Linked bibliography for the SEP article "Instrumental Rationality" by Niko Kolodny and John Brunero
This is an automatically generated and experimental page
If everything goes well, this page should display the bibliography of the aforementioned article as it appears in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, but with links added to PhilPapers records and Google Scholar for your convenience. Some bibliographies are not going to be represented correctly or fully up to date. In general, bibliographies of recent works are going to be much better linked than bibliographies of primary literature and older works. Entries with PhilPapers records have links on their titles. A green link indicates that the item is available online at least partially.
This experiment has been authorized by the editors of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The original article and bibliography can be found here.
- Andreou, C., 2005, “The Voices of Reason,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 42(1): 33–45. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “Might Intentions Be the Only Source of Practical Imperatives?,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 9(3): 311–325. (Scholar)
- Anscombe, E., 1957, Intention, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Archer, A., 2018, “Trying Cognitivism: A Defense of the Strong Belief Thesis,” Theoria, 84(2): 140–156. (Scholar)
- Beardman, S., 2007, “The Special Status of Instrumental Reasons,” Philosophical Studies, 124(2): 255–287. (Scholar)
- Bedke, M., 2009, “The Iffiest Oughts: A Guise of Reasons Account of End-Given Conditionals,” Ethics, 119(4): 672–698. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, “Ends to Means: A Probability-Raising Account of Means and the Weight of Reasons to Take Them,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 12(1): 6–28. (Scholar)
- Bennett, J., 1983, “Positive and Negative Relevance,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 20(2): 185–194. (Scholar)
- Binkley, R., 1965, “A Theory of Practical Reason,” The Philosophical Review, 74(4): 423–448. (Scholar)
- Bratman, M., 1987, Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009a, “Intention, Belief, and Instrumental Rationality,” in D. Sobel and S. Wall (eds.), Reasons for Action, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 13–36. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009b, “Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical,” in S. Robertson (ed.), Spheres of Reason: New Essays in the Philosophy of Normativity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 29–62. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009c, “Intention, Practical Rationality, and Self-Governance,” Ethics, 119(3): 411–443. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009d, “Intention Rationality,” Philosophical Explorations, 12(3): 227–242. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, Planning, Time and Self-Governance: Essays in Practical Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Broome, J., 1997, “Reason and Motivation,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 71: 131–146. (Scholar)
- –––, 1999, “Normative Requirements,” Ratio, 12(3): 398–419. (Scholar)
- –––, 2001, “Are intentions reasons? And how should we cope with incommensurable values?,” in C. Morris and A. Ripstein (eds.), Practical Rationality and Preference: Essays for David Gauthier, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 98–120. (Scholar)
- –––, 2003, “Practical Reasoning,” in
J. Bermùdez and A. Millar (eds.), Reason and Nature: Essays
in the Theory of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
pp. 85–112. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005a, “Does Rationality Give Us
Reasons?,” Philosophical Issues, 15:
321–337. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005b, “Have We Reason to Do as Rationality Requires?—A Comment on Raz,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, Symposium 1: 1–8. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008a, “Is Rationality
Normative?,” Disputatio, 11: 153–171. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008b, “Reply to Southwood, Kearns and Star, and Cullity,” Ethics, 119: 96–108. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “The Unity of Reasoning?,” in S. Robertson (ed.), Spheres of Reason: New Essays in the Philosophy of Normativity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 62–92. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, Rationality Through Reasoning, Oxford: Wiley Blackwell. (Scholar)
- Brunero, J., 2005a, “Instrumental Rationality and
Carroll’s Tortoise,” Ethical Theory and Moral
Practice, 8: 557–569. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005b, “Two Approaches to Instrumental Rationality and Belief Consistency,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 1(1): 1–20. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Are Intentions Reasons?” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 88(4): 424–444. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “Against Cognitivism about
Practical Rationality,” Philosophical Studies, 146(3):
311–325. (Scholar)
