Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Public Health Ethics" by Ruth Faden, Justin Bernstein and Sirine Shebaya
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Adler, M., 2012, Well-Being and Fair Distribution: Beyond Cost-Benefit Analysis, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Adler, M. D., J. K. Hammitt, and N. Treich, 2014, “Luck
Egalitarianism, Social Determinants, and Public Health
Initiatives,” Journal of Health Economics, 35:
82–93. (Scholar)
- Albertsen, A., 2015, “Workplace Wellness Programs Can
Generate Savings,” Public Health Ethics, 8 (1):
42–49. (Scholar)
- Anand, S, F. Peter, and A. Sen, (eds.), 2006,Public Health, Ethics, and Equity, Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Ananth, M., 2008, In Defense of an Evolutionary Concept of Health, Aldershot: Ashgate. (Scholar)
- Annas, G., 1998, “Human Rights and Health – The
Universal Declaration of Human Rights at 50,” New England
Journal of Medicine, 339(24): 1778–1781. (Scholar)
- Anomaly, J., 2011, “Public Health and Public Goods,” Public Health Ethics, 4 (3): 251–259. (Scholar)
- Anomaly, J., 2012, “Is Obesity a Public Health Problem?,” Public Health Ethics, 5 (3): 216–221. (Scholar)
- Arras, J., 2005, “Rationing Vaccine During an Avian
Influenza Pandemic: Why It Won’t Be Easy,” Yale
Journal of Biology and Medicine, 78: 287–300. (Scholar)
- Bærøe, K., and R. Baltussen, 2014, “Workplace
Wellness Programs Can Generate Savings,” Health
Affairs, 29 (2): 304–311. (Scholar)
- Baicker, K., D. Cutler, and Z. Song, 2010, “Workplace
Wellness Programs Can Generate Savings,” Health
Affairs, 29 (2): 304–311. (Scholar)
- Baker, R., I. Bateman, C. Donaldson, M. Jones-Lee, E. Lancsar, G.
Loomes, H. Mason, and M. Odejar, 2008, Weighting and Valuing
Quality Adjusted Life Years: Preliminary Results from the Social Value
of a QALY Project, Publication No. JH12, London: Crown.
[Available online]. (Scholar)
- Barry, B., 1982, “Humanity and Justice in Global
Perspective,” in NOMOS XXIV: Ethics, Economics and
Law,J.R. Pennock and J.W. Chapman (eds.), New York: NYU
Press. (Scholar)
- Barton, A., 2013, “How Tobacco Health Warnings Can Foster Autonomy,” in Public Health Ethics, 6: 207–219. (Scholar)
- Bayer, R, 2008, “Stigma and the Ethics of Public Health: Not
Can We But Should We,” in Social Science and Medicine,
48: 463–472. (Scholar)
- Bayer, R., and A.L. Fairchild, 2004, “The Genesis of Public Health Ethics,” in Bioethics, 18 (6): 473–92. (Scholar)
- Baylis, F., N. Kenny, and S. Sherwin, 2008, “A Relational Account of Public Health Ethics,” in Public Health Ethics, 1 (3): 196–209. (Scholar)
- Bernstein, J., 2017, “The Case Against Libertarian Arguments for Compulsory Vaccination,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 43 (11): 1–5. (Scholar)
- Beauchamp, T., 2010, “The Concept of Paternalism in Biomedical Ethics,” in Standing on Principles, T. Beauchamp (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 101–119. (Scholar)
- Beauchamp, T., and J. Childress, 2019, Principles of
Biomedical Ethics (Eighth Edition), New York: Oxford University
Press. (Scholar)
- Beauchamp, D. E., and Steinbock, B. (eds), 1999, New Ethics
for the Public’s Health, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Beitz, C., 2015. “The Force of Subsistence Rights,” in Cruft, R., S.M. Liao, and M. Renzo (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press (Scholar)
- Belsky, L., and Richardson, H. S., 2004, “Medical
Researchers’ Ancillary Clinical Care Responsibilities,”
BMJ, 328 (7454): 1494–1496. (Scholar)
- Benatar, S. R., 2002, “Reflections and Recommendations on
Research Ethics in Developing Countries,” Social Science
& Medicine, 54 (7): 1131–1141. (Scholar)
- Beyrer, C., and H. F. Pizer, (eds.), 2007, Public Health and
Human Rights: Evidence-Based Approaches, Baltimore, MD: JHU
Press. (Scholar)
- Beyrer, C., J. C. Villar, V. Suwanvanichkij, S. Singh, S. D.
Baral, and E. J. Mills, 2007, “Neglected Diseases, Civil
Conflicts, and the Right to Health,” The Lancet, 370
(9587): 619–627. (Scholar)
- Bickenbach, J., 2016, “Disability and Health Care
Rationing,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Spring 2016 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/disability-care-rationing/>. (Scholar)
- Blake, M., and P.T. Smith, 2015, “International Distributive
Justice,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Spring 2015 edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/international-justice/> (Scholar)
- Bolnick, H., F. Millard, and J. Dugas, 2013, “Medical Care
Savings from Workplace Wellness Programs: What Is a Realistic Savings
Potential?,” Journal of Occupational and Environmental
Medicine, 55 (1): 4–9. (Scholar)
- Bonotti, M., 2014, “Food Labels, Autonomy, and the Right (Not) to Know,” Kennedy Institute of Ethics, 24 (4): 301–321. (Scholar)
- Bonotti, M., and A. Barnhill, 2019, “Are Healthy Eating
Policies Consistent with Public Reason Liberalism?” Journal
of Applied Philosophy, 36 (3): 506–522. (Scholar)
- Boorse, C., 1975, “On the Distinction Between Disease and Illness,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 5 (1): 49–68. [Available online.] (Scholar)
- Braveman, P., et al. 2011. “Health Disparities and Health
Equity: The Issue is Justice,” American Journal of Public
Health (Supplement 1), 101 (1): 149–155. (Scholar)
- Braveman, P. & S. Gruskin, 2003, “Defining Equity in
Health,” Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health,
57: 254–258. (Scholar)
- Brennan, J., 2018, “A Libertarian Case for Mandatory Vaccination,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 44: 37–43. (Scholar)
- Brock, D. W., 2002, “Priority to the Worse Off in Health-Care Resource Prioritization,” in Medicine and Social Justice: Essays on the Distribution of Health Care, R. Rhodes, M. Battin, and A. Silvers (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 362–372. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015, “Identified Versus Statistical
Lives,” Identified versus Statistical Lives: An
Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels, and N. Eyal
(eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: pp. 43–52 (Scholar)
- Brock, G. (ed.), 2013, Cosmopolitanism versus Non-Cosmopolitanism: Critiques, Defenses, Reconceptualizations, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, “Global Justice,” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), E.N.
