigation, Legislation, and Psychiatry,” International
Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 5: 341–54. (Scholar)
- Paul, Laurie, 2015, “What You Can’t Expect When You’re Expecting,” Res Philosophica, 92(2). doi:10.11612/resphil.2015.92.2.1 (Scholar)
- Priest, Maura, 2019, “Transgender Children and the Right to Transition: Medical Ethics When Parents Mean Well but Cause Harm,” The American Journal of Bioethics, 19(2): 45–59. (Scholar)
- Prusak, Bernard, 2011a, “The Costs of Procreation,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 42(1): 61–75. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011b, “Breaking the Bond: Abortion and the Grounds of Parental Obligations,” Social Theory and Practice, 37(2): 311–332. (Scholar)
- Purdy, Laura, 1989, “Surrogate Mothering: Exploitation or Empowerment?,” Bioethics, 3(1): 18–34. (Scholar)
- –––, 1990, “Are Pregnant Women Fetal Containers,” Bioethics, 4(4): 273–291 (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “Loving Future People,” in J. Callahan, (ed.), Reproduction, Ethics and the Law, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Is Preconception Sex Selection Necessarily Sexist?,” Reproductive BioMedicine Online, 15(2): 33–37. (Scholar)
- Rachels, James, 1989, “Morality, Parents, and
Children,” in Graham and LaFollette (eds.), Person to
Person, Philadelphia: Temple University Press. (Scholar)
- Rachels, Stuart, 1998, “Is it Good to Make Happy People?,” Bioethics, 12(2): 93–110. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “The Immorality of Having Children,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 17(3): 567–582. (Scholar)
- Radin, Margaret Jane, 1996, Contested Commodities, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Reefhuis, J., et al., 2009, “Assisted reproductive
technology and major structural birth defects in the United
States,” Human Reproduction, 24(2): 360–6. (Scholar)
- Richards, Norvin, 2010, The Ethics of Parenthood, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Roberts, Dorothy, 1997, Killing the Black Body: Race,
Reproduction, and the Meaning of Liberty, New York:
Pantheon. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “Feminism, Race, and Adoption
Policy,” in Haslanger and Witt 2006, pp. 234–246. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Reproductive Justice, Not Just
Rights,” Dissent, 62(4): 79–82. (Scholar)
- Roberts, Melinda, 1998, Child Versus Childmaker, Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield. (Scholar)
- Robertson, John, 1994, Children of Choice, Princeton:
Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “Extending Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: Medical And Non-Medical Uses,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 29(4): 213–216. (Scholar)
- Rosenman, A.S., 1995, “Babies Jessica, Richard and Emily:
The Need for Legislative Reform of Adoption Laws,” Chicago
Kent Law Review, 70: 1851–95. (Scholar)
- Ross, Lainie Friedman, 2002, Children, Families, and Health Care Decision Making, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Rothman, Barbara K., 1989, Recreating Motherhood: Ideology and Technology in a Patriarchal Society, New York: W.W. Norton. (Scholar)
- Rulli, Tina, 2014, “The Unique Value of Adoption,” in Baylis and McLeod 2014, pp. 109–130. (Scholar)
- –––, 2016, “Preferring a Genetically-Related Child,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, 13(6): 669–698, doi: 10.1163/17455243-4681062 (Scholar)
- Russell, Camisha A., 2018, The Assisted Reproduction of Race, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. (Scholar)
- Sandel, Michael J., 2007, The Case Against Perfection: Ethics
in the Age of Genetic Engineering, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press. (Scholar)
- Satz, Debra, 2010, Why Some Things Should Not Be for Sale: The Moral Limits of Markets, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Savulescu, Julian, 2001, “Procreative Beneficence: Why we Should Select the Best Children,” Bioethics, 15(5–6): 413–426. (Scholar)
- Savulescu, J. and G. Kahane, 2009, “The Moral Obligation to
Create Children with the Best Chance of the Best Life,”
Bioethics, 23(5): 274–290. (Scholar)