- –––, 2010, “Self-governance, Means-end Coherence, and Unalterable Ends,” Ethics, 120(3): 579–591. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012, “Instrumental Rationality, Symmetry and Scope,” Philosophical Studies, 157(1): 125–140. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Cognitivism about Practical Rationality,” Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Volume 9), Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 18–44. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, Instrumental Rationality: The Normativity of Means-Ends Coherence, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Carroll, L., 1895, “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles,” Mind, 4(14): 278–80. (Scholar)
- Cheng-Guajardo, L., 2014, “The Normative Requirement of Means-end Rationality and Modest Bootstrapping,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 17(3): 487–503; first published online 2013. doi:10.1007/s10677-013-9455-y (Scholar)
- Cullity, G., 2008, “Decisions, Reasons, and Rationality,” Ethics, 119(1): 57–95. (Scholar)
- Darwall, S., 1983, Impartial Reason, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. (Scholar)
- Davidson, D., 2004, “Incoherence and Irrationality” in Problems of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 189–98. (Scholar)
- Dreier, J., 2001, “Humean Doubts about Categorical Imperatives,” in E. Millgram (ed.) Varieties of Practical Reasoning, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 27–49. (Scholar)
- Ellis, S., 2008, “The Varieties of Instrumental Rationality,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46(2): 199–220. (Scholar)
- Fink, J., forthcoming, “The Essence of Structural
Irrationality: The Impossibility of Attitudinal Success,”
Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy. (Scholar)
- Finlay, S., 2009, “Against All Reason? Skepticism About the Instrumental Norm,” in Charles Pigden (ed.), Hume, Motivation and Virtue, New York: Palgrave MacMillan, pp. 155–178. (Scholar)
- Fogal, D., 2018, “On the Scope, Jurisdiction, and Application of Rationality and the Law,” Problema, 12: 21–57. (Scholar)
- –––, 2020, “Rational Requirements and the Primacy of Pressure,” Mind, 129(516): 1033–1070. (Scholar)
- Fogal, D. & A. Worsnip, 2021, “Which Reasons? Which Rationality?” Ergo, 8(11): 306–343 (Scholar)
- Foot, P., 1972, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” The Philosophical Review, 81(3): 305–316. (Scholar)
- Fullhart, S., and C. Martinez, forthcoming, “Coherence as Joint Satisfiability,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy. (Scholar)
- Gertken, J. and B. Kiesewetter, 2021, “How Do Reasons Transmit to Non-Necessary Means?” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 99(2): 271–285. (Scholar)
- Greenspan, P., 1975, “Conditional Oughts and Hypothetical Imperatives,” The Journal of Philosophy, 72(10): 259–276. (Scholar)
- Grice, P., 1971, “Intention and uncertainty,”
Proceedings of the British Academy, 57: 263–279. (Scholar)
- Hampshire, S. and H. L. A. Hart, 1958, “Decision, Intention, and Uncertainty,” Mind, 67: 1–12. (Scholar)
- Hampton, J., 1995, “Does Hume have an Instrumental Conception of Practical Reason?,” Hume Studies, 21(1): 57–74. (Scholar)
- –––, 1998, The Authority of Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Harcourt, E., 2004, “Instrumental Desires, Instrumental Rationality,” in Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 78(1): 111–130. (Scholar)
- Harman, G., 1976, “Practical Reasoning,” Review of
Metaphysics, 29(3): 431–463. (Scholar)
- –––, 1986, Change in View: Principles of Reasoning, Cambridge: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Hill, T., 1973, “The Hypothetical Imperative,” The Philosophical Review, 82(4): 429–450. (Scholar)
- –––, 1992, Dignity and Practical Reason in
Kant’s Moral Theory, New York: Cornell University
Press. (Scholar)
- Holton, R., 2008, “Partial Belief, Partial Intention,” Mind, 117(1): 27–58. (Scholar)
- Hubin, D., 1999, “What’s Special about
Humeanism,” Noûs, 33(1): 30–45. (Scholar)
- –––, 2001, “The Groundless Normativity of Instrumental Rationality,” The Journal of Philosophy, 98(9): 445–468. (Scholar)
- Hume, D., 1739–40, Treatise of Human Nature. L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), 2nd. ed., revised by P.H. Nidditch, Oxford: Clarendon, 1975. (Scholar)
- Jackson, F. and R. Pargetter, 1986, “Ought, Options, and Actualism,” Philosophical Review, 95(2): 233–255. (Scholar)
- Jollimore, T., 2005, “Why Is Instrumental Rationality Rational?,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 35(2): 289–308. (Scholar)
- Kant, I., 1785, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, transl. by James Ellington, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1993. [Citations to this text are given using the standard volume and page numbers from the Akademie Edition.] (Scholar)
- Kamm, F., 2007, Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm, New York: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Kamm, F., 2000, “The Doctrine of Triple Effect and Why a Rational Agent Need Not Intend the Means to His End,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 74: 21–39. (Scholar)
- Kelly, T., 2003, “Epistemic Rationality as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3): 612–640. (Scholar)
- Kenny, A.J., 1966, “Practical Inference,” Analysis, 26(3): 65–75. (Scholar)
- Kiesewetter, B., 2015, “Instrumental Normativity: In Defense of the Transmission Principle,” Ethics, 125(4): 921–946. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, The Normativity of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Contrary-to-Duty Scenarios, Deontic Dilemmas, and Transmision Principles,” Ethics, 129: 98–115. (Scholar)
- Kolnai, A., 1962, “Deliberation is of Ends,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 62: 195–218. (Scholar)