Zalta (ed.), URL =
≶https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/justice-global/>. (Scholar)
- Broome, J., 1984, “Selecting People Randomly,” Ethics, 95: 38–55. (Scholar)
- Brown-Johnson, C.G. and J.J. Prochaska, 2015, “Shame-Based
Appeals in a Tobacco Control Public Health Campaign: Potential Harms
and Benefits,” Tobacco Control, 24 (5):
419–420. (Scholar)
- Broussard, G., L.S. Rubenstein, C. Robinson, et al.,
2019, “Challenges to ethical obligations and humanitarian
principles in conflict settings: a systematic
review,” International Journal of Humanitarian
Action, 4 (15): 1–13. (Scholar)
- Buchanan, A, 2013, The Heart of Human Rights, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Buchanan, D. R., 2008, “Autonomy, Paternalism, and Justice:
Ethical Priorities in Public Health,” American Journal of
Public Health, 98 (1): 15. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “Public Health Interventions: Ethical
Implications,” in The Oxford Handbook of Public Health
Ethics, ed. Mastroianni, A.C., J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass. New York:
Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Burris, S., 2008, “Stigma, Ethics and Policy: A Commentary
on Bayer’s ‘Stigma and the Ethics of Public Health: Not
Can We but Should We?’,” Social Science &
Medicine, 67: 473–475. (Scholar)
- Callahan, D., 2013, “Obesity: Chasing an Elusive Epidemic,” Hastings Center Report, 43 (1): 34–40. (Scholar)
- Caspar Hare, 2015, “Statistical People and Counterfactual
Indeterminacy,” Identified versus Statistical Lives: An
Interdisciplinary Perspective, Identified versus Statistical
Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels,
and N. Eyal (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: pp.
124–136. (Scholar)
- Childress, J. F., R. R. Faden, R. D. Gaare, L. O. Gostin, J. Kahn,
R. J. Bonnie, N. E. Kass, A. C. Mastroianni, J. D. Moreno, and P.
Nieburg, 2002, “Public Health Ethics: Mapping the
Terrain,” The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 30
(2): 170–178. (Scholar)
- Christakis, N. & J. Fowler, 2007, “The Collective
Dynamics of Smoking in a Large Social Network,” The New
England Journal of Medicine, 358 (21):
2249–2258. (Scholar)
- Christiano, T., 2013, “Authority,” Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/authority/>. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Democracy,” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition),
E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/democracy/>. (Scholar)
- Cochrane, J., 2015, “After the ACA: Freeing the Market for
Healthcare,” in The Future of Healthcare Reform in the
United States, ed. Anup Malani and Michael Shill, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press: pp. 161–201. (Scholar)
- Coggon, J., 2012, What Makes Health Public? A Critical Evaluation of Moral, Legal, and Political Claims in Public Health, Cambridge: Cambridge University Pres. (Scholar)
- Cohen, J. T., P. J. Neumann, and M. C. Weinstein, 2008,
“Does Preventive Care Save Money? Health Economics and the
Presidential Candidates,” The New England Journal of
Medicine, 358 (7): 661–663. (Scholar)
- Cohen, G., N. Daniels, and N. Eyal (eds.), 2015, Identified
versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective,
Cohen, G., N. Daniels, and N. Eyal, New York: Oxford University
Press. (Scholar)
- Cohen, J., and C. Sabel, 2006, “Extra Rempublicam Nulla Justia?” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 34 (2): 147–175. (Scholar)
- Conly, S., 2014, “Against Autonomy: Justifying Coercive Paternalism,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 40 (5): 349. (Scholar) (Scholar)
- Conly, S., 2014, “Against Autonomy: Justifying Coercive Paternalism,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 40 (5): 349. (Scholar)
- Cookson, R., C. McCabe, and A. Tsuchiya, 2008, Journal of
Medical Ethics, 34: 540–544. (Scholar)
- Cookson, R., M. Drummond, and H. Weatherly, 2009, “Explicit
Incorporation of Equity Considerations into Economic Evaluation of
Public Health Interventions,” Health Economics, Policy and
Law, 4 (2): 231–245. (Scholar)
- Coons, C., and M. Weber (eds.) 2014, Manipulation: Theory and Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (Scholar)
- Crawford, R., 1977, “You Are Dangerous to Your Health: The
Ideology and Politics of Victim Blaming,” International
Journal of Health Services, 7 (4): 663–680. (Scholar)
- Courtwright, A., 2013, “Stigmatization and Public Health Ethics,” Bioethics, 27 (2): 74–80. (Scholar)
- Daniels, N., 2002, “Accountability for Reasonableness:
Establishing a Fair Process for Priority Setting is Easier than
Agreeing on Principles,” BMJ, 321
(7272): 1300–1301. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “Equity and Population Health,” Hastings Center Report, 36 (4): 22–35. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, Just Health: Meeting Health Needs Fairly, New York: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Reasonable Disagreement about Identified vs. Statistical Victims,” Hastings Center Report, 42 (1): 35–45. (Scholar)
- –––, 2015,“Can There Be Moral Force to Favoring
to an Identified over a Statistical Life?” Identified versus
Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective,
Identified versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary
Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels, and N. Eyal (eds.), New York:
Oxford University Press: pp. 110–123. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019,“Reconciling Two Goals of Public
Health” (Scholar)
- Daniels, N., and J. Sabin, 1997, “Limits to Health Care: Fair Procedures, Democratic Deliberation, and the Legitimacy Problem for Insurers,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 26 (4): 303–350. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, Setting Limits Fairly: Learning to Share
Resources for Health, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Darwall, Stephen, 2006, The Second Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Daugherty Biddison, E., R. Faden, H. Gwon, D. Mareiniss, A.
Regenberg, M. Schoch-Spana, J. Schwartz, E. Toner, (2018), “Too
Many Patients… A Framework to Guide Statewide Allocation of
Scarce Mechanical Ventilation During Disasters” CHEST
(2018) 155 (4). (Scholar)
- Dawson, A., (ed.), 2011, Public Health Ethics, New York: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Dawson, A., and B. Jennings, 2012, “The Place of Solidarity
in Public Health Ethics,” Public Health Review, 34, 1:
65–79. (Scholar)
- Dawson, A., and M. Verweij, (eds.), 2007, Ethics, Prevention, and Public Health, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, “Public Health Ethics: A Manifesto,” Public Health Ethics, 1 (1): 1–2. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Public Health and Legitimacy: Or Why There is Still a Place for Substantive Work in Ethics,” Public Health Ethics, 7 (2): 95–97. (Scholar)
- Dees, R., 2018, “Public Health and Normative Public Goods,” Public Health Ethics, 11 (1): 20–26. (Scholar)
- Department of Health, 2009, Tackling Health Inequalities: 10
Years On, Publication No. 291444, London: Crown. (Scholar)
- Distefano, M. and J. Levin, 2019, “Does Incorporating
Cost-Effectiveness Analysis Into Prescribing Decisions Promote Drug
Access Equity,” AMA Journal of Ethics, 21 (8):
679–685. (Scholar)
- Dorfman, L., and L. Wallack, 2009, Moving From Them
to Us: Challenges in Reframing Violence Among Youth,
Berkeley Media Studies Group. (Scholar)
- Dworkin, G., 1981, “Taking Risks, Assessing Responsibility,” The Hastings Center Report, 11 (5): 26–31. (Scholar)
- Dworkin, G., 2005, “Paternalism,” The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta
(ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2005/entries/paternalism/>. (Scholar)
- Emanuel, E., 2002, “Patient v. Population: Resolving Ethical
Dilemmas Posed By Treating Patients as Members of Populations,”
in Ethical Dimensions of Health Policy, M. Danis and C.