- Schouten, Gina, 2019, Liberalism, Neutrality, and the Gendered Division of Labor, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Schroeder, S. Andrew, 2018, “Well-Being, Opportunities, and Selecting for Disability,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 14(1). doi:10.26556/jesp.v14i1.353 (Scholar)
- Shanley, Mary Lyndon, 1993, “‘Surrogate
Mothering’ and Women’s Freedom: A Critique of Contracts
for Human Reproduction,” Signs, 18(3):
618–39. (Scholar)
- –––, 1995, “Fathers’ Rights,
Mothers’ Wrongs? Reflections on Unwed Fathers’ Rights and
Sex Equality,” Hypatia, 10(1): 74–103. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Surrogacy: Reconceptualizing
Family Relationships in an Age of Reproductive Technologies,” in
Brake and Ferguson 2018, pp. 293–312. (Scholar)
- Sherwin, Susan, 1987, “Feminist Ethics and In Vitro Fertilization,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 13 (Supplementary Volume): 276–284. (Scholar)
- –––, 1992, No Longer Patient: Feminist Ethics and Health Care, Philadelphia: Temple University Press. (Scholar)
- Shiffrin, Seana Valentine, 1999, “Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm,” Legal Theory, 5(2): 117–148. (Scholar)
- Shoeman, Ferdinand, 1980, “Rights of Children, Rights of Parents and the Moral Basis of the Family,” Ethics, 91: 6–19. (Scholar)
- Shrage, Laurie, 2018, “Decoupling Marriage and Parenting,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 35(3): 496–512. (Scholar)
- Shultz, M. M., 1990, “Reproductive Technology and
Intent-based Parenthood: An Opportunity for Gender Neutrality,”
Wisconsin Law Review, 297(2): 297–398. (Scholar)
- Silver, Lee, 2001, “Confused Meanings of Life, Genes, and Parents,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 34(4): 647–661. (Scholar)
- Smilansky, Saul, 1995, “Is there a moral obligation to have children?,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 12(1): 41–53. (Scholar)
- Statman, Daniel, 2005, “The Right to Parenthood.”
Ethical Perspectives, 10(3): 224–235. (Scholar)
- Steinbock, Bonnie, 1988, “Surrogate Motherhood as Prenatal Adoption,” Law, Medicine, and Health Care, 16(1–2): 44–50. (Scholar)
- Steinbock, B. and R. McClamrock, 1994, “When Is Birth Unfair to the Child?,” Hastings Center Report, 24(6): 15–21. (Scholar)
- Straehle, Christine, 2016, “Is There a Right to
Surrogacy?,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 33(2):
146–159. (Scholar)
- Stumpf, Andrea, 1986, “Redefining Mother: A Legal Matrix for
New Reproductive Technologies,” The Yale Law Journal,
96: 187–208. (Scholar)
- Swift, Adam, 2003, How Not to be a Hypocrite: School Choice for the Morally Perplexed Parent, Psychology Press. (Scholar)
- Taylor, Robert, 2009, “Children as Projects and Persons: A Liberal Antinomy,” Social Theory and Practice, 35(4): 555–576. (Scholar)
- United Nations General Assembly, 1948, Universal Declaration
of Human Rights, General Assembly resolution 217 A (III), 10
December 1948. (Scholar)
- Van Zyl, Liezl, 2002, “Intentional Parenthood and the Nuclear Family,” Journal of Medical Humanities, 23: 107–18. (Scholar)
- Vehmas, Simo, 2002, “Is It Wrong to Deliberately Conceive or Give Birth to a Child with Mental Retardation?,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 27(1): 47–63. (Scholar)
- Velleman, J. David, 2005, “Family History,” Philosophical Papers, 34(3): 357–378. (Scholar)
- Wasserman, David, 2005, “The Nonidentity Problem, Disability, and the Role Morality of Prospective Parents,” Ethics, 116: 132–152. (Scholar)
- Weinberg, Rivka, 2016, The Risk of a Lifetime: How, When, and Why Procreation May be Permissible, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “The Endless Umbilical Cord: Parental Obligation to Grown Children,” Journal of Practical Ethics, 6(2): 55–72. (Scholar)
- Wilkinson, Stephen, 2016, “Exploitation in International
Paid Surrogacy Arrangements,” Journal of Applied
Philosophy, 33(2): 125–145. (Scholar)
- Woodward, James, 1986, “The Non-Identity Problem,” Ethics, 96: 804–831. (Scholar)
- Young, Iris Marion, 1995, “Mothers, Citizenship, and Independence: A Critique of Pure Family Values,” Ethics, 105: 535–556. (Scholar)
- Young, Thomas, 2001, “Overconsumption and Procreation: Are they Morally Equivalent?,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 18(2): 183–192. (Scholar)
- Zwarthoed, Danielle, 2017, “Parental Education and Expensive Consumption Habits,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 35(4): 825–843. (Scholar)