- Kolodny, N., 2005, “Why be Rational?,” Mind, 114(455): 509–563. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007a, “State or Process Requirements?,” Mind, 116(462): 371–385. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007b, “How does Coherence Matter?,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 107(1–Part 3): 229–263. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008a, “The Myth of Practical Consistency,” European Journal of Philosophy, 16(3): 366–402. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008b, “Why be Disposed to Be Coherent?” Ethics, 188(3): 437–463. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Instrumental Reasons,” in D. Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Korsgaard, C., 1986, “Skepticism about Practical Reason,” Journal of Philosophy, 83(1): 5–25. (Scholar)
- –––, 1997, “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason,” in G. Cullity and B. Gaut (eds.), Ethics and Practical Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 215–254. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Lavin, D., 2004, “Practical Reason and the Possibility of Error,” Ethics, 114(3): 424–57. (Scholar)
- Lee, W., 2018, “Willing the End Means Willing the Means: An Overlooked Reading of Kant,” Ergo, 5(16): 419–444. (Scholar)
- –––, 2021, “The Independence of (In)coherence,” Synthese 199: 6563–6584. (Scholar)
- –––, 2022, “The Real Myth of Coherence,” Erkenntnis 87: 1211–1230. (Scholar)
- Liberman, A. and M. Schroeder, 2016, “Commitment: Worth the Weight,” in E. Lord and B. Maguire (eds.), Weighing Reasons, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Lord, E., 2011, “Violating Requirements, Exiting from Requirements, and the Scope of Rationality,” Philosophical Quarterly, 61(243): 392–399. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014a, “The Coherent and the Rational,” Analytic Philosophy, 55(2): 151–175. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014b, “The Real Symmetry Problem(s) for Wide-Scope Accounts of Rationality,” Philosophical Studies, 170(3): 443–464. (Scholar)
- –––, 2017, “What You’re Rationally
Required to Do and What you Ought to Do (Are The Same Thing!),”
Mind, 126(504): 1109–1154. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “The Explanatory Problem for Cognitivism about Practical Reason,” in C. McHugh, J. Way, and D. Whiting (eds.), Normativity: Practical and Epistemic, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, The Importance of Being Rational, Oxford, Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Millgram, E., 1995, “Was Hume a Humean?,” Hume Studies, 21(1): 75–94. (Scholar)
- –––, 2001, “Practical Reasoning: The Current State of Play,” in E. Millgram (ed.) Varieties of Practical Reasoning, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 1–26. (Scholar)
- Morton, J., 2011, “Towards an Ecological Theory of the Norms
of Practical Deliberation,” European Journal of
Philosophy, 19(4): 561–584. (Scholar)
- Nozick, R., 1993, The Nature of Rationality, Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- Nuñez, C., 2020, “Requirements of Intention in Light of Belief,” Philosophical Studies, 177(9): 2471–2492. (Scholar)
- Parfit, D., 2006, “Normativity,” in Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Volume 1), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 325–380. (Scholar)
- Price, A., 2008a, Contextuality in Practical Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2008b, “Against Requirements of Rationality,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108: 157–76. (Scholar)
- Quinn,W., 1992, “Rationality and the Human Good,” Social Philosophy and Policy, 9(2): 81–95. Reprinted in W. Quinn, 1993, Morality and Action, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Railton, P., 1997, “On the Hypothetical and Non-Hypothetical in Reasoning about Belief and Action,” in G. Cullity and B. Gaut (eds.), Ethics and Practical Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 52–79. (Scholar)
- Raz, J., 2003, “Numbers, With and Without Contractualism,” Ratio, 16(4): 346–367. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005a, “Instrumental Rationality: A Reprise,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, Symposium 1: 1–19. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005b, “The Myth of Instrumental Rationality,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 1(1): 1–28. (Scholar)
- Reisner, A., 2009, “Unifying the Requirements of Rationality,” Philosophical Explorations 12(3): 243–260. (Scholar)
- Richardson, H., 1994, Practical Reasoning about Final Ends, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Scholar)
- Rippon, S., 2011, “In Defense of the Wide-Scope Instrumental
Principle,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy,
5(2): 1–21. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014, “Were Kant’s Hypothetical
Imperatives Wide-Scope Oughts?” Australasian Journal of
Philosophy, 92(4): 783–788. (Scholar)
- Ross, J., 2009, “How to be a Cognitivist about Practical Reason,” in Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.) Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 4, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 243–282. (Scholar)