Clancy and R. Churchill (eds.) Oxford: Oxford University Press: pp.
227–245. (Scholar)
- Emanuel, E., H. Schmidt, and A Steinmetz, eds., 2018,
Rationing and Allocation in Health Care: Essential Readings,
New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Emanuel, E., D. Wendler, J. Killen, and C. Grady, 2004,
“What Makes Clinical Research in Developing Countries Ethical?
The Benchmarks of Ethical Research,” The Journal of
Infectious Diseases, 189 (5): 930–937. (Scholar)
- Emerson, C.I., 2014, “The Moral Case for Eradication”
in. Disease Eradication in the 21st Century: Implications for
Global Health, Cochi, S.L., and W.R. Dowdle (ed.), Cambridge: MIT
Press: pp. 103–113. (Scholar)
- Emerson, C.I., P. Singer, 2010, “Is there an Ethical
Obligation to Complete Polio Eradication,” The Lancet,
375: 1340–1341. (Scholar)
- Engelen, B., 2019, “Ethical Criteria for Health-Promoting Nudges: A Case-by-Case Analysis,” The American Journal of Bioethics, 19 (5): 48–59. (Scholar)
- Epstein, R., 2004, “In Defense of the ‘Old’
Public Health,” Brooklyn Law Review: 69,
1421–1470. (Scholar)
- Estlund, D., 2007, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Eyal, N., 2015, “Concentrated Risk, the Coventry Blitz,
Chamberlain’s Cancer,” Identified versus Statistical
Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Identified versus
Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G.,
N. Daniels, and N. Eyal (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press:
pp. 94–109. (Scholar)
- Eyal, N., S. A. Hurst, O. F. Norheim, and D. Wikler, (eds.), 2013, Inequalities in Health: Concepts, Measures, and Ethics, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Faden, R. R., 1987, “Ethical Issues in Government Sponsored
Public Health Campaigns,” Health Education &
Behavior, 14 (1): 27–37. (Scholar)
- Faden, R., and R. Karron, 2009, “A Moral Obligation? Should
the U.S. Produce Enough H1N1 Flu Vaccine to Help Developing
Countries?,” Baltimore Sun, August 17, 2009,
[available online] (Scholar)
- Faden, R.R., N. Kass, and M. Powers, M. 1991, “Warrants for
Screening Programs: Public Health, Legal and Ethical
Frameworks,” in AIDS, Women and the Next Generation,
Faden, R., G. Geller, and M. Powers (eds.), Oxford University Press,
1991: pp. 3–26. (Scholar)
- Faden, R., S. Shebaya, and A. Siegel, 2019, “Public Health
Programs and Policies: Ethical Justifications,” in The
Oxford Handbook of Public Health Ethics, ed. Mastroianni, A.C.,
J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass. New York: Oxford University Press, pp.
21–32. (Scholar)
- FCC, 2000, Investigation into NORML Foundation’s Complaint
Against ABC, CBS, NBC, FOX, and WB, Publication No.
EB-00-IH-0078. (Scholar)
- Feinberg, J., 1986, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law,
Volume 3: Harm to Self, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Feudtner, C., and E. K. Marcuse, 2001, “Ethics and
Immunization Policy: Promoting Dialogue to Sustain Consensus,”
Pediatrics, 107 (5): 1158–1164. (Scholar)
- de Fine Licht, J., 2011, “Do We Really Want to Know? The
Potentially Negative Effect of Transparency in Decision Making on
Perceived Legitimacy,” Scandinavian Political Studies,
34 (3): 183–201. (Scholar)
- Flanigan, J., 2014a, “A Defense of Compulsory Vaccination,” HEC Forum, 26: 5–25. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014b, “The Perils of Public Health
Regulations,” Society, 51: 229–236. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, Pharmaceutical Freedom, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Fourie, C., and A. Rid (eds.), 2017, What Is Enough?: Sufficiency, Justice, and Health, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Freudenthal, E., “Ebola’s lost blood: row over samples flown
out of Africa as ‘big pharma’ set to cash in,” The
Telegraph, February 6, 2019. (Scholar)
- Frick, J., “Treatment versus Prevention in the Fight Against
HIV/AIDS and the Problem of Identified versus Statistical
Lives,” in Identified versus Statistical Lives: An
Interdisciplinary Perspective, Identified versus Statistical
Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels,
and N. Eyal (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: pp.
182–202. (Scholar)
- Friedman, A., 2008, “Beyond Accountability for Reasonableness,” Bioethics, 22 (2): 101–112. (Scholar)
- Gafni, A., 1991, “Willingness-to-Pay as A Measure of
Benefits: Relevant Questions in the Context of Public Decisionmaking
about Health Care Programs,” Medical Care, 29 (12):
1246–1252. (Scholar)
- Gaus, G., 2011, The Order of Public Reason : a Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World, New York: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Gaus, G., S. Courtland, and D. Schmidtz, 2018,
“Liberalism,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/liberalism/>. (Scholar)
- Geller, G., R. Dvoskin, C.L. Thio, P. Duggal, M.H. Lewis, T.C.
Bailey, A. Sutherland, D.A. Salmon, and J.P. Kahn, 2014,
“Genomics and infectious disease: a call to identify the
ethical, legal and social implications for public health and clinical
practice,” Genome Medicine, 6 (106): 1–13. (Scholar)
- Giubilini, A., 2019, The Ethics of Vaccination, Palgrave Macmillan. (Scholar)
- Gold, M.R., D. Stevenson, and D.G. Fryback. (2002). “HALYS
and QALYS and DALYS, Oh My: Similarities and Differences in Summary
Measures of Population Health,” Annual Review of Public
Health, 23(1): 115–134. (Scholar)
- Gold, M.R., J.E. Siegel, L.B. Russell, and M.C. Weinstein (eds.),
1996 Cost-Effectiveness in Health and Medicine, New York:
Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Goldberg, D., and Puhl, R, 2013, “Obesity Stigma: A Failed and Ethically Dubious Strategy,” Hastings Center Report (May-June) 2013, 43 (3): 5–6 (Scholar)
- Goodin, R., 1990, No Smoking: The Ethical Issues, Chicago: Chicago University Press. (Scholar)
- Goodman, E. P., 2006, “Stealth Marketing and Editorial
Integrity,” Texas Law Review, 85, 83–152. (Scholar)
- Goold, S.D., A.K. Biddle, G. Klipp, C.N. Hall, and M. Danis, 2005,
“Choosing Healthplans All Together: a deliberative exercise for
allocating limited health care resources,” J. Health Polit
Policy Law 30 (4): 563–602. (Scholar)
- Gostin, L. O., 2002, “Public Health Law in the Time of Terrorism,” Health Affairs, 21 (6): 79–93. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “The Model State Emergency Health Powers Act…” Health Matrix, 13 (1): 3–32. (Scholar)
- Gostin, L. O., 2012, “A Framework Convention on Global
Health: Health for All, Justice for All,” Journal of the
American Medical Association, 307 (19): 2087–2092. (Scholar)
- Gostin, L. O., and E. Friedman, 2013, “Towards a Framework
Convention on Global Health: A Transformative Agenda for Global Health
Justice,” Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law, and
Ethics, 13, 1–75. (Scholar)
- Grill, K., and K. Voigt, 2016, “The Case for Banning Cigarettes” Journal of Medical Ethics, 42: 293–301. (Scholar)
- Grover, A., B. Citro, M. Mankad, and F. Lander, 2012, “Pharmaceutical Companies and Global Lack of Access to Medicines: Strengthening Accountability Under the Right to Health,” The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 40 (2): 234–250. (Scholar)
- Grynbaum, M., and M. Connelly, 2012, “60% in City Oppose
Bloomberg’s Soda Ban, Poll Finds,” New York
Times, August 21, 2012,
[available online] (Scholar)
- Hanna, J., 2019, In Our Best Interest: A Defense of Paternalism, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Hardin, R., 2013, “The Free Rider Problem,” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Spring
2013 Edition URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/free-rider/> (Scholar)
- Hare, C., 2015, “Statistical People and Counter-Factual
Indeterminacy,” in Identified versus Statistical Lives: An
Interdisciplinary Perspective, Identified versus Statistical
Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels,
and N. Eyal (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: pp.
124–136. (Scholar)
- Hart, H.L.A., 1982, Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Hasman, A., and S. Holm, 2005, “Accountability for Reasonableness: Opening the Black Box of Process,” Health Care Analysis, 13 (4): 261–273. (Scholar)
- Hatzenbuehler, M., J.C. Phelan, and B. Link, 2013, “Stigma
as a Fundamental Cause of Population Health Inequalities,”
American Journal of Public Health, 103 (5):
813–821. (Scholar)
- ten Have, M., I.D. de Beaufort, J.P. Mackenbach, A van der Heide,
2010, “An overview of ethical frameworks in public health: can
they be supportive in the evaluation of programs to prevent
overweight?” BMC Public Health, 10 (638):
1–11. (Scholar)
- Hesslow, G., 1993, “Do We Need a Concept of Disease?”, Theoretical Medicine, 14: 1–14. (Scholar)
- Hoffman, S.J., and C. Tan, 2015, “Overview of Systematic Reviews on
the Health-Related Effects of Government Tobacco Control
Policies,” BMC Public Health, 15 (744): 1–11. (Scholar)
- Hofmann, B., 2010, “The Concept of Disease – Vague, Complex, or Just Indefinable?” Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy, 13 (1): 3–10. (Scholar)
- Holland, S., 2007, Public Health Ethics, Cambridge: Polity Press. (Scholar)
- Hollands, G. J., I. Shemilt, T. M. Marteau, S. A. Jebb, M. P.
Kelly, R. Nakamura, M. Suhrcke, and D. Ogilvie, 2013, “Altering
Micro-Environments to Change Population Health Behaviour: Towards an
Evidence Base for Choice Architecture Interventions,” BMC
Public Health, 13 (1): 1218. (Scholar)
- Hope, T., 2001, “Rationing and Lifesaving Treatments: Should Identifiable Patients Have Higher Priority?” Journal of Medical Ethics, 27: 179–185. (Scholar)
- Horne, L., 2019, Public Health, Public Goods, and Market Failure. Public Health Ethics, 12 (3): 287–292. (Scholar)
- Hughes, J., and T. Walker, 2009, “The Rule of Rescue in Clinical Practice,” Clinical Ethics, 4 (1): 50–54. (Scholar)
- Hunt, P., and UN Economic and Social Council, 2004, Report of
the Special Rapporteur on the Right of Everyone to the Enjoyment of
the Highest Attainable Standard of Physical and Mental Health, Paul
Hunt, Publication No. E/CN.4/2005/51. (Scholar)
- Hyder, A. A., B. Pratt, J. Ali, N. E. Kass, and N. Sewankambo,
2014, “The Ethics of Health Systems Research in Low and
Middle-Income Countries: A Call to Action,” Global Public
Health, 7: 1–15. (Scholar)
- Hyder, A. A., and M. W. Merritt, 2009, “Ancillary Care for
Public Health Research in Developing Countries,” Journal of
the American Medical Association, 302 (4): 429. (Scholar)
- Institute of Medicine (USA), 1988, The Future of Public
Health, Washington: National Academy Press. (Scholar)
- Institute of Medicine (USA), 2003, The Future of the
Public’s Health in the 21st Century, Washington: National
Academies Press. (Scholar)
- Jecker, N., 2015, “Rethinking Rescue Medicine,” The American Journal of Bioethics, 15 (2): 12–18. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “The Problem with Rescue Medicine,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 38 (1): 64–81. (Scholar)
- Jenni, K.E. and G. Lowenstein, 1997, Journal of Risk and
Uncertainty, 14: 235–257. (Scholar)
- Jennings, B., 2007, “Public Health and Civic Republicanism: Toward an Alternative Framework for Public Health Ethics,” in Ethics, Prevention, and Public Health, A. Dawson (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 30–58. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “Public Health and Liberty: Beyond the Millian Paradigm,” Public Health Ethics, 2 (2): 123–134. (Scholar)
- Jennings, B., and A. Dawson, 2015, “Solidarity in the Moral Imagination of Bioethics,” Hastings Center Report, 45 (5): 31–38. (Scholar)
- Johri, M., and O. F. Norheim, 2012, “Can Cost-Effectiveness