- Scanlon, T., 2007, “Structural Irrationality,” in G. Brennan, G. Robert, J. Frank, and S. Michael (eds.), Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of Philip Pettit, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Schroeder, M., 2004, “The Scope of Instrumental Reason,” Philosophical Perspectives, 18: 337–364. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005a, “Instrumental Mythology,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, Symposium 1: 1–12. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005b, “The Hypothetical Imperative?,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 83(3): 357–372. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, Slaves of the Passions, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2009, “Means-end Coherence, Stringency, and Subjective Reasons,” Philosophical Studies, 143(2): 223–248. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014a, “Hypothetical Imperatives,
Scope, and Jurisdiction” in Explaining the Reasons We Share:
Explanation and Expression in Ethics (Volume 1), Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 216–226. (Scholar)
- –––, 2014b, “Scope for Rational
Autonomy” in Explaining the Reasons We Share: Explanation
and Expression in Ethics (Volume 1), Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 227–239. (Scholar)
- Schwartz, J., 2008, “Do Hypothetical Imperatives Require
Categorical Imperatives?,” European Journal of
Philosophy, 18: 84–107. (Scholar)
- Schwitzgebel, E., 2010, “Introspection,” in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition), [Introspection/" target="other">Schwitzgebel 2010 available online]. (Scholar)
- Searle, J., 2001, Rationality in Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Scholar)
- Setiya, K., 2004, “Hume on Practical Reason,” Philosophical Perspectives, 18: 365–389. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Is Efficiency a Vice?,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 42(4): 333–339. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “Cognitivism about Instrumental Reason,” Ethics, 117(4): 649–673. (Scholar)
- Shafer-Landau, R., 2006, “Ethics as Philosophy,” in T. Horgan and M. Timmons (eds.), Metaethics after Moore, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 209–232. (Scholar)
- Shaver, R., 2006, “Korsgaard on Hypothetical Imperatives,” Philosophical Studies, 129: 335–347. (Scholar)
- Shpall, S., 2013, “Wide and Narrow Scope,” Philosophical Studies, 163: 717–736. (Scholar)
- Smith, M., 2004, “Instrumental Desires, Instrumental Rationality,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 78(1): 93–109. (Scholar)
- Sobel, D., 2005, “Instrumental Rationality—Not Dead Yet,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, Symposium 1: 1–12. (Scholar)
- Southwood, N., 2008, “Vindicating the Normativity of Rationality,” Ethics, 119(1): 9–30. (Scholar)
- Tenenbaum, S., 2021, Rational Powers in Action: Instrumental Rationality and Extended Agency, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Titelbaum, M., 2015, “How to Derive a Narrow-scope Requirement from Wide-scope Requirements,” Philosophical Studies, 172(2): 535–542. (Scholar)
- Thompson, M., 2008, Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Valaris, M., 2014, “Instrumental Rationality,” European Journal of Philosophy, 22(3): 443–462. (Scholar)
- Velleman, J.D., 1989, Practical Reflection, Princeton:
Princeton University Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, “What Good is a Will?,” in A. Leist and H. Baumann (eds.), Action in Context, Berlin: de Gruyter, pp. 193–215. (Scholar)
- Vogler, C., 2002, Reasonably Vicious, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Scholar)
- Wallace, R. J., 2005, “Comment on Raz,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, Symposium 1: 1–4. (Scholar)
- –––, 2006, “Normativity, Commitment, and
Instrumental Reason,” reprinted with a postscript in
Normativity and the Will: Selected Essays on Moral Psychology and
Practical Reason, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- Way, J., 2010, “Defending the Wide-scope Approach to
Instrumental Reason,” Philosophical Studies, 147(2):
213–233. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “The Symmetry of Rational Requirements,” Philosophical Studies, 155(2): 227–239. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012a, “Explaining the Instrumental Principle,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(3): 487–506. (Scholar)
- –––, 2012b, “Instrumental
Rationality,” Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
doi: 10.4324/9780415249126-l148-1. (Scholar)
- –––, 2013, “Intentions, Akrasia, and Mere Permissibility,” Organon F, 20(4): 588–611. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Reasons and Rationality,” in D. Star (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)
- Wedgwood, R., 2003, “Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly,” in S. Stroud and C. Tappolet (eds.) Weakness of Will and Practical Irrationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 201–229. (Scholar)
- –––, 2005, “Railton on Normativity,” Philosophical Studies, 126(3): 463–479. (Scholar)
- –––, 2007, The Nature of Normativity, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Scholar)
- –––, 2011, “Instrumental Rationality,” Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 6: 280–309. (Scholar)
- White, S., 2017, “Transmission Failures,” Ethics, 127(3): 719–732. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “Intention and Prediction in Means-Ends Reasoning,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 55(3): 251–266. (Scholar)
- Worsnip, A., 2015, “Narrow-Scoping for Wide-Scopers” Synthese, 192(8): 2617–2646. (Scholar)
- –––, 2018, “What is (in)coherence?” Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 13: 184–206. (Scholar)
- –––, 2021, Fitting Things Together: Coherence and the Demands of Structural Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Scholar)