Analysis Integrate Concerns for Equity? Systematic Review,”
International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health
Care, 28 (2): 125–132. (Scholar)
- Jones, M. M., and R. Bayer, 2007, “Paternalism & Its
Discontents: Motorcycle Helmet Laws, Libertarian Values, and Public
Health,” American Journal of Public Health, 97
(2):208–217. (Scholar)
- Jonsen, A., 1986, “Bentham in a Box: Technology Assessment and Healthcare Allocation” Law, Medicine, and Healthcare Sep 14 (3–4): 172–174. (Scholar)
- Kamm, F., 2007, Intricate Ethics, Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harms, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Kappel, K., and P. Sandoe, 1992, “QALYs, Age and Fairness,” Bioethics, 6 (4): 297–316. (Scholar)
- Kass, N. E., 2001, “An Ethics Framework for Public
Health,” American Journal of Public Health, 91 (11):
1776–1782. (Scholar)
- Kettner, J., and J. Ball, 2004, Reducing Health Disparities:
Roles of the Health Sector: Discussion Paper, Ottawa, Ontario:
Public Health Agency of Canada. (Scholar)
- Khader, S., 2009, “Adaptive Preferences and Procedural
Autonomy,” Journal of Human Development and
Capabilities, 10, (2): pp. 169–187. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “ Must Theorising about
Adaptive Preferences Deny Women’s Agency?” Journal of
Applied Philosophy, 29 (4): 302–317. (Scholar)
- Kim, S.-H., and Shanahan, J. 2003, “Stigmatizing Smokers:
Public Sentiment toward Cigarette Smoking and its Relationship to
Smoking Behaviors,” Journal of Health
Communication, 8(4): 343–367. (Scholar)
- Knight, C., 2015, “Abandoning the Abandonment Objection: Luck Egalitarian Arguments for Insurance,” Res Publica, 21: 119–135. (Scholar)
- Krauthammer, C., 2000, January 21, “A Network
Sellout,” Washington Post, p. A29. (Scholar)
- Krubiner, C., and R. Faden, 2017, “A Matter of Morality:
Embedding Ethics and Equity in the Health Benefits Policy,” in
What’s In, What’s Out: Designing Benefits for
Universal Health Coverage, A. Glassman, U. Giedion, P.C., Smith
(eds.)Washington, DC: Center for Global Development. (Scholar)
- Kurtz, H., and S. Waxman, 2000, January 14, “White House Cut
Anti-Drug Deal with TV,” Washington Post, p. A1. (Scholar)
- Kymlicka, W., 1992, “The Rights of Minority Cultures: Reply to Kukathas,” Political Theory, 20 (1): 140–146. (Scholar)
- Larmore, C., 2001, “A Critique of Philip Pettit’s
Republicanism,” Philosophical Issues, 11:
229–43. (Scholar)
- Latham, S.R., 2016, “Political Theory, Values, and Public Health,” Public Health Ethics, 9 (2): 139–149. (Scholar)
- Lee, L., 2012, “Public Health Ethics Theory: Paths to Convergence,” Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics Spring: 85–98. (Scholar)
- Lee, L., C. Heilig, and A. White, (2012), “Ethical
Justification for Conducting Public Health Surveillance Without
Patient Consent,” American Journal of Public Health,
102 (1): 38–44. (Scholar)
- Lee, L.M., 2019, “Public Health Surveillance: Ethical
Considerations,” in The Oxford Handbook of Public Health
Ethics, ed. Mastroianni, A.C., J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass. New York:
Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Levy, N., 2017, “Nudges in a Post-Truth World,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 43 (8): 495–500. (Scholar)
- Liao, M., 2015, The Right to Be Loved, New York: Oxford
University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “Human Rights and Public Health
Ethics,” in The Oxford Handbook of Public Health Ethics
ed. Mastroianni, A.C., J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass. New York: Oxford
University Press pp. 47–56. (Scholar)
- Link, B. G., and J.C. Phelan, (2001), “Conceptualizing
Stigma,” Annual Review of Sociology, 27:
363–385. (Scholar)
- Lipscomb, J., M. Drummond, D. Fryback, M. Gold, and D. Revicki,
2009, “Retaining, and Enhancing, the QALY,” Value in
Health, 12 (s1): 18–26. (Scholar)
- List, C. and L. Valentini, 2016, “Freedom as Independence,” Ethics, 126: 1043–1074. (Scholar)
- Lovett, F., 2001, “Domination: A Preliminary Analysis,” The Monist, 84: 98–112. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Republicanism,” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), E.N.
Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/republicanism/>. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Non-Domination,”
in The Oxford Handbook of Freedom, D. Schmidtz and C.E.
Pavel (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Mack, E. and G. F. Gaus, 2004, “Classical Liberalism and
Libertarianism: The Liberty Tradition,” in The Handbook of
Political Theory, Gerald F. Gaus and Chandran Kukathas (eds.),
London: Sage, 115–130. (Scholar)
- Mann, J. M., 1996, “Health and Human
Rights,” BMJ: 312 (7036): 924. (Scholar)
- Mann, J. M., L. Gostin, S. Gruskin, T. Brennan, Z. Lazzarini, and
H. V. Fineberg, 1994, “Health and Human Rights,”
Health and Human Rights, 1 (1): 6–23. (Scholar)
- Marckmann, G., H. Schmidt, N. Sofaer, and D. Strech. (2015).
“Putting Public Health Ethics into Practice: A Systematic
Framework,” Frontiers in Public Health, 3
(23): 1–7. (Scholar)
- Marmot, M.M., 2005, “Social Determinants of Health
Inequalities,” The Lancet, 365: 1099–1104. (Scholar)
- Mason, H., R. Baker, and C. Donaldson, 2011, “Understanding
Public Preferences for Prioritizing Health Care Interventions in
England: Does the Type of Health Gain Matter?,” Journal of
Health Services Research & Policy, 16 (2): 81–89. (Scholar)
- Martin, D.K., M. Giacomini, and P.A. Singer, “Fairness,
accountability for reasonableness, and the views of priority setting
decision-makers,” Health Policy, 61 (3):
279–90. (Scholar)
- Mastroianni, A.C., J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass (eds.), 2019, The
Oxford Handbook of Public Health Ethics, New York: Oxford
University Press. (Scholar)
- McKie, J., J. Richardson, “The Rule of Rescue,”
Social Science and Medicine, 2003, 56 (12):
2407–2419. (Scholar)
- McLeroy, K. R., D. Bibeau, A. Steckler, and K. Glanz, 1988,
“An Ecological Perspective on Health Promotion Programs,”
Health Education & Behavior, 15 (4): 351–377. (Scholar)
- Mello, M. M., 2009, “New York City’s War on Fat,”
The New England Journal of Medicine, 360 (19):
2015–2020. (Scholar)
- Menard, J.F., 2010, “A Nudge for Public Health
Ethics,” Public Health Ethics, 3: 229–238. (Scholar)
- Menzel, P., M. R. Gold, E. Nord, J. L. Pinto-Prades, J.
Richardson, and P. Ubel, 1999, “Toward A Broader View of Values
in Cost-Effectiveness Analysis of Health,” The Hastings
Center Report, 29 (3): 7–15. (Scholar)
- Mill, J. S., 1869, On Liberty & Other Essays (2nd
edition), J. Gray (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press,
1998. (Scholar)
- Miller, D., 2017, “Justice,” in Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.)
URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/justice/> (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, National Responsibility and Global Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Miller, E., P. Waight, N. Gay, M. Ramsay, J. Vurdien, P.
Morgan-Capner, L. Hesketh, D. Brown, P. Tookey, and C. Peckham, 1997,
“The Epidemiology of Rubella in England and Wales Before and
After the 1994 Measles and Rubella Vaccination Campaign: Fourth Joint
Report from the PHLS and the National Congenital Rubella Surveillance
Programme,” Communicable Disease Report Review, 7 (2):
R26–32. (Scholar)
- Millum, J., and E. J. Emanuel (eds.), 2012, Global Justice and Bioethics, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Moles, A, 2015, “Nudging for Liberals,” Social Theory and Practice, 41 (4): 644–667. (Scholar)
- Moyn, S., 2018 Not Enough: Human Rights in an Unequal
World, Cambridge: Belknap Press. (Scholar)
- Muldoon, R., 2018, “Norms, Nudges, and Autonomy” in the Palgrave Handbook of Philosophy and Public Policy, ed. David Boonin, Palgrave-Macmillan: 225–233. (Scholar)
- Murphy, D., “Concepts of Disease and Health,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/health-disease/> (Scholar)
- Navin, M., 2016, Values and Vaccine Refusal: Hard Questions in Ethics, Epistemology, and Health Care, New York: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Nestle, M., and M. Bittman, 2015, Soda Politics: Taking on Big
Soda (And Winning), New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- New York Times, 2012, “The New York Times’s Public
Opinion Poll,” New York Times, August 21, 2012,
[available online]. (Scholar)
- Nickel, J., 2019, “Human Rights,” The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 Edition) E.N Zalta (ed.),
URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/rights-human/>. (Scholar)
- Nielsen, M.E.J and J.D. Jensen, 2016, “Sin Taxes,
Paternalism, and Justifiability to All: Can Paternalistic Taxes Be
Justified on a Public Reason-Sensitive Account?” Journal of
Social Philosophy, 47 (1): 55–69. (Scholar)
- Noggle, R., 2018, “Manipulation, Salience, and Nudges,” Bioethics, 32: 164–170. (Scholar)
- Nord, E., 1999, “Towards Cost-Value Analysis in Health Care?,” Health Care Analysis, 7 (2): 167–175. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Concerns for the Worse Off:
Fair Innings Versus Severity,” Social Science &
Medicine, 60 (2): 257–263. (Scholar)
- Nuffield Council on Bioethics, 2007, Public Health: Ethical
Issues, Cambridge: Cambridge Publishers. (Scholar)
- Nussbaum, M., 2004, Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, Frontiers of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Omer, S. B., D. A. Salmon, W. A. Orenstein, M. P. deHart, and N.
Halsey, 2009, “Vaccine Refusal, Mandatory Immunization, and the
Risks of Vaccine-Preventable Diseases,” The New England
Journal of Medicine, 360 (19): 1981–1988. (Scholar)
- O’Neill, O., “Public Health or Clinical Ethics: Thinking Beyond Borders,” Ethics and International Affairs 16 (2): 35–45. (Scholar)
- Orenstein, W. A., and A. R. Hinman, 1999, “The Immunization
System in the United States – The Role of School Immunization
Laws,” Vaccine, 17 (Supplement 3): S19–S24. (Scholar)
- Otsuka, M., 2015, “Risking Life and Limb: How to Discount
Harms by their Improbability,” Identified versus Statistical
Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Identified versus
Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G.,
N. Daniels, and N. Eyal (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: pp.
77–93. (Scholar)
- Ottersen, T., D. Mbilinyi, O. Mæstad, and O.F. Norheim,
2008, “Distribution Matters: Equity Considerations among Health
Planners in Tanzania,” Health Policy, 85 (2):
218–227. (Scholar)
- Ottersen, T., O.F. Norheim, F. Berhane, B. Chitah, R. Cookson, N.
Daniels, et al., 2014, “Making Fair Choices on the Path to Universal
Health Coverage,” Final report of the WHO Consultative Group on
Equity and Universal Health Coverage, Geneva: World Health
Organization. (Scholar)
- Ottersen, T., O. Mæstad, and O.F. Norheim, 2014,
“Lifetime QALY Prioritarianism in Priority Setting:
Quantification of the Inherent Trade-Off,” Cost
Effectiveness and Resource Allocation, 12(1),
first online 14 Jan 2014. doi: 10.1186/1478-7547-12-2 (Scholar)
- Parfit, D, 1987, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon
Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997, “Equality and Priority,” Ratio, 10(3): 202–221. (Scholar)
- Persad, G., 2019, “Justice and Public Health” in The Oxford Handbook of Public Health Ethics, Mastroianni, A.C., J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 33–46. (Scholar)
- Persad, G., A. Werthehimer, E.J. Emanuel, 2009, “Principles
for Allocation of Scarce Medical Interventions,” The
Lancet, 373 (9661): 423–431 (Scholar)
- Peter, F., “Political Legitimacy,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/legitimacy/> (Scholar)
- Petrini, C., 2010, “Theoretical Models and Operational
Frameworks in Public Health Ethics,” Int. J. Environ. Res.
Public Health, 7 (1): 189–202. (Scholar)
- Pettit, P, 1997, Republicanism : a Theory of Freedom and Government, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, On the People’s Terms: A
Republican Theory and Model of Democracy, Oxford: Oxford
University Press. (Scholar)
- Pogge, T. W., 2002, “Responsibilities for Poverty-Related Ill Health,” Ethics & International Affairs, 16 (2): 71–81. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “Moral Universalism and Global Economic Justice” in Politics, Philosophy, Economics, 29 No. 1. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, Freedom from Poverty as a Human
Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor?, New York: Oxford
University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms, 2nd edition, Cambridge: Polity Press. (Scholar)
- Pomeranz, J.L., 2012, “Advance Policy Options to Regulate
Sugar-Sweetened Beverages to Support Public Health,” Journal
of Public Health Policy, 33 (1): 75–88. (Scholar)
- Powers, M., forthcoming in 2020, “Ethical Challenges Posed
by Climate Change: an Overview,” in Moral Theory and Climate
Change, D. Miller and B. Eggleston, (ed.), London; Taylor &
Francis/Routledge. (Scholar)
- Powers, M., and R. Faden, 2006, Social Justice, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, Structural Injustice: Power, Advantage, and Human Rights, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Powers, M., R. Faden, and Y. Saghai, 2012, “Liberty, Mill,
and the Framework of Public Health Ethics,” Public Health
Ethics, 5 (1): 6–15. (Scholar)
- Pratt, B., and A. Hyder, 2015, “Reinterpreting Responsiveness for Health Systems Research in Low and Middle-Income Countries,” Bioethics, 29 (6): 379–88. (Scholar)
- Pugh, J., 2014, “Coercive Paternalism and Backdoor Perfectionism,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 40 (5): 350–351. (Scholar)
- Quigley, M., 2013, “Nudging for Health: On Public Policy and
Designing Choice Architecture,” Medical Law Review, 21
(4): 588–621. (Scholar)
- Quong, J., 2011, Liberalism Without Perfection, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Public Reason,” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition), E.N.
Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/public-reason/>. (Scholar)
- Radoilska, L., 2009, “Public Health Ethics and Liberalism,” Public Health Ethics,, 2 (2): 135–145. (Scholar)
- Railton, P., 2015, “‘Dual-Process’ Models of the
Mind and the ‘Identifiable Victim Effect,” Identified
versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective,
Identified versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary
Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels, and N. Eyal (eds.), New York:
Oxford University Press: pp. 24–40. (Scholar)
- Rajczi, A., 2016, “Liberalism and Public Health Ethics,” Bioethics, 30 (2): 96–108. (Scholar)
- Rawls, J., 1971, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 1993, Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press. (Scholar)
- Reich, R., 2018, Just Giving: Why Philanthropy is Failing Democracy and How it Can Do Better, Princeton:Princeton University Press (Scholar)
- Reichert, T. A., N. Sugaya, D. S. Fedson, W. P. Glezen, L.
Simonsen, and M. Tashiro, 2001, “The Japanese Experience with
Vaccinating Schoolchildren Against Influenza,”The New
England Journal of Medicine, 344 (12): 889–896. (Scholar)
- Resnik, D.B., 2015, “Food and Beverage Policies and Public Health Ethics,” Health Care Analysis, 23: 122–133. (Scholar)
- Roberts, M.A., 2019, “The Non-Identity Problem,”
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019
Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/nonidentity-problem/> (Scholar)
- Roberts, M.J. and M.R. Reich. (2002). “Ethical Analysis in
Public Health” The Lancet, 359 (9311):
1055–1059. (Scholar)
- Robeyns, I., 2016, “The Capability Approach,” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), E.N.
Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/capability-approach/> (Scholar)
- Robeznieks, A., 2020, “Doctors Demand Presidential Action on
Climate Change,” American Medical Association, 10 Jan 2020,
available online. (Scholar)
- Rose, G., 1985, “Sick Individuals and Sick
Populations,” International Journal of Epidemiology, 14
(1): 32–38. (Scholar)
- Rose, G., K.T. Khaw, and M. Marmot, 2008, Rose’s
Strategy of Preventive Medicine, New York: Oxford University
Press. (Scholar)
- Rubincam, C., and S. Naysmith, “Unexpected Agency:
Participation as a Bargaining Chip for the Poor,” Health and
Human Rights in Practice, 11 (1): 87–92. (Scholar)
- Ruger, J.P., 2010, Health and Social Justice, New York:
Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Russell, L. B., 1986, Is Prevention Better than Cure?,
Washington: Brookings Institution Press. (Scholar)
- Sabik, L.M., and R.K. Lie, “Priority Setting in Health Care: Lessons from The Experiences of Eight Countries,” International Journal for Equity in Health, 7 (4): 1–13. (Scholar)
- Saghai, Y., 2013a, “The Concept of Nudge and its Moral Significance: A Reply to Ashcroft, Bovens, Dworkin, Welch and Wertheimer,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 39: 499–501. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013b, “Salvaging the Concept of
Nudge,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 39: 487–493. (Scholar)
- Schroeder, S.A., 2017 “Value Choices in Summary Measures of Population Health,” Public Health Ethics, 10 (2): 176–187. (Scholar)
- Segall, S., 2010, Health, Luck, and Justice, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Selgeid, M., 2009, “A Moderate Pluralist Approach to Public Health Policy and Ethics,” Public Health Ethics, 2 (2): 195–205. (Scholar)
- Schmidt, H., S. Stock, and T. Doran, 2012, Moving Forward with
Wellness Incentives Under the Affordable Care Act: Lessons from
Germany, Commonwealth Fund. (Scholar)
- Schwappach, D. L. B., 2007, “The Economic Evaluation of
Prevention–Let’s Talk about Values and the Case of
Discounting,” International Journal of Public Health,
52 (6): 335–336. (Scholar)
- Sedyaningsih E.R., S. Isfandari S, T. Soendoro et al., 2008,
“Towards mutual trust, transparency and equity in virus sharing
mechanism: the avian influenza case of Indonesia,” Annals of
the Academy of Medicine Singapore, 37 (6): 482–88. (Scholar)
- Shebaya, S., A. Sutherland, O. Levine, and R. Faden, 2010, “Alternatives to National Average Income Data as Eligibility Criteria for International Subsidies: A Social Justice Perspective,” Developing World Bioethics, 10 (3): 141–149. (Scholar)
- Sher, G., 2017, “How Bad Is it To Be Dominated?”, in
Me, You, Us, New York: Oxford University Press, pp.
88–108. (Scholar)
- Shiffrin, S., 2000, “Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 29 (3): 205–250. (Scholar)
- Siegler, M. & A. Moss, 1991, “Should Alcoholics Compete
Equally for Liver Transplantation,” Journal of the American
Medical Association, 265 (10): 1295–1298. (Scholar)
- Silverman, W.A. and Chalmers, I., 2001, “Casting and Drawing
Lots: A Time Honoured Way of Dealing with Uncertainty and Ensuring
Fairness,” BMJ, 323:
1467–68. (Scholar)
- Skinner, Q., 1998, Liberty Before Liberalism,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008. “Freedom as the Absence of Arbitrary Power,” in Republicanism and Political Theory, C. Laborde and J. Maynor (eds.), Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing. (Scholar)
- Slote, M., 2015, “Why Not Empathy?” Identified
versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective,
Identified versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary
Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels, and N. Eyal (eds.), New York:
Oxford University Press: pp. 150–158. (Scholar)
- Small, D., 2015, “On the Psychology of the Identifiable
Victim Effect,” Identified versus Statistical Lives: An
Interdisciplinary Perspective, Identified versus Statistical
Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels,
and N. Eyal (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: pp.
13–22. (Scholar)
- Soares, M. O., 2012, “Is the QALY Blind, Deaf and Dumb to
Equity? NICE’s Considerations Over Equity,” BMJ, 101
(1): 17–31. (Scholar)
- Soccia, D., 2019, “Paternalism and Nudges,” Economics and Philosophy, 35 (1): 79–102. (Scholar)
- Sreenivasan, G., 2012, “A Human Right to Health? Some Inconclusive Scepticism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 86(1): 239–265. (Scholar)
- ––2016, “Health Care and Human Rights: Against
the Split Duty Gambit,” Theoretical Medicine and
Bioethics, 37(4): 343–364. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Justice, Inequality, and
Health,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall
2018 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/justice-inequality-health/> (Scholar)
- Stein, M.S., 2002, “The Distribution of Lifesaving Medical Resources: Equality, Life Expectancy, and Choice Behind the Veil,” Social Philosophy and Policy, 19: 212–45. (Scholar)
- Stoljar, Natalie, 2018, “Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/feminism-autonomy/>. (Scholar)
- Sugaya, N., 2014, “A Review of the Indirect Protection of
Younger Children and the Elderly Through a Mass Influenza Vaccination
Program in Japan,” Expert Review of Vaccines, 0:
1–8. (Scholar)
- Sugerman, D. E., A. E. Barskey, M. G. Delea, I. R. Ortega-Sanchez,
D. Bi, K. J. Ralston, P. A. Rota, K. Waters-Montijo, and C. W.
LeBaron, 2010, “Measles Outbreak in a Highly Vaccinated
Population, San Diego, 2008: Role of the Intentionally
Undervaccinated,” Pediatrics, 125 (4):
747–755. (Scholar)
- Sunstein, C. R., 2013, “The Storrs Lectures: Behavioral
Economics and Paternalism,” Yale Law Journal, 122:
1826–2082. (Scholar)
- Tasioulas, J., and E. Vayena, 2015a, “Getting Human Rights
Right in Global Health Policy,” The Lancet,
385(9978): e42–4. doi: 10.1016/s0140-6736(14)61418-5 (Scholar)
- –––, 2015b, “Just Global Health:
Integrating Human Rights and Common Goods,” in The Oxford
Handbook of Global Justice, T. Brooks (ed.), New York: Oxford
University Press. [publication forthcoming] (Scholar)
- Taylor, H.A., 2019, “Overview of Ethics and How Public
Health Does its Work,” in The Oxford Handbook of Public
Health Ethics, ed. Mastroianni, A.C., J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass. New
York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Thaler, R. H., and C. R. Sunstein, 2003, “Libertarian
Paternalism,” American Economic Review, 93 (2):
175–179. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008, Nudge, New Haven: Yale
University Press. (Scholar)
- Thomas, J. C., M. Sage, J. Dillenberg, and V. J. Guillory, 2002,
“A Code of Ethics for Public Health,” American Journal
of Public Health, 92 (7): 1057–1059. (Scholar)
- Thompson, J. W., S. Tyson, P. Card-Higginson, R. F. Jacobs, J. G.
Wheeler, P. Simpson, J. E. Bost, K. W. Ryan, and D. A. Salmon, 2007,
“Impact of Addition of Philosophical Exemptions on Childhood
Immunization Rates,” American Journal of Preventive
Medicine, 32 (3): 194–201. (Scholar)
- Ubel, P. A., 1999, “How Stable Are People’s Preferences for
Giving Priority to Severely Ill Patients?,” Social Science
& Medicine, 49 (7): 895–903. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, Free Market Madness: Why Human
Nature Is At Odds With Economics – and Why It Matters,
Boston: Harvard Business School Press. (Scholar)
- Unguru, Y., M. DeCamp, C. Fernandez, R. Faden, and S. Joffe,
“Chemotherapy Drug Shortages in Pediatric Oncology: A Consensus
Statement” Pediatrics, 133(3) (2014): 1–9. (Scholar)
- United Nations General Assembly, 1948, Universal Declaration
of Human Rights, G.A. res 217A (III), U.N. Doc A/810 at 71. (Scholar)
- Upshur, R, 2002, “Principles for the Justification of Public
Health Intervention,” Canadian Journal of Public
Health,, 93 (2): 101–103. (Scholar)
- Uscher-Pines, L., P. S. Duggan, J. P. Garoon, R. A. Karron, and R. R. Faden, 2007, “Planning for an Influenza Pandemic: Social Justice and Disadvantaged Groups,” Hastings Center Report, 37 (4): 32–39. (Scholar)
- Vallier, K., 2018, “Public Justification,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/justification-public/>. (Scholar)
- Venkatapuram, S., 2011, Health Justice: An Argument from the Capabilities Approach, Cambridge: Polity Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2019, “Health Disparities and the Social
Determinants of Health,” in The Oxford Handbook of Public
Health Ethics, ed. Mastroianni, A.C., J.P. Kahn, N.E. Kass. New
York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Verweij, M., “How (Not) to Argue for the Rule of Rescue: Claims of Individuals versus Group Solidarity,” Identified versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Identified versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, Cohen, G., N. Daniels, and N. Eyal (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press: pp. 137–149. (Scholar)
- Verweij, M., and A. Dawson, 2007, “The Meaning of
‘Public’ in Public Health,” in Dawson, A. and M.
Verweij, (eds.), Ethics, Prevention and Public Health,
Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Viens, A.M., 2016 “Public Health and Political Theory: The Importance of Taming Individualism,” Public Health Ethics, 9 (2): 136–138. (Scholar)
- Wall, S., 2001, “Freedom, Interference, and
Domination,” Political Studies, 49:
216–30. (Scholar)
- Weinstock, D., 2016, “Can Republicanism Tame Public Health,” Public Health Ethics, 9 (2): 125–133. (Scholar)
- Whitehead, S. J., and S. Ali, 2010, “Health Outcomes in
Economic Evaluation: The QALY and Utilities,” British
Medical Bulletin, 96 (1): 5–21. (Scholar)
- Wikler, D., 1987, “Who Should Be Blamed for Being
Sick?” Health Education Quarterly, 14 (1):
11–25. (Scholar)
- –––, 2002, “Personal and Social Responsibility for Health,” Ethics and International Affairs, 15 (2): 47–55. (Scholar)
- Wikler, D., and D. W. Brock, 2007, “Population-Level Bioethics: Mapping A New Agenda,” in Ethics, Prevention, and Public Health, A. Dawson, and M. Verweij (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, p. 78. (Scholar)
- Wilkinson, R.G., 2005, The Impact of Inequality: How to Make Sick Societies Healthier, Abindgdon: Routledge. (Scholar)
- Wilkinson, R.G., and K.E. Pickett, 2006, “Income inequality
and population health: a review and explanation of the
evidence,” Social Science & Medicine, 62 (7):
1768–84. (Scholar)
- Williams, A., 2001, “The ‘Fair Innings Argument’
Deserves a Fairer Hearing! Comments by Alan Williams on Nord and
Johannesson,” Health Economics, 10 (7):
583–585. (Scholar)
- Wolff, J., 2012, “Global Justice and Health: The Basis of
the Global Health Duty,” in Global Justice and
Bioethics, J. Millum and E. J. Emanuel, (eds.), New York: Oxford
University Press, pp. 78–101. (Scholar)
- Wolff, J., and A. de-Shalit, 2007, Disadvantage, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)